|
Human Cloning and Human Dignity:
An Ethical Inquiry
The President's Council on
Bioethics
Washington, D.C., July 2002
|
Letter of Transmittal
The President's Council on Bioethics
1801 Pennsylvania Avenue, N.W., Suite 600
Washington, D.C. 20006
July 10, 2002
The President
The White House
Washington, D.C.
Dear Mr. President:
I am pleased to present to you the first report of the President's
Council on Bioethics, Human Cloning and Human Dignity: An Ethical
Inquiry. The product of six months of discussion, research,
reflection, and deliberation, we hope that it will prove a worthy
contribution to public understanding of this momentous question.
Man's biotechnological powers are expanding in scope, at what
seems an accelerating pace. Many of these powers are double-edged,
offering help for human suffering, yet threatening harm to human
dignity. Human cloning, we are confident, is but a foretaste
the herald of many dazzling genetic and reproductive technologies
that will raise profound moral questions well into the future. It
is crucial that we try to understand its full human significance.
We have tried to conduct our inquiry into human cloning unblinkered,
with our eyes open not only to the benefits of the new biotechnologies
but also to their challenges moral, social, and political.
We have not suppressed differences but sought rather to illuminate
them, that all might better appreciate what is at stake. We have
eschewed a thin utilitarian calculus of costs and benefits, or a
narrow analysis based only on individual "rights." Rather,
we have tried to ground our reflections on the broader plane of
human procreation and human healing, with their deeper meanings.
Seen in this way, we find that the power to clone human beings is
not just another in a series of powerful tools for overcoming unwanted
infertility or treating disease. Rather, cloning represents a turning
point in human history the crossing of an important line separating
sexual from asexual procreation and the first step toward genetic
control over the next generation. It thus carries with it a number
of troubling consequences for children, family, and society.
Although the Council is not unanimous, either in some of its ethical
conclusions or its policy recommendations, we are unanimous in submitting
the entire report as a fair and accurate reflection both of our
views and of the state of the question. To summarize our findings
briefly:
First. The Council holds unanimously that cloning-to-produce-children
is unethical, ought not to be attempted, and should be indefinitely
banned by federal law, regardless of who performs the act or whether
federal funds are involved.
Second. On the related question of the ethics of cloning-for-biomedical
research, the Council is of several minds and is divided in its
policy preferences:
- Seven Members (a minority), eager to see the research proceed,
recommend permitting cloning-for-biomedical-research to go forward,
but only under strict federal regulation.
- Ten Members (a majority), convinced that no human cloning should
be permitted at least for the time being, recommend instituting,
by law, a four-year ban on cloning-for-biomedical-research, applicable
to all researchers regardless of whether federal funds are involved.
Third. The same ten-Member majority recommends a federal
review of current and projected practices of human embryo research,
pre-implantation genetic diagnosis, genetic modification of human
embryos and gametes, and related matters, with a view to recommending
and shaping ethically sound policies for the entire field. A thorough
federal review, during the moratorium, could help to clarify the
issues and foster a public consensus about how to proceed, not just
on cloning-for-biomedical-research but on all the related reproductive
and genetic technologies. We think this Council is well situated
to initiate such a review, and we have already begun it. But we
also stand ready to assist any other body that may be established
to take up this large and complex subject.
The extensive reasoning underlying these recommendations is given
at length in the report and is well summarized in the Executive
Summary, and so I shall not rehearse it here.
On behalf of my Council colleagues, and our fine staff, allow
me to thank you, Mr. President, for the opportunity you have given
us to serve the nation on this weighty subject.
Sincerely,
/s/
Leon R. Kass, M.D.
Chairman
Members of the President's Council on Bioethics
Leon R. Kass, M.D., Ph.D., Chairman
Addie Clark Harding Professor, The College and the Committee on Social
Thought,
University of Chicago.
Hertog Fellow, American Enterprise Institute.
Elizabeth H. Blackburn, Ph.D.,
D.Sc.
Professor, Department of Biochemistry and Biophysics,
University of California-San Francisco.
Stephen L. Carter, J.D.
William Nelson Cromwell Professor of Law,
Yale Law School.
Rebecca S. Dresser, J.D., M.S.
Daniel Noyes Kirby Professor of Law, Washington University School
of Law.
Professor of Ethics in Medicine, Washington University School of Medicine.
Daniel W. Foster, M.D.
Donald W. Seldin Distinguished Chair in Internal Medicine,
Chairman of the Department of Internal Medicine,
University of Texas Southwestern Medical School.
Francis Fukuyama, Ph.D.
Bernard Schwartz Professor of International Political Economy,
Dean of the Faculty, Paul H. Nitze School of Advanced International
Studies,
Johns Hopkins University.
Michael S. Gazzaniga, Ph.D.
David T. McLaughlin Distinguished Professor in Cognitive Neuroscience,
Dean of the Faculty, and Director of the Center for Cognitive Neuroscience,
Dartmouth College.
Robert P. George, D.Phil., J.D.
McCormick Professor of Jurisprudence,
Director of the James Madison Program in American Ideals and Institutions,
Princeton University.
Mary Ann Glendon, J.D., M.Comp.L.
Learned Hand Professor of Law,
Harvard University.
Alfonso Gómez-Lobo, Ph.D.
Ryan Family Professor of Metaphysics and Moral Philosophy,
Georgetown University.
William B. Hurlbut, M.D.
Consulting Professor in Human Biology,
Stanford University.
Charles Krauthammer, M.D.
Syndicated Columnist.
William F. May, Ph.D.
Cary M. Maguire Professor of Ethics Emeritus,
Southern Methodist University.
Paul McHugh, M.D.
Henry Phipps Professor of Psychiatry and Director of the Department
of Psychiatry
and Behavioral Sciences, Johns Hopkins University School of Medicine.
Psychiatrist-in-chief, Johns Hopkins Hospital.
Gilbert C. Meilaender, Ph.D.
Richard & Phyllis Duesenberg Professor of Christian Ethics,
Valparaiso University.
Janet D. Rowley, M.D., D.Sc.
Blum-Riese Distinguished Service Professor of Medicine,
Molecular Genetics and Cell Biology, and Human Genetics,
Pritzker School of Medicine,
University of Chicago.
Michael J. Sandel, D.Phil.
Professor of Government,
Harvard University.
James Q. Wilson, Ph.D.
James A. Collins Professor of Management and Public Policy Emeritus,
University of California-Los Angeles.
Council Staff and Consultants
Dean Clancy
Executive Director
Michelle R. Bell
Receptionist/Staff Assistant
Eric Cohen
Senior Research Consultant
Judith Crawford
Administrative Director
Diane M. Gianelli
Director of Communications
Emily Jones
Executive Assistant
Joshua Kleinfeld
Research Analyst
Yuval Levin
Senior Research Analyst
Richard Roblin, Ph.D.
Scientific Director
Audrea R. Vann
Staff Assistant
Rachel Flick Wildavsky
Director, Education Project
Adam Wolfson
Consultant
Lee L. Zwanziger, Ph.D.
Director of Research
Preface
Human Cloning and Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry is
the first publication of the President's Council on Bioethics, which
was created by President George W. Bush on November 28, 2001, by
means of Executive Order 13237.
The Council's purpose is to advise the President on bioethical
issues related to advances in biomedical science and technology.
In connection with its advisory role, the mission of the Council
includes the following functions:
- To undertake fundamental inquiry into the human and moral significance
of developments in biomedical and behavioral science and technology.
- To explore specific ethical and policy questions related to
these developments.
- To provide a forum for a national discussion of bioethical issues.
- To facilitate a greater understanding of bioethical issues.
- To explore possibilities for useful international collaboration
on bioethical issues.
President Bush left the Council free to establish its own priorities
among the many issues encompassed within its charter, based on the
urgency and gravity of those issues and the public need for practical
guidance about them.
The Council had little difficulty in choosing its first topic of
inquiry. The ethics of human cloning has been the subject of intense
discussion in the United States and throughout the world for more
than five years, and it remains the subject of heated debate in
Congress. On the surface, discussion has focused on the safety of
cloning techniques, the hoped-for medical benefits of cloning research,
and the morality of experimenting on human embryos. But driving
the conversations are deeper concerns about where biotechnology
may be taking us and what it might mean for human freedom, equality,
and dignity.
Human cloning, were it to succeed, would enable parents for the
first time to determine the entire genetic makeup of their children.
Bypassing sexual reproduction, it would move procreation increasingly
under artful human control and in the direction of manufacture.
Seen as a forerunner of possible future genetic engineering, it
raises for many people concerns also about eugenics, the project
to "improve" the human race. A world that practiced human cloning,
we sense, could be a very different world, perhaps radically different,
from the one we know. It is crucial that we try to understand, before
it happens, whether, how, and why this may be so.
Investigating human cloning also provides the Council an important
opportunity to illustrate how bioethics can and should deal with
those technological innovations that touch deeply our humanity.
Here, as elsewhere, the most profound issues go beyond the commonplace
and utilitarian concerns of feasibility, safety, and efficacy. In
addition, on the policy side, cloning offers us a test case for
considering whether public control of biotechnology is possible
and desirable, and if so, by what means and at what cost.
The Council commenced deliberations on the topic of human cloning
at its first meeting in January 2002, and continued the discussion
at its February, April, and June meetings, all held in Washington,
D.C. We heard presentations on the recent cloning report of the
National Academy of Sciences; on human stem cell research, embryonic
and adult; on the ethics of embryo research; and on international
systems of regulation of embryo research and assisted reproductive
technologies. We received a great deal of public comment, oral and
written. All told, we held twelve ninety-minute conversations on
the subject.
Recognizing "the complex and often competing moral positions" on
biomedical issues, President Bush specified in creating the Council
that it need not be constrained by "an overriding concern to find
consensus." In this report we have chosen not to be so constrained.
We have not suppressed disagreements in search of a single, watered-down
position. Instead, we have presented clear arguments for the relevant
moral and policy positions on multiple sides of these difficult
questions, representing each as fairly and fully as we can. As a
result, the reader will notice that, on some of the matters discussed
in the report, Members of the Council are not all of one mind. Members
are united, though, in endorsing the worthiness of the approach
taken and the importance of the separate arguments made. Accordingly,
the Council is unanimous in owning the entire report and in recommending
all its discussions and arguments for serious consideration.
Readers interested in delving further into this subject may wish
to consult the Bibliography, which includes all of the documents
referred to within the report, as well as the verbatim transcripts
of our meetings, which are posted at our website (www.bioethics.gov).
It was in his remarks to the nation on federal funding of embryonic
stem cell research, on August 9, 2001, that President Bush first
declared his intention to create this Council. At the end of that
speech, the President said:
I will also name a President's council to monitor stem
cell research, to recommend appropriate guidelines and regulations,
and to consider all of the medical and ethical ramifications of
biomedical innovation. . . . This council will keep us apprised
of new developments and give our nation a forum to continue to discuss
and evaluate these important issues. As we go forward, I hope we
will always be guided by both intellect and heart, by both our capabilities
and our conscience.
It has been our goal in these pages and shall remain our
goal in the future to live up to the President's high hopes
and noble aspirations.
LEON R. KASS, M.D.
Chairman
Executive Summary
For the past five years, the prospect of human cloning has been
the subject of considerable public attention and sharp moral debate,
both in the United States and around the world. Since the announcement
in February 1997 of the first successful cloning of a mammal (Dolly
the sheep), several other species of mammals have been cloned. Although
a cloned human child has yet to be born, and although the animal
experiments have had low rates of success, the production of functioning
mammalian cloned offspring suggests that the eventual cloning of
humans must be considered a serious possibility.
In November 2001, American researchers claimed to have produced
the first cloned human embryos, though they reportedly reached only
a six-cell stage before they stopped dividing and died. In addition,
several fertility specialists, both here and abroad, have announced
their intention to clone human beings. The United States Congress
has twice taken up the matter, in 1998 and again in 2001-2002, with
the House of Representatives in July 2001 passing a strict ban on
all human cloning, including the production of cloned human embryos.
As of this writing, several cloning-related bills are under consideration
in the Senate. Many other nations have banned human cloning, and
the United Nations is considering an international convention on
the subject. Finally, two major national reports have been issued
on human reproductive cloning, one by the National Bioethics Advisory
Commission (NBAC) in 1997, the other by the National Academy of
Sciences (NAS) in January 2002. Both the NBAC and the NAS reports
called for further consideration of the ethical and social questions
raised by cloning.
The debate over human cloning became further complicated in 1998
when researchers were able, for the first time, to isolate human
embryonic stem cells. Many scientists believe that these versatile
cells, capable of becoming any type of cell in the body, hold great
promise for understanding and treating many chronic diseases and
conditions. Some scientists also believe that stem cells derived
from cloned human embryos, produced explicitly for such research,
might prove uniquely useful for studying many genetic diseases and
devising novel therapies. Public reaction to the prospect of cloning-for-biomedical-research
has been mixed: some Americans support it for its medical promise;
others oppose it because it requires the exploitation and destruction
of nascent human life, which would be created solely for research
purposes.
Human Cloning: What Is at Stake?
The intense attention given to human cloning in both its potential
uses, for reproduction as well as for research, strongly suggests
that people do not regard it as just another new technology. Instead,
we see it as something quite different, something that touches fundamental
aspects of our humanity. The notion of cloning raises issues about
identity and individuality, the meaning of having children, the
difference between procreation and manufacture, and the relationship
between the generations. It also raises new questions about the
manipulation of some human beings for the benefit of others, the
freedom and value of biomedical inquiry, our obligation to heal
the sick (and its limits), and the respect and protection owed to
nascent human life.
Finally, the legislative debates over human cloning raise large
questions about the relationship between science and society, especially
about whether society can or should exercise ethical and prudential
control over biomedical technology and the conduct of biomedical
research. Rarely has such a seemingly small innovation raised such
big questions.
The Inquiry: Our Point of Departure
As Members of the President's Council on Bioethics, we have taken
up the larger ethical and social inquiry called for in the NBAC
and NAS reports, with the aim of advancing public understanding
and informing public policy on the matter. We have attempted to
consider human cloning (both for producing children and for biomedical
research) within its larger human, technological, and ethical contexts,
rather than to view it as an isolated technical development. We
focus first on the broad human goods that it may serve as well as
threaten, rather than on the immediate impact of the technique itself.
By our broad approach, our starting on the plane of human goods,
and our open spirit of inquiry, we hope to contribute to a richer
and deeper understanding of what human cloning means, how we should
think about it, and what we should do about it.
On some matters discussed in this report, Members of the Council
are not of one mind. Rather than bury these differences in search
of a spurious consensus, we have sought to present all views fully
and fairly, while recording our agreements as well as our genuine
diversity of perspectives, including our differences on the final
recommendations to be made. By this means, we hope to help policymakers
and the general public appreciate more thoroughly the difficulty
of the issues and the competing goods that are at stake.
Fair and Accurate Terminology
There is today much confusion about the terms used to discuss human
cloning, regarding both the activity involved and the entities that
result. The Council stresses the importance of striving not only
for accuracy but also for fairness, especially because the choice
of terms can decisively affect the way questions are posed, and
hence how answers are given. We have sought terminology that most
accurately conveys the descriptive reality of the matter, in order
that the moral arguments can then proceed on the merits. We have
resisted the temptation to solve the moral questions by artful redefinition
or by denying to some morally crucial element a name that makes
clear that there is a moral question to be faced.
On the basis of (1) a careful analysis of the act of cloning, and
its relation to the means by which it is accomplished and the purposes
it may serve, and (2) an extensive critical examination of alternative
terminologies, the Council has adopted the following definitions
for the most important terms in the matter of human cloning:
- Cloning: A form of reproduction in which offspring
result not from the chance union of egg and sperm (sexual reproduction)
but from the deliberate replication of the genetic makeup of another
single individual (asexual reproduction).
- Human cloning: The asexual production of a new human
organism that is, at all stages of development, genetically virtually
identical to a currently existing or previously existing human
being. It would be accomplished by introducing the nuclear material
of a human somatic cell (donor) into an oocyte (egg) whose own
nucleus has been removed or inactivated, yielding a product that
has a human genetic constitution virtually identical to the donor
of the somatic cell. (This procedure is known as "somatic cell
nuclear transfer," or SCNT). We have declined to use the terms
"reproductive cloning" and "therapeutic cloning." We have chosen
instead to use the following designations:
- Cloning-to-produce-children: Production of a cloned
human embryo, formed for the (proximate) purpose of initiating
a pregnancy, with the (ultimate) goal of producing a child who
will be genetically virtually identical to a currently existing
or previously existing individual.
- Cloning-for-biomedical-research: Production of a cloned
human embryo, formed for the (proximate) purpose of using it in
research or for extracting its stem cells, with the (ultimate)
goals of gaining scientific knowledge of normal and abnormal development
and of developing cures for human diseases.
- Cloned human embryo: (a) A human embryo resulting from
the nuclear transfer process (as contrasted with a human embryo
arising from the union of egg and sperm). (b) The immediate (and
developing) product of the initial act of cloning, accomplished
by successful SCNT, whether used subsequently in attempts to produce
children or in biomedical research.
Scientific Background
Cloning research and stem cell research are being actively investigated
and the state of the science is changing rapidly; significant new
developments could change some of the interpretations in our report.
At present, however, a few general points may be highlighted.
- The technique of cloning. The following steps have
been used to produce live offspring in the mammalian species that
have been successfully cloned. Obtain an egg cell from a female
of a mammalian species. Remove its nuclear DNA, to produce an
enucleated egg. Insert the nucleus of a donor adult cell into
the enucleated egg, to produce a reconstructed egg. Activate the
reconstructed egg with chemicals or electric current, to stimulate
it to commence cell division. Sustain development of the cloned
embryo to a suitable stage in vitro, and then transfer it to the
uterus of a female host that has been suitably prepared to receive
it. Bring to live birth a cloned animal that is genetically virtually
identical (except for the mitochondrial DNA) to the animal that
donated the adult cell nucleus.
- Animal cloning: low success rates, high morbidity.
At least seven species of mammals (none of them primates) have
been successfully cloned to produce live births. Yet the production
of live cloned offspring is rare and the failure rate is high:
more than 90 percent of attempts to initiate a clonal pregnancy
do not result in successful live birth. Moreover, the live-born
cloned animals suffer high rates of deformity and disability,
both at birth and later on. Some biologists attribute these failures
to errors or incompleteness of epigenetic reprogramming of the
somatic cell nucleus.
- Attempts at human cloning. At this writing, it is uncertain
whether anyone has attempted cloning-to-produce-children (although
at least one physician is now claiming to have initiated several
active clonal pregnancies, and others are reportedly working on
it). We do not know whether a transferred cloned human embryo
can progress all the way to live birth.
- Stem cell research. Human embryonic stem cells have
been isolated from embryos (produced by IVF) at the blastocyst
stage or from the germinal tissue of fetuses. Human adult stem
(or multipotent) cells have been isolated from a variety of tissues.
Such cell populations can be differentiated in vitro into a number
of different cell types, and are currently being studied intensely
for their possible uses in regenerative medicine. Most scientists
working in the field believe that stem cells (both embryonic and
adult) hold great promise as routes toward cures and treatments
for many human diseases and disabilities. All stem cell research
is at a very early stage, and it is too soon to tell which approaches
will prove most useful, and for which diseases.
- The transplant rejection problem. To be effective as
long-term treatments, cell transplantation therapies will have
to overcome the immune rejection problem. Cells and tissues derived
from adult stem cells and returned to the patient from whom they
were taken would not be subject (at least in principle) to immune
rejection.
- Stem cells from cloned embryos. Human embryonic stem
cell preparations could potentially be produced by using somatic
cell nuclear transfer to produce a cloned human embryo, and then
taking it apart at the blastocyst stage and isolating stem cells.
These stem cells would be genetically virtually identical to cells
from the nucleus donor, and thus could potentially be of great
value in biomedical research. Very little work of this sort has
been done to date in animals, and there are as yet no published
reports of cloned human embryos grown to the blastocyst stage.
Although the promise of such research is at this time unknown,
most researchers believe it will yield very useful and important
knowledge, pointing toward new therapies and offering one of several
possible routes to circumvent the immune rejection problem. Although
some experimental results in animals are indeed encouraging, they
also demonstrate some tendency even of cloned stem cells to stimulate
an immune response.
- The fate of embryos used in research. All extractions
of stem cells from human embryos, cloned or not, involve the destruction
of these embryos.
The Ethics of Cloning-to-Produce-Children
Two separate national-level reports on human cloning (NBAC, 1997;
NAS, 2002) concluded that attempts to clone a human being would
be unethical at this time due to safety concerns and the likelihood
of harm to those involved. The Council concurs in this conclusion.
But we have extended the work of these distinguished bodies by undertaking
a broad ethical examination of the merits of, and difficulties with,
cloning-to-produce-children.
Cloning-to-produce-children might serve several purposes. It might
allow infertile couples or others to have genetically-related children;
permit couples at risk of conceiving a child with a genetic disease
to avoid having an afflicted child; allow the bearing of a child
who could become an ideal transplant donor for a particular patient
in need; enable a parent to keep a living connection with a dead
or dying child or spouse; or enable individuals or society to try
to "replicate" individuals of great talent or beauty. These purposes
have been defended by appeals to the goods of freedom, existence
(as opposed to nonexistence), and well-being all vitally important
ideals.
A major weakness in these arguments supporting cloning-to-produce-children
is that they overemphasize the freedom, desires, and control of
parents, and pay insufficient attention to the well-being of the
cloned child-to-be. The Council holds that, once the child-to-be
is carefully considered, these arguments are not sufficient to overcome
the powerful case against engaging in cloning-to-produce-children.
First, cloning-to-produce-children would violate the principles
of the ethics of human research. Given the high rates of morbidity
and mortality in the cloning of other mammals, we believe that cloning-to-produce-children
would be extremely unsafe, and that attempts to produce a cloned
child would be highly unethical. Indeed, our moral analysis of this
matter leads us to conclude that this is not, as is sometimes implied,
a merely temporary objection, easily removed by the improvement
of technique. We offer reasons for believing that the safety risks
might be enduring, and offer arguments in support of a strong conclusion:
that conducting experiments in an effort to make cloning-to-produce-children
less dangerous would itself be an unacceptable violation of the
norms of research ethics. There seems to be no ethical way to try
to discover whether cloning-to-produce-children can become safe,
now or in the future.
If carefully considered, the concerns about safety also begin to
reveal the ethical principles that should guide a broader assessment
of cloning-to-produce-children: the principles of freedom, equality,
and human dignity. To appreciate the broader human significance
of cloning-to-produce-children, one needs first to reflect on the
meaning of having children; the meaning of asexual, as opposed to
sexual, reproduction; the importance of origins and genetic endowment
for identity and sense of self; the meaning of exercising greater
human control over the processes and "products" of human reproduction;
and the difference between begetting and making. Reflecting on these
topics, the Council has identified five categories of concern regarding
cloning-to-produce-children. (Different Council Members give varying
moral weight to these different concerns.)
- Problems of identity and individuality. Cloned children
may experience serious problems of identity both because each
will be genetically virtually identical to a human being who has
already lived and because the expectations for their lives may
be shadowed by constant comparisons to the life of the "original."
- Concerns regarding manufacture. Cloned children would
be the first human beings whose entire genetic makeup is selected
in advance. They might come to be considered more like products
of a designed manufacturing process than "gifts" whom their parents
are prepared to accept as they are. Such an attitude toward children
could also contribute to increased commercialization and industrialization
of human procreation.
- The prospect of a new eugenics. Cloning, if successful,
might serve the ends of privately pursued eugenic enhancement,
either by avoiding the genetic defects that may arise when human
reproduction is left to chance, or by preserving and perpetuating
outstanding genetic traits, including the possibility, someday
in the future, of using cloning to perpetuate genetically engineered
enhancements.
- Troubled family relations. By confounding and transgressing
the natural boundaries between generations, cloning could strain
the social ties between them. Fathers could become "twin brothers"
to their "sons"; mothers could give birth to their genetic twins;
and grandparents would also be the "genetic parents" of their
grandchildren. Genetic relation to only one parent might produce
special difficulties for family life.
- Effects on society. Cloning-to-produce-children would
affect not only the direct participants but also the entire society
that allows or supports this activity. Even if practiced on a
small scale, it could affect the way society looks at children
and set a precedent for future nontherapeutic interventions into
the human genetic endowment or novel forms of control by one generation
over the next. In the absence of wisdom regarding these matters,
prudence dictates caution and restraint.
Conclusion: For some or all of these reasons, the Council is in
full agreement that cloning-to-produce-children is not only unsafe
but also morally unacceptable, and ought not to be attempted.
The Ethics of Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research
Ethical assessment of cloning-for-biomedical-research is far more
vexing. On the one hand, such research could lead to important knowledge
about human embryological development and gene action, both normal
and abnormal, ultimately resulting in treatments and cures for many
dreaded illnesses and disabilities. On the other hand, the research
is morally controversial because it involves the deliberate production,
use, and ultimate destruction of cloned human embryos, and because
the cloned embryos produced for research are no different from those
that could be implanted in attempts to produce cloned children.
The difficulty is compounded by what are, for now, unanswerable
questions as to whether the research will in fact yield the benefits
hoped for, and whether other promising and morally nonproblematic
approaches might yield comparable benefits. The Council, reflecting
the differences of opinion in American society, is divided regarding
the ethics of research involving (cloned) embryos. Yet we agree
that all parties to the debate have concerns vital to defend, vital
not only to themselves but to all of us. No human being and no society
can afford to be callous to the needs of suffering humanity, or
cavalier about the treatment of nascent human life, or indifferent
to the social effects of adopting one course of action rather than
another.
To make clear to all what is at stake in the decision, Council
Members have presented, as strongly as possible, the competing ethical
cases for and against cloning-for-biomedical-research in the form
of first-person attempts at moral suasion. Each case has tried to
address what is owed to suffering humanity, to the human embryo,
and to the broader society. Within each case, supporters of the
position in question speak only for themselves, and not for the
Council as a whole.
A. The Moral Case for Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research
The moral case for cloning-for-biomedical-research rests on our
obligation to try to relieve human suffering, an obligation that
falls most powerfully on medical practitioners and biomedical researchers.
We who support cloning-for-biomedical-research all agree that it
may offer uniquely useful ways of investigating and possibly treating
many chronic debilitating diseases and disabilities, providing aid
and relief to millions. We also believe that the moral objections
to this research are outweighed by the great good that may come
from it. Up to this point, we who support this research all agree.
But we differ among ourselves regarding the weight of the moral
objections, owing to differences about the moral status of the cloned
embryo. These differences of opinion are sufficient to warrant distinguishing
two different moral positions within the moral case for cloning-for-biomedical-research:
Position Number One. Most Council Members who favor cloning-for-biomedical-research
do so with serious moral concerns. Speaking only for ourselves,
we acknowledge the following difficulties, but think that they can
be addressed by setting proper boundaries.
- Intermediate moral status. While we take seriously
concerns about the treatment of nascent human life, we believe
there are sound moral reasons for not regarding the embryo in
its earliest stages as the moral equivalent of a human person.
We believe the embryo has a developing and intermediate moral
worth that commands our special respect, but that it is morally
permissible to use early-stage cloned human embryos in important
research under strict regulation.
- Deliberate creation for use. We believe that concerns
over the problem of deliberate creation of cloned embryos for
use in research have merit, but when properly understood should
not preclude cloning-for-biomedical-research. These embryos would
not be "created for destruction," but for use in the service of
life and medicine. They would be destroyed in the service of a
great good, and this should not be obscured.
- Going too far. We acknowledge the concern that some
researchers might seek to develop cloned embryos beyond the blastocyst
stage, and for those of us who believe that the cloned embryo
has a developing and intermediate moral status, this is a very
real worry. We approve, therefore, only of research on cloned
embryos that is strictly limited to the first fourteen days of
development a point near when the primitive streak is formed
and before organ differentiation occurs.
- Other moral hazards. We believe that concerns about
the exploitation of women and about the risk that cloning-for-biomedical-research
could lead to cloning-to-produce-children can be adequately addressed
by appropriate rules and regulations. These concerns need not
frighten us into abandoning an important avenue of research.
Position Number Two. A few Council Members who favor cloning-for-biomedical-research
do not share all the ethical qualms expressed above. Speaking only
for ourselves, we hold that this research, at least for the purposes
presently contemplated, presents no special moral problems, and
therefore should be endorsed with enthusiasm as a potential new
means of gaining knowledge to serve humankind. Because we accord
no special moral status to the early-stage cloned embryo and believe
it should be treated essentially like all other human cells, we
believe that the moral issues involved in this research are no different
from those that accompany any biomedical research. What is required
is the usual commitment to high standards for the quality of research,
scientific integrity, and the need to obtain informed consent from
donors of the eggs and somatic cells used in nuclear transfer.
B. The Moral Case against Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research
The moral case against cloning-for-biomedical-research acknowledges
the possibility though purely speculative at the moment
that medical benefits might come from this particular avenue of
experimentation. But we believe it is morally wrong to exploit and
destroy developing human life, even for good reasons, and that it
is unwise to open the door to the many undesirable consequences
that are likely to result from this research. We find it disquieting,
even somewhat ignoble, to treat what are in fact seeds of the next
generation as mere raw material for satisfying the needs of our
own. Only for very serious reasons should progress toward increased
knowledge and medical advances be slowed. But we believe that in
this case such reasons are apparent.
- Moral status of the cloned embryo. We hold that the
case for treating the early-stage embryo as simply the moral equivalent
of all other human cells (Position Number Two, above) is simply
mistaken: it denies the continuous history of human individuals
from the embryonic to fetal to infant stages of existence; it
misunderstands the meaning of potentiality; and it ignores the
hazardous moral precedent that the routinized creation, use, and
destruction of nascent human life would establish. We hold that
the case for according the human embryo "intermediate and developing
moral status" (Position Number One, above) is also unconvincing,
for reasons both biological and moral. Attempts to ground the
limited measure of respect owed to a maturing embryo in certain
of its developmental features do not succeed, and the invoking
of a "special respect" owed to nascent human life seems to have
little or no operative meaning if cloned embryos may be created
in bulk and used routinely with impunity. If from one perspective
the view that the embryo seems to amount to little may invite
a weakening of our respect, from another perspective its seeming
insignificance should awaken in us a sense of shared humanity
and a special obligation to protect it.
- The exploitation of developing human life. To engage
in cloning-for-biomedical-research requires the irreversible crossing
of a very significant moral boundary: the creation of human life
expressly and exclusively for the purpose of its use in research,
research that necessarily involves its deliberate destruction.
If we permit this research to proceed, we will effectively be
endorsing the complete transformation of nascent human life into
nothing more than a resource or a tool. Doing so would coarsen
our moral sensibilities and make us a different society: one less
humble toward that which we cannot fully understand, less willing
to extend the boundaries of human respect ever outward, and more
willing to transgress moral boundaries once it appears to be in
our own interests to do so.
- Moral harm to society. Even those who are uncertain
about the precise moral status of the human embryo have sound
ethical-prudential reasons to oppose cloning-for-biomedical-research.
Giving moral approval to such research risks significant moral
harm to our society by (1) crossing the boundary from sexual to
asexual reproduction, thus approving in principle the genetic
manipulation and control of nascent human life; (2) opening the
door to other moral hazards, such as cloning-to-produce-children
or research on later-stage human embryos and fetuses; and (3)
potentially putting the federal government in the novel and unsavory
position of mandating the destruction of nascent human life. Because
we are concerned not only with the fate of the cloned embryos
but also with where this research will lead our society, we think
prudence requires us not to engage in this research.
- What we owe the suffering. We are certainly not deaf
to the voices of suffering patients; after all, each of us already
shares or will share in the hardships of mortal life. We and our
loved ones are all patients or potential patients. But we are
not only patients, and easing suffering is not our only moral
obligation. As much as we wish to alleviate suffering now and
to leave our children a world where suffering can be more effectively
relieved, we also want to leave them a world in which we and they
want to live a world that honors moral limits, that respects
all life whether strong or weak, and that refuses to secure the
good of some human beings by sacrificing the lives of others.
Public Policy Options
The Council recognizes the challenges and risks of moving from
moral assessment to public policy. Reflections on the "social contract"
between science and society highlight both the importance of scientific
freedom and the need for boundaries. We note that other countries
often treat human cloning in the context of a broad area of biomedical
technology, at the intersection of reproductive technology, embryo
research, and genetics, while the public policy debate in the United
States has treated cloning largely on its own. We recognize the
special difficulty in formulating sound public policy in this area,
given that the two ethically distinct matters-cloning-to-produce-children
and cloning-for-biomedical-research-will be mutually affected or
implicated in any attempts to legislate about either. Nevertheless,
our ethical and policy analysis leads us to the conclusion that
some deliberate public policy at the federal level is needed in
the area of human cloning.
We reviewed the following seven possible policy options and considered
their relative strengths and weaknesses: (1) Professional self-regulation
but no federal legislative action ("self-regulation"); (2) A ban
on cloning-to-produce-children, with neither endorsement nor restriction
of cloning-for-biomedical-research ("ban plus silence"); (3) A ban
on cloning-to-produce-children, with regulation of the use of cloned
embryos for biomedical research ("ban plus regulation"); (4) Governmental
regulation, with no legislative prohibitions ("regulation of both");
(5) A ban on all human cloning, whether to produce children or for
biomedical research ("ban on both"); (6) A ban on cloning-to-produce-children,
with a moratorium or temporary ban on cloning-for-biomedical-research
("ban plus moratorium"); or (7) A moratorium or temporary ban on
all human cloning, whether to produce children or for biomedical
research ("moratorium on both").
The Council's Policy Recommendations
Having considered the benefits and drawbacks of each of these options,
and taken into account our discussions and reflections throughout
this report, the Council recommends two possible policy alternatives,
each supported by a portion of the Members.
Majority Recommendation: Ten Members of the Council recommend
a ban on cloning-to-produce-children combined with a four-year
moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research. We also call for
a federal review of current and projected practices of human embryo
research, pre-implantation genetic diagnosis, genetic modification
of human embryos and gametes, and related matters, with a view to
recommending and shaping ethically sound policies for the entire
field. Speaking only for ourselves, those of us who support
this recommendation do so for some or all of the following reasons:
- By permanently banning cloning-to-produce-children, this policy
gives force to the strong ethical verdict against cloning-to-produce-children,
unanimous in this Council (and in Congress) and widely supported
by the American people. And by enacting a four-year moratorium
on the creation of cloned embryos, it establishes an additional
safeguard not afforded by policies that would allow the production
of cloned embryos to proceed without delay.
- It calls for and provides time for further democratic deliberation
about cloning-for-biomedical research, a subject about which the
nation is divided and where there remains great uncertainty. A
national discourse on this subject has not yet taken place in
full, and a moratorium, by making it impossible for either side
to cling to the status-quo, would force both to make their full
case before the public. By banning all cloning for a time, it
allows us to seek moral consensus on whether or not we should
cross a major moral boundary (creating nascent cloned human life
solely for research) and prevents our crossing it without deliberate
decision. It would afford time for scientific evidence, now sorely
lacking, to be gathered from animal models and other avenues
of human research that might give us a better sense of whether
cloning-for-biomedical-research would work as promised, and whether
other morally nonproblematic approaches might be available. It
would promote a fuller and better-informed public debate. And
it would show respect for the deep moral concerns of the large
number of Americans who have serious ethical objections to this
research.
- Some of us hold that cloning-for-biomedical-research can never
be ethically pursued, and endorse a moratorium to enable us to
continue to make our case in a democratic way. Others of us support
the moratorium because it would provide the time and incentive
required to develop a system of national regulation that might
come into use if, at the end of the four-year period, the moratorium
were not reinstated or made permanent. Such a system could not
be developed overnight, and therefore even those who support the
research but want it regulated should see that at the very least
a pause is required. In the absence of a moratorium, few proponents
of the research would have much incentive to institute an effective
regulatory system. Moreover, the very process of proposing such
regulations would clarify the moral and prudential judgments involved
in deciding whether and how to proceed with this research.
- A moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research would enable
us to consider this activity in the larger context of research
and technology in the areas of developmental biology, embryo research,
and genetics, and to pursue a more comprehensive federal regulatory
system for setting and executing policy in the entire area.
- Finally, we believe that a moratorium, rather than a lasting
ban, signals a high regard for the value of biomedical research
and an enduring concern for patients and families whose suffering
such research may help alleviate. It would reaffirm the principle
that science can progress while upholding the community's moral
norms, and would therefore reaffirm the community's moral support
for science and biomedical technology.
The decision before us is of great importance. Creating cloned
embryos for any purpose requires crossing a major moral
boundary, with grave risks and likely harms, and once we cross it
there will be no turning back. Our society should take the time
to make a judgment that is well-informed and morally sound, respectful
of strongly held views, and representative of the priorities and
principles of the American people. We believe this ban-plus-moratorium
proposal offers the best means of achieving these goals.
This position is supported by Council Members Rebecca S. Dresser,
Francis Fukuyama, Robert P. George, Mary Ann Glendon, Alfonso Gómez-Lobo,
William B. Hurlbut, Leon R. Kass, Charles Krauthammer, Paul McHugh,
and Gilbert C. Meilaender.
Minority Recommendation: Seven Members of the Council
recommend a ban on cloning-to-produce-children, with regulation
of the use of cloned embryos for biomedical research. Speaking
only for ourselves, those of us who support this recommendation
do so for some or all of the following reasons:
- By permanently banning cloning-to-produce-children, this policy
gives force to the strong ethical verdict against cloning-to-produce-children,
unanimous in this Council (and in Congress) and widely supported
by the American people. We believe that a ban on the transfer
of cloned embryos to a woman's uterus would be a sufficient and
effective legal safeguard against the practice.
- It approves cloning-for-biomedical-research and permits
it to proceed without substantial delay. This is the most
important advantage of this proposal. The research shows great
promise, and its actual value can only be determined by allowing
it to go forward now. Regardless of how much time we allow it,
no amount of experimentation with animal models can provide the
needed understanding of human diseases. The special benefits from
working with stem cells from cloned human embryos cannot be obtained
using embryos obtained by IVF. We believe this research could
provide relief to millions of Americans, and that the government
should therefore support it, within sensible limits imposed by
regulation.
- It would establish, as a condition of proceeding, the
necessary regulatory protections to avoid abuses and misuses of
cloned embryos. These regulations might touch on the secure handling
of embryos, licensing and prior review of research projects, the
protection of egg donors, and the provision of equal access to
benefits.
- Some of us also believe that mechanisms to regulate cloning-for-biomedical-research
should be part of a larger regulatory program governing all research
involving human embryos, and that the federal government should
initiate a review of present and projected practices of human
embryo research, with the aim of establishing reasonable policies
on the matter.
Permitting cloning-for-biomedical-research now, while governing
it through a prudent and sensible regulatory regime, is the most
appropriate way to allow important research to proceed while insuring
that abuses are prevented. We believe that the legitimate concerns
about human cloning expressed throughout this report are sufficiently
addressed by this ban-plus-regulation proposal, and that the nation
should affirm and support the responsible effort to find treatments
and cures that might help many who are suffering.
This position is supported by Council Members Elizabeth H. Blackburn,
Daniel W. Foster, Michael S. Gazzaniga, William F. May, Janet D.
Rowley, Michael J. Sandel, and James Q. Wilson.
Chapter One
The Meaning of Human Cloning: An Overview
The prospect of human cloningi
burst into the public consciousness in 1997, following the announcement
of the successful cloning of Dolly the sheep. It has since captured
much attention and generated great debate, both in the United States
and around the world. Many are repelled by the idea of producing
children who would be genetically virtually identical to pre-existing
individuals, and believe such a practice unethical. But some see
in such cloning the possibility to do good for infertile couples
and the broader society. Some want to outlaw it, and many nations
have done so. Others believe the benefits outweigh the risks and
the moral concerns, or they oppose legislative interference with
science and technology in the name of freedom and progress.
Complicating the national dialogue about human cloning is the isolation
in 1998 of human embryonic stem cells, which many scientists believe
to hold great promise for understanding and treating many chronic
diseases and conditions. Some scientists also believe that stem
cells derived from cloned human embryos, produced explicitly for
such research, might prove to be uniquely useful for studying many
genetic diseases and devising novel therapies. Public reaction to
this prospect has been mixed, with some Americans supporting it
in the hope of advancing biomedical research and helping the sick
and the suffering, while others are concerned about the instrumentalization
or abuse of nascent human life and the resulting danger of moral
insensitivity and degradation.
In the United States, several attempts have been made to initiate
a comprehensive public review of the significance of human cloning
and to formulate appropriate policies. Most notably, the National
Bioethics Advisory Commission (NBAC) released a report on the subject
of cloning-to-produce-children in 1997.ii
The Commission concluded that cloning-to-produce-children was, at
least for the time being, unethical on safety grounds, and that
the deeper and more permanent moral concerns surrounding the practice
should be the subject of continuing deliberation "in order to further
our understanding of the ethical and social implications of this
technology and to enable society to produce appropriate long-term
policies regarding this technology" (p. 106).
In this report, the President's Council on Bioethics takes up this
important charge, and considers the ethical and social implications
of human cloning (both for producing children and for biomedical
research) in their full scope, with the aim of informing public
policy on the matter.
Our work toward this end is guided by a number of explicit methodological
choices about modes of approach, points of departure, and spirit
of inquiry. We locate human cloning within its larger human and
technological context, rather than consider it in isolation. We
focus first on the broad human goods that it may serve or threaten,
rather than on the immediate impact of the technique itself. And
we present the strongest arguments for the relevant moral and policy
positions, rather than frame the arguments in order to seek consensus.
By our broad approach, our starting on the plane of human goods,
and our open spirit of inquiry, we hope to contribute to a richer
and deeper understanding of what human cloning entails, how we should
think about it, and what we should do about it.
Two points of clarification before we proceed. First, all of our
considerations and arguments assume that cloning techniques, both
for producing children and for providing embryos useful in biomedical
research, could succeed in human beings as they have with other
mammals. Cloning-to-produce-children has never been successfully
carried out in humans, and cloning embryos for biomedical research
has not progressed beyond the earliest experiments. We consider
it part of our task to judge whether even attempts at human cloning
would be ethical or should be lawful. To conduct the analysis and
assessment needed for such judgment, we necessarily proceed on the
assumption, which we believe is supported by evidence from animal
experiments, that human cloning is indeed a possibility that
sooner or later, if it were allowed and attempted, human cloning
could be successfully carried out. Practically all public discussion
of the ethics of human cloning has, whether expressly or not, proceeded
on this same premise, and rightly so.
Second, on some of the matters discussed in this report, Members
of the Council are not of one mind. Given that competing goods are
at stake, and different people regard them differently, this is
not at all surprising. Rather than bury these differences in search
of a spurious consensus, we have sought to present all views fairly
and fully. Yet transcending these differences is a more fundamental
agreement about the worthiness of the approach we have adopted and
the arguments we have made. Accordingly, the Council is unanimous
in owning the entire report and in recommending, to all, the report's
discussions and arguments for serious consideration.
In the remainder of this overview, we describe the context of human
cloning and the discussions it has generated. In the course of doing
so, we identify the kinds of questions and concerns that would permit
a full assessment of the meaning of human cloning. These questions
and concerns will guide us throughout the report.
Human Cloning in Context
It is useful to begin by observing how it is that the question
of human cloning has come before us. The prospect of cloning human
beings confronts us now not as the result of a strong public demand
or a long-standing need. Unlike sought-for medical therapies, it
was not at the outset pursued as a cure for disease. Neither has
it been sought explicitly as a tool for genetic control or "enhancement"
of human offspring. Cloning has arisen not so much because it was
actively sought for its own sake, but because it is a natural extension
of certain biotechnological advances of the past several decades.iii
For more than half a century, and at an accelerating pace, biomedical
scientists have been gaining wondrous new knowledge of the workings
of living beings, from small to great. Increasingly, they also are
providing precise and sophisticated knowledge of the workings of
the human body and mind. Such knowledge of how things work often
leads to new technological powers to control or alter these workings,
powers ordinarily sought in order to treat human disease and relieve
suffering.
Questions regarding the meaning of acquiring such powers
both the promise and the peril have attracted scholarly and
public attention. For more than thirty years, ethical issues related
to biomedical advance have occupied the growing field of bioethics.
Increasingly, these ethical issues have spawned public discussion
and debates. A growing number of people sense that something new
and momentous is happening; that the accelerating waves of biotechnical
advances touch deeply on our most human concerns; and that the centuries-old
project for human mastery of nature may now be, so to speak, coming
home, giving humanity the power to alter and "master" itself.
One important aspect of human life already affected by new biotechnologies
is human reproduction. For several decades now, building on advances
in genetics, cell biology, and developmental biology, and on technologies
used first in animal husbandry, scientists around the world have
been adapting techniques and developing tools to study, influence,
and manipulate the origins of human life. Beginning with techniques
of artificial insemination and progressing through in vitro fertilization
(IVF) and intracytoplasmic sperm injection, artificial aids to reproduction
have come into standard medical use.
Cloning is, in one sense, another step along this path. It developed
as the result of research into mammalian reproduction and development,
where it is desired also as a means of replicating animals especially
useful to human beings. It is also proposed as an additional means
to overcome infertility in humans.
But the controversy surrounding human cloning, and the widespread
sense of disquiet and concern with which the prospect has been received
around the world, make it clear that cloning is not just another
reproductive technology, to be easily assimilated into ordinary
life. Nearly all participants in the public debate over human cloning
appear to agree that the subject touches upon some of the most fundamental
questions regarding the nature of our humanity and the character
of our society. In addition, it raises questions about the aims
of biomedical science and about the relation between science and
society, including the possibility and desirability of exercising
public control over the uses of biomedical technology and the conduct
of biomedical research. It is because we sense these larger entailments
that the subject of cloning matters so much to us. It is these considerations
that give the present debate its force and prominence. Thus only
through a serious reflection on these broader questions can the
full meaning of human cloning be discovered. The prospect of human
cloning may have been brought before us by the march of biotechnology,
but now that it is here it is incumbent upon us to look well beyond
its technical and medical aspects, if we are to appreciate its significance
in full.
Three areas of inquiry in particular seem essential to any understanding
of the full meaning of human cloning: the nature and meaning of
human procreation; the aims, ends, and means of biomedical science
and technology; and the relation of science and technology to the
larger society.
Cloning and Human Procreation
Human procreation provides the major context for considering the
prospect of cloning, especially cloning-to-produce-children. Much
of the time, most of us tend to take for granted this central aspect
of human life, through which all of us come to be and through which
we give birth to our posterity. But the prospect of creating children
by cloning brings this subject sharply before us and compels us
to examine the nature and meaning of human procreation. For cloning-to-produce-children,
while it may be a potential aid to human reproduction, appears also
to be a substitute for it, or at least for its natural, un-programmed,
sexual character. Properly to assess the meaning of producing cloned
children, one must first of all consider the meaning of human procreation
in all its aspects and entailments.iv
Human procreation, though seemingly an exclusively private act,
has a profoundly public meaning. It determines the relations between
one generation and the next, shapes identities, creates attachments,
and sets up responsibilities for the care and rearing of children
(and the care of aging parents or other needy kin). Thus, in considering
proposals to clone children, we must ask ourselves what cloning
would mean not only for the individual parents and children involved,
but also for the surrounding families and for all of society. Opinions
on this subject will of course differ, sometimes widely, as they
rest on possibly differing perceptions of human procreation and
family life. Yet the following basic observations, concerns, and
questions seem pertinent, notwithstanding possible differences of
opinion among us about how much weight to give them.
Among the important aspects of the topic are these: the meaning
of having children; the meaning of sexual, as opposed to asexual,
reproduction; the meaning of origins and genetic endowment for identity
and sense of self; the meaning of exercising greater human control
over the processes and "products" of human reproduction; and the
difference between begetting and making.
To understand what it would mean to clone a child, we do well to
consider most generally what it means to bring a child into the
world, and with what attitude we should regard his or her arrival
and presence. Our children are, to begin with, our replacements,
those who will one day stand in our place. They are, as Hans Jonas
has remarked, "life's own answer to mortality." Though their conception
is the fruit of our activity, and though we are responsible for
saying "yes" to their arrival, we do not, in normal procreation,
command their conception, control their makeup, or rule over their
development and birth. They are, in an important sense, "given"
to us. Though they are our children, they are not our property.
Though they are our flesh and blood, and deeply kin, they are also
independent "strangers" who arrive suddenly out of the darkness
and whom we must struggle to get to know. Though we may seek to
have them for our own self-fulfillment, they exist also and especially
for their own sakes. Though we seek to educate them, they are not
like our other projects, determined strictly according to our plans
and serving only our desires.
If these observations are correct, certain things follow regarding
the attitudes we should have toward our children. We treat them
rightly when we treat them as gifts rather than as products, and
when we treat them as independent beings whom we are duty-bound
to protect and nurture rather than as extensions of ourselves subject
only to our wills and whims. Might these attitudes toward children
be altered by cloning, and, if so, how? Would social attitudes toward
children change, even if cloning were not practiced widely? What
might these changes mean?
To understand how the introduction of asexual reproduction
might affect human life, we must first seek the intrinsic meaning
of the sexual character of human reproduction and what
it implies for individuals, for families, and for the relation between
the generations. Once again, the following observations while
hardly exhaustive seem pertinent and important.
In sexual reproduction,v
each child has two complementary biological progenitors. Each child
thus stems from and unites exactly two lineages, lines that trace
backward in similar branching fashion for ages. Moreover, the precise
genetic endowment of each child is determined by a combination of
nature and chance, not by human design: each human child naturally
acquires and shares the common human species genotype, each child
is genetically (equally) kin to each (both) parent(s), yet each
child is also genetically unique.vi
Cloning-to-produce-children departs from this pattern. A cloned
child has unilineal, not bilineal, descent; he or she is genetically
kin to only one progenitor. What is more, the genetic kinship is
near-total: the cloned child is not genetically unique, but shares
almost completely the genetic endowment of the "original" progenitor.
Finally, this endowment comes to the cloned child not by chance
but by human choice and decision. What do these differences mean
for the cloned child, for family relations, and for relations across
the generations?
Origins and genetic endowment are significant aspects of who one
is and how one regards oneself, of one's "identity," individuality,
and place in the social order. The biological linkages and prospects
implicit in sexual reproduction help to define us, though, it should
go without saying, they do not define us completely. While we are
more "what we choose to become" than we are "where we came from,"
our human beginnings matter, biologically, psychically, and socially.
Because of the way we are generated, each of us is at once (1) equally
human, (2) equally marked by and from birth as mortal, (3) equally
enmeshed in a particular familial nexus of origin, (4) equally individuated
in our trajectory from the beginning to the end of our lives
and, if all goes well, (5) equally capable (despite our mortality)
of participating with a complementary other in the very same renewal
of human possibility through procreation. Our genetic identity
manifest, for instance, in our distinctive appearance by which we
are recognized by others and in our immune system by which we maintain
our integrity against "foreign invasions" also symbolizes
and foreshadows exactly the unique, never-to-be-repeated character
of each human life. In addition, human societies virtually everywhere
have structured child-rearing responsibilities and systems of identity
and relationships on the bases of these natural facts of begetting.
Kinship is tied to origins, and identity, at least in part, is tied
to kinship. It is against this background that we must consider
the implications of clonal reproduction, and the alterations it
might produce in how cloned children would regard themselves and
how they would be regarded by others. What would cloning-to-produce-children
mean for individual identity, for kinship, and for sense of self,
not only for the cloned child but also for his or her family?
Unaided sexual procreation is an activity at once natural, private,
mysterious, unmediated, unpredictable, and undesigned. With the
arrival of techniques such as IVF to assist procreation in the face
of infertility, the process becomes less private and more mediated.
But although technique is used, the basic structure of sexual reproduction
the combination of genetic material from father and mother
resulting in a genetically unique child is unaltered, the
outcome is still unpredictable, and the genetic endowment of the
child remains uncontrolled and undesigned. Cloning-to-produce-children
would seem to bring procreation under human control and direction.
What would this mean? What are the implications of allowing reproductive
activities to become increasingly technological and commercialized?
Cloning would be the first instance in which parents could select
in advance the precise (or nearly precise) genetic makeup of their
child, by selecting the donor to be cloned. It therefore forces
us to ask what might be the difference between begetting and making,
to wonder whether cloning somehow crosses the line between them,
and, if so, to consider whether and why that should worry us.
Though admittedly sketchy and incomplete, these preliminary reflections
on the nature and meaning of human procreation should enable us
to see cloning and especially cloning-to-produce-children-in
its most important human context and to understand its deepest implications
for its practitioners and for society.
Cloning and Biomedical Science
Human procreation is not the only context for evaluating the prospect
of human cloning. As a product of biotechnology, a potential means
of assisted reproduction, and a possible source of cloned embryos
for research and medical use, human cloning also points us to questions
about the aims, ends, and means of biomedical science and technology.
Ordinarily, we are not prompted to much reflection about what science
is for and what goals technology should serve. Our society tacitly
accepts the self-directing and self-augmenting character of these
activities, and the vast majority of us support them because we
esteem and benefit from their contributions to human understanding
and human welfare. However, when developments such as cloning raise
profound questions affecting fundamental moral values and social
institutions, we are forced to consider the ends and means of science
and technology, and to explore their standing in the scheme of human
goods.
To provide a context for assessing human cloning and its possible
benefits, we do well to remember the goals of medicine and modern
science: the great value and importance of treating disease and
relieving suffering, including the sorrows of infertility; and the
great value and importance of gaining knowledge about the workings
of nature, our own nature emphatically included. No one can doubt
the merit of these noble aims. Yet there has always been some disagreement
about the lengths to which we should allow ourselves to go in serving
them. Questions therefore arise about the need for limits on scientific
pursuits and technological activities, and, conversely, about the
meaning of such limits for the scientific and technological enterprises.
To address these questions, we must appreciate the human good of
biomedical science in its fullness, and we must ask about the necessary
and sufficient conditions for its flourishing. We must recognize,
among other things, the unpredictability of scientific discovery
and technological innovation, and the importance, therefore, of
keeping open lines of inquiry and experimentation regardless of
current estimates of their likelihood of success. Although serendipity
often favors the prepared mind, nature guards her secrets well,
and even the best scientists are regularly surprised by where the
keys to the locks are ultimately found.
But precisely because so much of biomedical science is exploratory
and experimental, scientific inquiry is not just thought but also
action, action often involving research on living subjects, including
human beings. And precisely because the use of technologies often
has unintended or undesirable side effects, affecting many human
goods in addition to health, safety, and the relief of suffering,
large questions are necessarily raised when the goods promoted by
technology come into conflict with others. For example, is the need
to discover new cures for the sick a moral imperative that should
trump all other goods and values? If not, then on what basis can
it be limited? What moral boundaries should scientists and technologists
respect as they continue their quests for knowledge and cures, whether
or not they receive public funding? How can society establish and
enforce such boundaries? And, on the other hand, how can science
and technology be protected against unreasonable limitations imposed
by excessively fearful legislators or overzealous regulators?
To be sure, these large questions are hard to answer in the abstract.
As a result, they do not recommend themselves for much deliberation.
Yet they are very close to the surface of the current debate about
human cloning. Moreover, implicit answers to these questions, seldom
articulated and rarely defended save by mere assertion, at least
color and may even determine what people think should be done about
human cloning. A clearer and more thoughtful awareness of the aims
of biomedical science could help us assess whether and how human
cloning might serve the ends of science and medicine and could help
us more fully consider its possible benefits and potential drawbacks.
But we must consider not only the ends of science, but also the
means it employs. Cloning, after all, is a technique, a means of
reaching some desired end. Even if the purposes it might serve are
worthy, it must still be evaluated as a means. Not every means employed
in the pursuit of worthy ends can pass ethical muster. This truth
is widely recognized in the establishment of canons of ethics regarding
the use of human subjects in research. It is also recognized in
the established practice of technology assessment, which seeks to
find the least problematic and least dangerous means for achieving
a desirable end.
For instance, as a means of treating infertility or of providing
a suitable source of compatible organs for transplantation, cloning
raises difficulties having to do with human dignity and the costs
of "manufacture" of the sort discussed earlier. Human cloning also
raises questions about the ethics of research with human subjects,
with risks of harm to the child-to-be, the egg donor, and the woman
who would bring the cloned child to birth, questions that we shall
take up in some detail in Chapter
Five. Yet the most highly controverted moral argument about
human cloning research involves a human subject not always considered
when the ethics of research is discussed: the early human embryo.
Because all cloning begins with the production of embryonic clones,
and because such clones are potentially highly useful in biomedical
research, questions of the ethics of means are absolutely central
to the debate about the morality of cloning.
Ethical questions regarding the use of human embryos in research
are, of course, not unique to cloning. They have been central to
the recent and continuing controversy about federal funding of research
on human embryonic stem cells, because human embryos produced by
IVF offer possibilities for medical advances, beyond their use in
assisted reproduction. The use of embryos has aided research on
early human development. These embryos are also the source of human
embryonic stem cells, pluripotent cellsvii
that may be induced to develop into all the tissues of the body.
These stem cells thus may hold great promise for future treatment
of chronic degenerative diseases and disabilities.
The difficulty arises because the embryos put to use in these ways
are themselves destroyed. This fact raises serious and troubling
questions about the proper way to regard these nascent human organisms
and the morally appropriate way to treat them. Cloning techniques
might provide an even more useful source of embryos for biomedical
research than current IVF techniques. Human cloning could yield
numerous identical embryos, could provide for the study of stem
cells derived from individuals known to possess genetic diseases,
and might eventually yield transplantable tissues for regenerative
medicine that would escape immune rejection. Human cloning-for-biomedical-research
therefore brings the moral question of means before us with even
greater force. It calls on us to think of the good of medical advances
and the relief of human suffering while at the same time considering
our responsibilities to nascent human life and the possible harms
to ourselves and future generations that may result from coming
to regard the beginning stages of human life as raw material for
use and exploitation.
While there is almost universal opposition to cloning-to-produce-children,
the prospect of using cloned embryos in biomedical research has
attracted significant support in the general public and among many
scientists, patient advocacy groups, and policymakers. It therefore
presents more complicated moral and policy challenges, and requires
serious reflection on the duty of society to those of its members
who are suffering, as well as its responsibility for nascent life.
The precise character of both that duty and that responsibility
is a subject of long-standing dispute, giving rise to a contentious
but very important public debate.
Cloning and Public Policy
Beneath the current debate about human cloning lie major questions
about the relation between science and technology and the larger
society. Valuing freedom and innovation, our society allows scientists
to inquire as they wish, to explore freely, and to develop techniques
and technologies based on the knowledge they find, and on the whole
we all benefit greatly as a result. We limit what scientists can
do only in certain cases, as when their research requires the use
of human subjects, in which case we erect rules and procedures to
protect the health, safety, and dignity of the weak from possible
encroachments by the strong. In more pervasive ways, we also shape
what science does through public decisions about financial support
and scientific education. With the uses of technology, we are sometimes
more intrusive, establishing regulations to protect public health
and safety or to preserve the environment. In rare cases, we even
ban certain practices, such as the buying and selling of organs
for transplantation. Yet, on the whole, the spirit of laissez-faire
governs technological research, development, and use.
But when innovations arise that appear to challenge basic goods
that we hold dear, or when the desirability of scientific and technological
progress runs up against concerns for the protection of human life
and well-being, we are forced to consider the tacit social contract
between science and technology and the larger society. The current
public and political deliberation about whether and how to restrict
or prohibit human cloning forces us to do so in a most powerful
way.
In addition, the current deliberation confronts us with the task
of balancing important and commonly defended freedoms the
freedom of scientists to inquire, of technologists to invent, of
individuals to reproduce, of entrepreneurs to invest and to profit
with the well-being of our society and its members. Circumstances
in which otherwise beneficent freedoms can endanger paramount moral
and social goods present serious challenges for free societies,
and the prospect of cloning presents us with just such a challenge.
This is not an altogether unfamiliar challenge. There are other
circumstances in which the freedom to explore, inquire, research,
and develop technologies has been constrained. Biomedical science,
as we have said, is restricted in its use of human subjects for
research, and scientists are required to obtain informed consent
and take great care to secure research subjects from harm. Scientific
work is also restricted from activities that might harm the health
of the general public, and from producing products that may endanger
consumers. For example, the federal Food and Drug Administration
sits at the juncture between development and marketing of medical
products, regulating their introduction and use according to criteria
of safety and efficacy. Our society has come to a near-total agreement
on the need for such an agency and the importance of its work.
Human cloning, however, does not easily fall into any of the familiar
classes of our experience with science. Nor do the ethical challenges
it raises fit neatly into the categories of risks to health and
safety that are ordinarily the basis of public oversight of science
and technology. Raising ethical questions about ends as well as
means, cloning is at once a potential human experiment, a possible
aid to reproduction, an altogether new sort of procreative technique,
a prospective means of human design, and a source of embryos and
embryonic stem cells for research. It points back to familiar dilemmas
of bioethics including the ethics of human experimentation
and embryo research and it points forward to the sorts of
challenges that will face us as biology gains greater technical
prowess. It therefore invites us to think anew about the relationship
between society and biomedical science and to evaluate the sufficiency
of current institutions and practices that govern that relationship.
The potential dangers we face do not result from ill intent or
bad faith. Neither of the prevailing caricatures in the cloning
debate the mad scientist on a blind quest for an inhuman immortality
or the puritanical Luddite seeking to keep the future at bay
is accurate, appropriate, helpful, or fair. The challenge we face
is not as easy as that. The challenge we face involves the conflict
of competing sets of concerns and priorities, each in the service
of vital human goods, and each driven by a desire to improve the
human condition and to protect essential principles. The widely
shared desire to cure disease, relieve suffering, understand human
biology, and provide humankind with new and more powerful means
of control can conflict, in this case, with the widely shared desire
to respect life, individual identity, the dignity of human procreation,
and other institutions and principles that keep our society healthy
and strong. The challenge for our society is to determine, through
public deliberation and thoughtful reflection, how best to adjudicate
between these two desires and to determine what form to give to
the tacit agreement between society and science, by which society
promises freedom within bounds, and science affords us innovation,
knowledge, and power while respecting reasonable limits.
The new and distinct challenges that confront us through cloning
call upon us to consider the character of that tacit agreement,
and to determine whether, and in what way, it might need to be amended
and supplemented, especially in the face of the rapidly arriving
new biomedical technologies that touch so directly upon our humanity.
It is our hope in this report to contribute to just such a thoughtful
consideration of the question.
The Report
In Chapter One
we present a brief history of human cloning. We summarize the scientific
developments, the various public and political debates, and the
actions of earlier panels and government bodies.
In Chapter Three
we discuss the terminology of the cloning debate. We analyze the
controversy over cloning terms, state the terms we intend to use,
and lay out the rationale behind our choice of terms.
In Chapter Four we present a survey of the scientific aspects of
human and animal cloning. We attempt to clarify what cloning is,
where the science stands, and where it may be going.
In Chapter Five
we discuss the ethical arguments for and against human cloning-to-produce-children.
We consider reasons to create cloned children, concerns over safety
and consent, and a series of moral objections.
In Chapter Six
we discuss the ethical arguments for and against cloning-for-biomedical-research.
We consider the likely medical benefits, the potential social and
ethical difficulties, and the concern over the treatment of human
embryos.
In Chapter Seven
we discuss the public policy alternatives. We consider various options
for government action, and present arguments for and against each.
In Chapter Eight,
we present the Council's conclusions and offer our recommendations.
______________________________
- The term "human cloning" is used in this chapter to refer to
all human cloning: cloning-to-produce-children and cloning-for-biomedical-research.
When only one particular use of human cloning is intended, we
use the more specific term. A full discussion of our choice of
terminology is provided in Chapter
Three. Back
to Text
- Cloning Human Beings, Rockville, MD: National Bioethics
Advisory Commission, 1997. Human embryonic stem cells had not
yet been isolated at the time of the NBAC report, so the Commission
did not offer any recommendations on cloning-for-biomedical-research.
Back
to Text
- Chapter One
summarizes selected historical aspects of the emergence of cloning
research and public reactions to the prospect of human cloning.
Chapter Four summarizes selected aspects of the current state
of the relevant science and technology. Back
to Text
- In order to be sure that we explore fully the human meaning
of cloning, we shall examine it in comparison with natural unaided
human reproduction, rather than assisted reproduction, say, with
in vitro fertilization. The established reproductive technologies
do provide some useful points of comparison, but they cannot be
taken as the most helpful baseline for understanding the significance
of cloning. For that, normal sexual reproduction is the appropriate
basis of comparison. Back
to Text
- The term "sexual reproduction" has two related meanings: the
first refers to the act of sexual intercourse that initiates conception
by introducing sperm into a woman's generative tract; the second
refers to the conception itself, the combination of genetic material
from egg and sperm that results in a new organism with a unique
genotype. Assisted reproduction techniques like IVF do not involve
the former, but do involve the latter and are therefore still
rightly considered sexual reproduction. (Likewise, children who
are adopted are the fruit of sexual reproduction.) Cloning involves
neither, and is therefore described as "asexual reproduction."
The second and more fundamental meaning of "sexual reproduction,"
the union of egg and sperm that results in a new genetically unique
organism, is the basis of our discussion in this section. Back
to Text
- The apparent exception of identical twins is discussed in Chapter
Five. Back
to Text
- Pluripotent cells are those that can give rise to many different
types of differentiated cells. See Glossary of Terms. Back
to Text
Chapter Two
Historical Aspects of Cloning
The previous chapter located human cloning in its larger human
context. This chapter provides a brief history of human cloning,
both as a scientific matter and as a subject of public discussion,
debate, and legislation.1
Although we present only selected highlights, rather than a comprehensive
account, we seek to enable the reader to place the present debate
about cloning and this report into their proper historical setting.
Until recently, all discussion of human cloning concentrated exclusively
on the prospect of clonal reproduction, the production of individuals
genetically virtually identical to previously existing ones. Our
historical account here reflects that emphasis. Yet we will also
consider the emerging interest in cloning-for-biomedical-research,
a prospect connected to the recent isolation of embryonic stem cells
and their potential for the understanding and treatment of human
disease and disability.
Scientific Milestones
As a scientific and technical possibility, human cloning has emerged
as an outgrowth of discoveries or innovations in developmental biology,
genetics, assisted reproductive technologies, animal breeding, and,
most recently, research on embryonic stem cells. Assisted reproductive
techniques in humans accomplished the in vitro fertilization of
a human egg, yielding a zygote and developing embryo that could
be successfully implanted into a woman's uterus to give rise to
a live-born child. Animal breeders developed and refined these techniques
with a view to perpetuating particularly valuable animals and maintaining
laboriously identified genomes. Most recently, the isolation of
embryonic stem cells and their subsequent in vitro differentiation
into many different cell types have opened up possibilities for
repairing and replacing diseased or nonfunctioning tissue, and thus
possible research uses for cloned human embryos.
The German embryologist Hans Spemann conducted what many consider
to be the earliest "cloning" experiments on animals. Spemann was
interested in answering a fundamental question of biological development:
does each differentiated cell retain the full complement of genetic
information present initially in the zygote? In the late 1920s,
he tied off part of a cell containing the nucleus from a salamander
embryo at the sixteen-cell stage and allowed the single cell to
divide, showing that the nucleus of that early embryo could, in
effect, "start over." In a 1938 book, Embryonic Development
and Induction, Spemann wondered whether more completely differentiated
cells had the same capacity and speculated about the possibility
of transferring the nucleus from a differentiated cell taken
from either a later-stage embryo or an adult organism into
an enucleated egg. As he explained it: "Decisive information about
this question may perhaps be afforded by an experiment which appears,
at first sight, to be somewhat fantastical. This experiment might
possibly show that even nuclei of differentiated cells can initiate
normal development in the egg protoplasms." 2
But Spemann did not know how to conduct such an experiment.
Research with frogs fourteen years later encouraged progress toward
the "fantastical experiment." In 1952, the American embryologists
Robert Briggs and Thomas J. King first successfully transferred
nuclei from early embryonic cells of leopard frogs to enucleated
leopard frog eggs. The "activated egg" began to divide and develop,
became a multicellular embryo, and then became a tadpole. 3
Embryologists in other laboratories successfully repeated these
initial experiments on different species of frogs. But additional
experience also showed that the older and more differentiated a
donor cell becomes, the less likely it is that its nucleus would
be able to direct development.
In 1962, the British developmental biologist John Gurdon reported
that he had produced sexually mature frogs by transferring nuclei
from intestinal cells of tadpoles into enucleated frog eggs.4
The experiments had a low success rate and remained controversial.
Gurdon continued this work in the 1970s, and he was able to produce
tadpoles by transferring the nucleus of adult frog skin cells into
enucleated frog eggs. Later experiments established that many factors
in addition to the intact nucleus are crucial to success (see Chapter
Four for further discussion). In retrospect, it is surprising that
any of these earlier experiments produced positive results.5
But despite their low success rates, these experiments demonstrated
that the nucleus retained its full complement of genetic information
and encouraged later investigators to explore mammalian cloning.
The birth of Louise Brown in 1978, the first baby conceived through
in vitro fertilization (IVF), was also an important milestone, because
it demonstrated that human birth was possible from eggs that were
fertilized outside the body and then implanted into the womb. As
for the possibility of cloning animals from adult cells especially
mammals the work in the intervening years focused largely
on the reprogramming of gene expression in somatic cells, the transfer
of nuclei taken from embryos in mammals (beginning with mice in
the 1980s), and finally the work of Ian Wilmut and his colleagues
at the Roslin Institute with adult nuclei, which led to the birth
of Dolly on July 5, 1996. Since then, similar success has been achieved
in cloning other mammalian species, including cattle, goats, pigs,
mice, cats, and rabbits (see Chapter
Four).
The animal cloners did not set out to develop techniques for cloning
humans. Wilmut's goal was to replicate or perpetuate animals carrying
a valuable genome (for example, sheep that had been genetically
modified to produce medically valuable proteins in their milk).
Others, such as the cloners of the kitten CC, were interested in
commercial ventures for the cloning of pets.6
Yet the techniques developed in animals have encouraged a small
number of infertility therapists to contemplate and explore efforts
to clone human children. And, following the announcement in 1998
by James Thomson and his associates of their isolation of human
embryonic stem cells, there emerged an interest in cloned human
embryos, not for reproductive uses but as a powerful tool for research
into the nature and treatment of human disease.
Human Cloning from Popular Literature to Public Policy:
From Brave New World to the Birth of Dolly
Technological novelties are often imagined and discussed in literature,
especially in science fiction, before they are likely or even possible
in practice. This has certainly been the case with human cloning,
whose place in the popular imagination precedes the earliest successful
animal cloning experiments. Perhaps the most famous early modern
account of human cloning is Aldous Huxley's Brave New World (1932),
where natural human procreation has become a thing of the past,
and where babies are produced in identical batches through "Bokanovsky's
Process." As the novelist tells it:
One egg, one embryo, one adult normality. But a
bokanovskified egg will bud, will proliferate, will divide . . .
becoming anywhere from eight to ninety-six embryos a prodigious
improvement, you will agree, on nature. Identical twins but
not in piddling twos and threes . . . Standard men and women; in
uniform batches.7
The relevance or irrelevance of Huxley's vision to the dilemmas
of the present is of course a matter of serious disagreement. Some
believe that fears of a "Brave New World" are fantasy divorced from
both the political realities of modern liberal democracy and the
facts of science. Others believe the book remains a prescient warning
of where biological self-manipulation could take us which
is to say, to a world where family is obsolete, life is engineered
to order in the laboratory, and human beings have reduced themselves
to well-satisfied human animals.
In the late 1960s, following John Gurdon's successful cloning experiments,
a more focused debate on both the likelihood and the ethical and
social implications of human cloning began among scientists, theologians,
and ethicists. At this time, the still hypothetical possibility
of cloning humans was considered as a part of a broader eugenic
project to improve the genetic stock of humans as a species. In
a famous article published in The American Naturalist in
1966, entitled "Experimental Genetics and Human Evolution," Nobel
laureate biologist Joshua Lederberg described what he took to be
the prospects of "clonal reproduction." "Experimentally," he wrote,
"we know of successful nuclear transplantation from diploid somatic
as well as germline cells into enucleated amphibian eggs. There
is nothing to suggest any particular difficulty about accomplishing
this in mammals or man, though it will rightly be admired as a technical
tour-de-force when it is first implemented." He also predicted "there
will be little delay between demonstration and use."8
While Lederberg concluded his essay by exhorting his readers not
to "mistake comment for advocacy," he clearly believed that clonal
reproduction might offer a number of human benefits or improvements.
"If a superior individual (and presumably then genotype) is identified,
why not copy it directly, rather than suffer all the risks of recombinational
disruption, including those of sex," he asked. "The same solace
is accorded the carrier of genetic disease: why not be sure of an
exact copy of yourself rather than risk a homozygous segregant;i
or at worst copy your spouse and allow some degree of biological
parenthood." He described other possibilities such as "the
free exchange of organ transplants with no concern for graft rejection"
and more efficient communication between individuals in "stressed
occupations."9
In the end, Lederberg argued that "tempered clonality" a
mix of clonal and sexual reproduction might, at least from
a biological standpoint, "allow the best of both worlds we
would at least enjoy being able to observe the experiment of discovering
whether a second Einstein would outdo the first one." Nevertheless,
he acknowledged the possibility for "social frictions" and ethical
dilemmas that might result from clonal reproduction including
whether "anyone could conscientiously risk the crucial experiment,
the first attempt to clone a man." He suggested that the "mingling
of individual human chromosomes with other mammals assures a gradualistic
enlargement of the field and lowers the threshold of optimism or
arrogance, particularly if cloning in other mammals gives incompletely
predictable results." And he feared that social policy might become
based on "the accidents of the first advertised examples" rather
than "well-debated principles." 10
In 1970, the theologian and ethicist Paul Ramsey responded to Lederberg's
portrait of human cloning and, more generally, to the prospects
for human self-modification in a book called Fabricated
Man: The Ethics of Genetic Control. He argued that human cloning
would violate the ethical responsibilities of both science and parenthood:
it would involve experiments on the child-to-be; it would transform
parenthood into manufacture; and it would burden children with the
genetic predisposition of their "maker" and so deny the cloned child
a unique independence in the very act of bringing him or her to
life. "[T]o attempt to soar so high above an eminently human parenthood,"
Ramsey wrote, "is inevitably to fall far below into a vast
technological alienation of man .. The entire rationalization of
procreation its replacement by replication can only
mean the abolition of man's embodied personhood." 11
Ramsey believed that such a willingness to experiment on human
life or to create sub-humans-showed how the effort to perfect
and improve humankind through genetic control leads in fact to ethical
coarsening and to a disregard for actual human beings. "In the present
age," he wrote, "the attempt will be made to deprive us of our wits
by comparing objections to schemes of progressive genetic engineering
or cloning men to earlier opposition to inoculations, blood transfusions,
or the control of malaria. These things are by no means to be compared:
the practice of medicine in the service of life is one thing; man's
unlimited self-modification of the genetic conditions of life would
be quite another matter."12
The debate over human cloning and genetic manipulation continued
in the early 1970s. The Nobel laureate geneticist James D. Watson
testified before Congress in 1971 on the subject of human cloning.
He described the science that was taking us there, including John
Gurdon's success in cloning frogs and the work of R. G. Edwards
and P. S. Steptoe "in working out the conditions for routine test-tube
conception of human eggs."13
"Human embryological development," Watson observed, "need no longer
be a process shrouded in secrecy. It can become instead an event
wide-open to a variety of experimental manipulations." Watson called
for the creation of national and international committees to promote
"wide-ranging discussion . at the informal as well as formal legislative
level, about the manifold problems which are bound to arise if test-tube
conception becomes a common occurrence." 14
"This is a decision not for the scientists at all," he said. "It
is a decision of the general public do you want this or not?"
and something that "if we do not think about it now, the possibility
of our having a free choice will one day suddenly be gone."15
In 1972, Willard Gaylin, a psychiatrist and co-founder of the newly
formed Institute of Society, Ethics, and the Life Sciences (later
called the Hastings Center), made James Watson's warnings about
cloning even more dramatic with a New York Times Magazine
article titled "The Frankenstein Myth Becomes a Reality We
Have the Awful Knowledge to Make Exact Copies of Human Beings."
Gaylin hoped that the prospect of human cloning would awaken the
public and the scientific community to the larger ethical
implications of the life sciences.16
The same year, biologist and ethicist Leon R. Kass published an
essay in The Public Interest called "Making Babies
The New Biology and the 'Old' Morality," which addressed the prospect
of both in vitro fertilization and human cloning, and wondered whether
"by tampering with and confounding [our] origins, we are involved
in nothing less than creating a new conception of what it means
to be human."17
In stark contrast to Gaylin and Kass, ethicist Joseph Fletcher
argued that human cloning would not be dehumanizing at all, but
would, in a number of circumstances, serve the good of both society
and individuals. In his 1974 book The Ethics of Genetic Control:
Ending Reproductive Roulette, he argued that "Good reasons
in general for cloning are that it avoids genetic diseases, bypasses
sterility, predetermines an individual's gender, and preserves family
likenesses. It wastes time to argue over whether we should do it
or not; the real moral question is when and why."18
For Fletcher unlike Ramsey, Gaylin, and Kass genetic
control would serve the human end of self-mastery and self-improvement,
it would improve the quality of life for individuals, and it would
aid the progress of the human species. Gunther Stent, a molecular
biologist at the University of California at Berkeley, echoed this
view that human cloning would contribute to human perfection. As
he wrote in a 1974 article in Nature: "To oppose human cloning .
. . is to betray the Western dream of the City of God. All utopian
visionaries, from Thomas More to Karl Marx, think of their perfect
societies as being populated not by men but by angels that embody
all of the best and none of the worst human attributes." 19
With cloning, he suggested, such a city might one day be possible.
For several years, cloning remained a topic for fiction and philosophy,
but fantasy had yet to turn into fact. In 1978, in a book titled
In His Image: The Cloning of a Man, science writer David Rorvik
claimed that he was involved in a secret project to clone a millionaire
in Montana named "Max."20
The book caused a flurry of reaction ranging from horror to
amusement to nearly universal skepticism and denunciation in the
scientific community and eventually led to hearings before
Congress on May 31, 1978. Robert Briggs, who with Thomas King cloned
the first frog embryo from blastula frog cells in 1952, declared
that the work in frogs demonstrated not that human cloning is now
or imminently possible, but that "cloning in man or any other animal
is not just a technical problem to be solved soon but may, in fact,
never occur."21
James Watson, who just a few years earlier had urged a national
conversation and possible legislation on human cloning because of
the rapid advances in the science, declared that we would "certainly
not [see the cloning of a man] in any of our lifetimes. I wouldn't
be able to predict when we might see the cloning of a mouse, much
less a man."22
Rorvik eventually admitted that the book was a hoax.
In the years that followed, claims and counter-claims of scientific
advances in mammalian cloning including the controversy beginning
in 1981 over whether any of several independent laboratories had
actually cloned mice prompted more public reaction and discussion
about the issue. But there was no sustained or widespread public
interest, and cloning lost its prominent place within the bioethics
literature. The President's Bioethics Commission, in its 1982 report
Splicing Life, briefly discussed human cloning as well
as IVF, but held that both were beyond the scope of that report
because they could be considered reproductive technologies that
did not necessarily involve modifying the genome (pp. 9-10). With
regard to human cloning in particular, the report added that the
possibility had received a good deal of public attention and it
was therefore important to emphasize that even if it ever did become
possible in humans, it would not result in an identical being.23
The National Institutes of Health Human Embryo Research Panel,
which issued a report in 1994 on federal funding for research involving
preimplantation human embryos, deemed research involving nuclear
transplantation, without transfer of the resulting cloned embryo
to a uterus, as one type of research that was acceptable for federal
support. The report noted that the majority on this point was narrow,
with nearly as many panel members concluding that the ethical implications
of nuclear transplantation should be studied further before any
such research could be acceptable for federal funding (Exec. Summ.,
p. xvii). In its discussion of cloning techniques, the panel noted
that many different procedures are all called "cloning," and said
in a footnote, "Popular notions of cloning derive from science fiction
books and films that have more to do with cultural fantasies than
actual scientific experiments." 24
Of course, there had been, in the meantime, continued scientific
work in nuclear transplantation in animals including mammals.
And with the 1997 announcement of the cloning of Dolly, the prospect
of human cloning once again became a prominent issue in public discussion,
debate, and public life.
The Human Cloning Debate:
From Dolly to the Present
In late February 1997, Ian Wilmut and his team at the Roslin Institute
in Scotland announced that they had, by means of somatic cell nuclear
transfer, successfully cloned the first mammal from an adult somatic
cell Dolly the sheep. President Bill Clinton and British Prime
Minister Tony Blair immediately denounced any attempts to clone
a human being, and the President asked his National Bioethics Advisory
Commission (NBAC) to report within ninety days on the scientific,
ethical, and legal questions surrounding the prospect of human cloning.
Congress likewise held a series of hearings the first one
on March 12, 1997. A widespread though not universal
consensus emerged that attempts to clone a human being would at
present be irresponsible and immoral. As Wilmut explained before
Congress, "Our own experiments to clone sheep from adult mammary
cells required us to produce 277 'reconstructed' embryos. Of these,
twenty-nine were implanted into recipient ewes, and only one developed
into a live lamb. In previous work with cells from embryos, three
out of five lambs died soon after birth and showed developmental
abnormalities. Similar experiments with humans would be totally
unacceptable." 25
Most ethicists agreed, though for different reasons. All agreed
that cloning attempts on human beings "at this time" would be reckless
experiments on the child-to-be and therefore totally unjustified.
Many stressed, as Ramsey, Gaylin, and Kass had done in the 1970s,
that human cloning would undermine the human meaning of parenthood
and identity; that it would mean a giant step toward genetic engineering,
creating the first children whose genetic predisposition was known
and selected in advance; and that it would turn procreation increasingly
into a form of manufacture.26
In contrast, some bioethicists, including John Robertson and Ruth
Macklin, believed that human cloning presented no inherent threat
to public or private morality, that government had no legal authority
or justification for banning clonal reproduction, and that it must
be judged in terms of its particular uses, not dismissed outright.27
In June 1997, NBAC released its report Cloning Human Beings,
which concluded that
At present, the use of this technique to create a child
would be a premature experiment that would expose the fetus and
the developing child to unacceptable risks. This in itself might
be sufficient to justify a prohibition on cloning human beings at
this time, even if such efforts were to be characterized as the
exercise of a fundamental right to attempt to procreate.28
NBAC also pointed to other moral concerns "beyond the issue of
the safety of the procedure," including "the potential psychological
harms to children and effects on the moral, religious, and cultural
values of society" that "merit further discussion." NBAC recommended
a three-to-five-year federal moratorium on human cloning stating
that the consensus came from the fact that the technique was not
yet safe to be revisited and reevaluated after that time.
"Whether upon such further deliberation our nation will conclude
that the use of cloning techniques to create children should be
allowed or permanently banned is, for the moment, an open question."
29
In early 1998, the United States Senate considered legislation,
proposed by Republican Senators Christopher Bond of Missouri, Bill
Frist of Tennessee, and Judd Gregg of New Hampshire, to ban all
human cloning permanently. Nearly all senators denounced clonal
reproduction, but many believed that the proposed ban, which would
have made it illegal to create human embryos by means of somatic
cell nuclear transfer, would undermine potentially valuable scientific
research. Democratic Senators Edward Kennedy of Massachusetts and
Tom Harkin of Iowa led the opposition, with the widespread support
of patient advocacy groups, scientific and medical organizations,
and the biotechnology industry. As Senator Kennedy put it:
Every scientist in America understands the threat this
legislation poses to critical medical research. Every American should
understand it, too. . . . Congress can and should act to ban cloning
of human beings during this session. But it should not act in haste,
and it should not pass legislation that goes far beyond what the
American people want or what the scientific and medical community
understands is necessary or appropriate.30
The legislation died after heated debate, and the concern over
human cloning temporarily lost urgency and subsided.
In November 1998, a new scientific discovery was unveiled that
would soon provoke a different public policy debate, one that would
become entangled with the ethical and social questions surrounding
human cloning. James Thomson and John Gearhart separately announced
the isolation of human embryonic stem cells multipotent cells
(see Glossary of Terms) derived from human embryos that they believed
hold great promise for curing or treating many diseases and injuries.
The discovery led to another wave of hearings on, and interest in,
the ethics of biological science. It also renewed debate over whether
embryo research should be eligible for public funding (since 1996,
Congress had prohibited federal funding of research involving the
destruction of human embryos). One subject under consideration was
the possible future use of cloned human embryos for stem cell research,
which some scientists believed might be uniquely useful for understanding
embryological development and genetic disease and for possible use
in stem cell therapies.
In August 2000 after another NBAC study President Clinton
announced new guidelines that would have altered the ban on federal
funding of embryo research. The new guidelines, proposed by the
National Institutes of Health, stipulated that the agency would
fund research on embryonic stem cells so long as public funds were
not used to destroy the embryos, the embryos were left over from
IVF clinics, and donors of the embryos consented to the research.
In early 2001, President George W. Bush announced that he would
review these guidelines rather than implement them immediately.2
Around the same time, a number of pro-cloning groups and fertility
doctors including the Raelians, who believe that humans are
the products of cloning by aliens announced their intention
to clone human beings by the end of the year. Other individuals
and scientific organizations worked to protect possible cloning
research from future restrictions, though some scientists (such
as Rudolf Jaenisch and Ian Wilmut31
) publicly argued against cloning-to-produce-children. A flurry
of hearings on human cloning soon followed the first one in
the House of Representatives on March 28, 2001, and continuing in
both the House and the Senate throughout the summer. The hearings
addressed cloning-to-produce-children as well as issues related
to cloning-for-biomedical-research.
Two general approaches to banning human cloning emerged. The first
approach, proposed in a bill sponsored by Republican Representative
David Weldon of Florida and Democratic Representative Bart Stupak
of Michigan in the House, and Republican Senator Sam Brownback of
Kansas and Democratic Senator Mary Landrieu of Louisiana in the
Senate, called for a ban on all human cloning, including the creation
of cloned embryos for biomedical research. The second approach,
proposed in a bill sponsored by Republican Senators Arlen Specter
of Pennsylvania and Orrin Hatch of Utah and Democratic Senators
Diane Feinstein of California and Edward Kennedy of Massachusetts,
sought to prohibit human reproductive cloning, while allowing the
use of cloning technology to produce stem cells, by making it illegal
to implant or attempt to implant cloned human embryos "into a uterus
or the functional equivalent of a uterus."
On July 31, 2001, the House of Representatives passed the Weldon
Stupak bill (the ban on all human cloning) by a vote of 265
to 162. In November 2001, scientists at Advanced Cell Technology,
Inc., of Worcester, Massachusetts, one of the leading commercial
advocates of cloning-for-biomedical-research, reported what they
claimed were the first cloned human embryos. The announcement
along with continued debate on the possible use of cloned human
embryos for stem cell research left the issue in the United
States Senate, where it stands as of this writing.
Meanwhile, the general public has consistently expressed the view
that human cloning is wrong most recently, a Gallup poll from
May 2002 that showed opposition to cloning to produce a child at
90 percent, and opposition to "cloning of human embryos for use
in medical research" at 61 percent. Asked about medical research
using stem cells obtained from human embryos (with no mention of
how the embryo was generated), 52 percent found it morally acceptable,
while 51 percent found acceptable the "cloning of human cells from
adults for use in medical research."32
In addition to activity at the federal level, many states have
been active. As of this writing, twenty-two states have considered
various policy alternatives on cloning, and six have passed legislation.3
Several nations, including Denmark, France, Norway, Spain, and
Canada have passed or sought either partial or total bans. For example,
in the United Kingdom, cloning-to-produce-children is forbidden
but cloned embryos up to fourteen days old may be used in biomedical
research. In Germany, all human cloning is forbidden by law. There
are also efforts now at the United Nations and other international
organizations to pass a world-wide ban on human cloning with
many of the same disagreements internationally as there are nationally
about what kind of ban to pass.
ENDNOTES
- Since the birth of Dolly, several volumes on the history and
significance of cloning have been published, including Kolata,
G., Clone: The Road to Dolly and the Path Ahead, New
York: Morrow and Company, 1998, and National Bioethics Advisory
Commission [NBAC], Cloning Human Beings, Bethesda, MD:
Government Printing Office, 1997. In addition, several valuable
anthologies have been edited, including Kristol, W., and E. Cohen
, The Future is Now, Lanham, MD: Rowman and Littlefield,
2002, and Nussbaum, M., and C.R. Sunstein, Clones and Clones,
New York: Norton, 1998. Back
to Text
- See Spemann, H., Embryonic Development and Induction
(New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1938). As quoted in Kolata,
G., Clone: The Road to Dolly and the Path Ahead (New
York: Morrow and Company, 1998), p. 61. Back
to Text
- Briggs, R., and T. J. King, "Transplantation of living nuclei
from blastula cells into enucleated frog's eggs," Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences (USA) 38: 455-463, 1952.
Back
to Text
- Gurdon, J. B., "The developmental capacity of nuclei taken from
intestinal epithelium cells of feeding tadpoles," Journal
of Embryology and Experimental Morphology 10, 622-640, 1962.
Back
to Text
- A fact also noted by NBAC in Cloning Human Beings,
p. 18. Back
to Text
- Regalado, A., "Only Nine Lives for Kitty? Not if She Is Cloned,"
Wall Street Journal, February 14, 2002, p. B1. Kluger,
J., "Here Kitty Kitty!" Time, February 17, 2002. Back
to Text
- Huxley, Aldous., Brave New World (New York: Harper
Perennial, 1998), p. 6-7. Originally published by Harper & Brothers,
1932. Back
to Text
- Lederberg, J., "Experimental Genetics and Human Evolution,"
The American Naturalist, September-October 1966, Vol.
100, No. 915, pp. 527. Back
to Text
- Ibid, p. 531, 527, 528. Back
to Top
- Ibid, p. 528, 529, 531. Back
to Top
- Ramsey, P., Fabricated Man: The Ethics of Genetic Control
(New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1970), p. 89. Back
to Text
- Ibid, p. 95. Back
to Text
- Watson, J., "Moving Toward the Clonal Man," The Atlantic
Monthly, May 1971, p. 51. (This article is a slightly modified
version of Watson's congressional testimony.) Back
to Text
- Ibid, p. 51, 53. Back
to Text
- Proceedings before the Committee on Science and Astronautics,
U. S. House of Representatives, Ninety-Second Congress, January
26, 27, and 28, 1971, p. 344. Back
to Text
- Gaylin, W., "The Frankenstein Myth Becomes a Reality-We Have
the Awful Knowledge to Make Exact Copies of Human Beings," The
New York Times Magazine, March 5, 1972, p. 12ff. Back
to Text
- Kass, L., "Making Babies-the New Biology and the 'Old' Morality,"
The Public Interest, Winter 1972, Number 26, p. 23. Back
to Text
- Fletcher, J., The Ethics of Genetic Control: Ending Reproductive
Roulette (New York: Anchor Books, 1974), p. 154. Back
to Text
- Stent, G., "Molecular Biology and Metaphysics," Nature,
Vol. 248, No. 5451, April 26, 1974, p. 781. As quoted in Kolata
op. cit., p. 92. Back
to Text
- Rorvik, D. M., In His Image: The Cloning of a Man (New York:
J. B. Lippincott, 1978). Back
to Text
- As quoted in Kolata, op. cit., p. 103. Back
to Text
- Interview by C. P. Anderson, "In His Own Words: Nobel Laureate
James Watson Calls Report of Cloning People 'Science Fiction Silliness,'"
People, April 17, 1978, pp. 93-95. As quoted in Kolata,
op. cit., p. 104. Back
to Text
- President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in
Medicine and Biomedical and Behavioral Research, Splicing
Life: A Report on the Social and Ethical Issues of Genetic Engineering
with Human Beings, November 1982. Back
to Text
- National Institutes of Health, Ad Hoc Group of Consultants to
the Advisory Committee to the Director, Report of the Human
Embryo Research Panel, September 1994, p. 28. Back
to Text
- Hearing before the Subcommittee on Public Health and Safety
of the Committee on Labor and Human Resources, United States Senate,
March 12, 1997. p. 22. Back
to Text
- See, for example, Kass, L., "The Wisdom of Repugnance," The
New Republic, June 2, 1997, pp. 17-26, and "Preventing a
Brave New World, The New Republic, May 21, 2001, pp.
30-39. Back
to Text
- Robertson, J.A., "A Ban on Cloning and Cloning Research Is Unjustified,"
testimony before the National Bioethics Advisory Commission, March
14, 1997. Macklin, R., testimony before NBAC, March 14, 1997.
Back
to Text
- NBAC, Cloning Human Beings, 1997, pp. ii-iii. Back
to Text
- Ibid, p. iii. Back
to Text
- Congressional Record, February 9, 1998, pp. S513-514.
Back
to Text
- Jaenisch, R., and I. Wilmut, "Don't clone humans!" Science
291: 5513, March 30, 2001. Back
to Text
- Saad, L. "Cloning Humans Is a Turn-Off to Most Americans" Gallup
Poll Analyses, May 16, 2002. Back
to Text
_____________________
- Homozygous segregant: an individual carrying two copies
of the same mutant gene, one inherited from each parent, and thus
destined to suffer from a genetic disease. Back
to Text
- On August 9, 2001, President Bush announced his new policy:
federal funding would be made available for research using only
those human embryonic stem cell lines that were already in existence
(that is, lines that had been derived prior to that date). Back
to Text
- As of June 2002 three states (Iowa, Michigan, and Virginia)
ban both cloning-to-produce-children and cloning-for-biomedical-research.
Two states (Louisiana and Rhode Island) ban cloning-to-produce-children,
but also have embryo-research laws that appear to prohibit cloning-for-biomedical-research.
One state (California) has banned cloning-to-produce-children,
until Dec. 31, 2002, but has no embryo-research law and thus effectively
permits cloning-for-biomedical-research. Back
to Text
Chapter Three
On Terminology
We begin our presentation of the important matter of terminology
by listing the crucial terms used in this report:
- Human cloning.
- Cloning-to-produce-children.
- Cloning-for-biomedical-research.
- Cloned human embryo.
The rest of this chapter will develop the meaning of these terms
and provide the analysis and argumentation that have led us to these
choices. Because there is much to be learned about the subject through
the discussion of alternative terminologies, and because we believe
strongly that the judicious use of language is necessary for sound
moral choice, we present our discussion of this matter at some length.
Introduction: The Importance of Careful Use of Names
Fruitful discussion of the ethical and policy issues raised by
the prospects of human cloning as with any other matter
can proceed only if we can find appropriate and agreed-upon terms
for describing the processes and products involved. Before we can
get to possible moral or policy arguments or disagreements, we need
to agree about what to call that about which we are arguing. As
a contribution to public understanding, we emphasize that this is
not an easy thing to do, and we indicate how and why we have gone
about making our terminological choices.
What exactly is meant by the term "cloning"? What criterion justifies
naming an entity a "clone"? How is the term "cloning" related to
what scientists call "somatic cell nuclear transfer (SCNT)" or "nuclear
transplantation"? What should we call the single-cell entity that
results from SCNT, and what should we call it once it starts to
divide and develop? How, if at all, should our names for such activities
or such entities be affected by the purposes we have for engaging
in the activities or for using the entities?
As these questions imply, there is much confusion today about the
terms used in discussing human cloning. There is honest disagreement
about what names should be used, and there are also attempts to
select and use terms in order to gain advantage for a particular
moral or policy position. One difficulty is the difference between
the perspective of science and the perspective of lived human experience.
People who look at the phenomena of human reproduction and development
through the lens of science will see and describe things in terms
that often differ widely from those in ordinary usage; moreover,
when an ordinary term is used in scientific parlance, it sometimes
is given a different meaning. Similar divergences are possible also
for people who look at these matters through the lens of different
cultural, philosophical, or religious beliefs. Yet at the same time,
all of us scientists or not, believers or not encounter
these same matters on the plane of lived human experience, for which
the terms of everyday speech may well be more suitable. Because
this same common (nonscientific) discourse is also the medium of
discourse for the ethical and policy discussions, we shall strive
to stay close to common speech, while at the same time making the
best use we can of scientific findings to avoid mistakes and misconceptions.
Advisers to decision makers should strive not only for accuracy,
but also for fairness, especially because the choice of names can
decisively affect the way questions are posed and, hence, how answers
are given. The issue is not a matter of semantics; it is a matter
of trying fairly to call things by names that correctly describe
them, of trying to fit speech to fact as best one can. For the sake
of clarity, we should at least stipulate clearly the meanings we
intend by our use of terms. But we should also try to choose terms
that most accurately convey the descriptive reality of the matter
at hand. If this is well done, the moral arguments can then proceed
on the merits, without distortion by linguistic sloppiness or chicanery.
Many of the terms that appear in the debate about cloning are confusing
or are used in a confused manner.
First, there are difficulties concerning the terms that seek to
name the activity or activities involved: cloning,
asexual reproduction, reproductive cloning, nonreproductive cloning,
research cloning, therapeutic cloning, somatic cell nuclear transfer
(or nuclear transplantation), nuclear transfer for stem cell research,
nuclear transplantation to produce stem cells, nuclear transfer
for regenerative medicine. At stake are such questions as whether
all acts of SCNT should be called cloning. Some worry that the term
"cloning" unfairly prejudices people against the activity when it
is used to describe research activities.
Second, there are difficulties concerning the terms that seek to
name the entity or entities that result from human
cloning (or human SCNT): cell, egg, activated cell, totipotent cell,
clonote, reconstituted (or reconstructed) egg, zygote, clump of
cells, embryo, human embryo, human organism, blastocyst, clonocyst,
potential human being, human being, human clone, person. At stake
here is the nature and the possible moral status
of the entities that are involved in the subsequent manipulations,
whether for producing a child or for use in biomedical research.
Some worry that use of any term but "embryo" will unfairly prejudice
people in favor of embryo-destructive activities by hiding from
view the full import of the activity.
Third, there are difficulties concerning the terms that seek to
describe the relation between the cloned entity and the
person whose somatic cell nucleus was transferred to produce the
cloned entity: genetic copy, replica, genetically virtually identical,
noncontemporary twin, delayed genetic twin, clone.
Tools of Analysis
As a prelude to examining the activity or the deed
of cloning, some general analytical observations will be helpful.
Although all aspects of an activity or action are relevant to understanding
its full human meaning, when describing a deed it is sometimes useful
to distinguish what it is from both how it is
done and why it is done. The act itself (what)
may be accomplished by a variety of means or techniques (how),
and it may be undertaken for a variety of motives or purposes (why).
To be sure, there is a danger of distortion in this disaggregating
analysis of human activity, and there is disagreement about the
degree to which the motives or purposes of the agent are to be reckoned
in the description of the act itself. People argue, for example,
whether "mercy killing" differs as an act from murdering
a rival (or executing a murderer or killing someone in self-defense),
or whether they are all equally acts of homicide (literally, "killing
a human being") whose moral meaning ("Is it justified or
not?" "Is it wrong or not?") we can then proceed to debate, if we
wish, by attending not only to the bare act of taking a human life
but also to the agent's motive and purpose. Though we do not wish
to beg this question, the very existence of this disagreement suggests
that we do well not to ignore the naked act itself, for it may have
a meaning independent of what moved the agent, a meaning relevant
to subsequent moral assessment that we do not wish to overlook.
To illustrate: in vitro fertilization (IVF: the merging of egg
and sperm outside the human body [in vitro = "in glass"],
yielding a zygote that is the beginning stage of a new living being)
is the deed (what). It is an act of "fertilization," of
making fertile, of making the egg cell ready and able to develop
into a human organism. This fertilization may be accomplished in
at least two ways (how): by merely mixing egg and sperm,
allowing the sperm to find and penetrate the egg, or by the technique
of injecting individual sperm directly into the egg (a technique
known as intracytoplasmic sperm injection, ICSI). And it may be
done for the (proximate) purpose (why) of initiating a
pregnancy, in turn for the (ultimate) purpose of providing a child
for an infertile couple; or it may be done for the (proximate) purpose
of providing living human embryos for basic research on normal and
abnormal embryological development, in turn for the (ultimate) purposes
of understanding human development or of discovering cures for diseases
and producing tissues for regenerative medicine. Though the technique
used or the purposes served may differ, in one crucial
respect the deed (IVF) remains the same and bears a common intrinsic
meaning: a human zygote, the first stage of a new human being,
is intentionally produced outside the body and exists in human hands
and subject to human manipulation.
As it happens, this fact is more or less accurately reflected in
the descriptive terminology used for IVF. Interestingly enough,
unlike the situation with cloning, no one distinguishes between
"reproductive IVF" and "therapeutic IVF" or "research IVF," naming
the activity or deed after the motive or purpose of the agent. This
may reflect the historical fact that IVF was initiated by people
who were interested in using it to produce live-born children for
infertile couples; the research use of "surplus" embryos produced
by IVF came only later. But it happens that this common name is
also descriptively apt and remains so regardless of why IVF was
done in a particular case: the deed is fertilization of
egg by sperm, producing a living human zygote, the first stage of
the development of a new human being.
It should be noted that, although we began by trying to describe
the deed rather than the product of the deed, the two aspects merged
necessarily. The meaning of the act of "fertilization" falls forward
onto the nature of the "object" that fertilization produces: the
fertilized egg or zygote or earliest embryo.i
(By contrast, there is nothing in the name of the technique "intracytoplasmic
sperm injection" that even hints at the immediate result or goal
of the intended injection.) Similar attention to the nature of the
product may turn out to be indispensable for a proper characterization
of the activity of cloning.
Cloning: Toward an Appropriate Terminology
Though much of the terminological confusion and controversy concerns
the way to describe the different kinds of cloning practices
that are envisioned, the term "cloning" itself is not without its
own ambiguities. A "clone" (noun, from the Greek klon,
"twig") refers to a group of genetically identical molecules,
cells, or organisms descended from a single common ancestor, as
well as to any one of the one or more individual organisms
that have descended asexually from a common ancestor. Both the group
and each of its members are "a clone." "To clone" (verb) is to duplicate
or produce a genetic duplicate or duplicates of a molecule, cell,
or individual organism. The replication of DNA fragments in the
laboratory is called "DNA cloning." The physical isolation of a
single cell and its subsequent multiplication in tissue culture
into a population of descendants is referred to as "single cell
cloning." The laboratory culture of bacteria and the asexual propagation
of plants by means of cuttings are instances of organismal cloning.
Cloning of higher organisms is more complex: all cloning of vertebrate
organisms must begin at the embryonic stages. Contrary to what some
people imagine, cloning of amphibians or mammals (including human
beings) is not the direct duplication ("photocopying") of an adult
organism.
In the sense relevant here, "cloning" is a form of asexual reproduction
(parthenogenesisii
is another), the production of a new individual not by the chance
union of egg and sperm but by some form of replication of the genetic
makeup of a single existing or previously existing individual. (In
biological or functional terms, the core of sexual reproduction
is not bodily intercourse but the fusion of male and female germ
cells; thus IVF, though it takes place outside the body, is
biologically speaking a form of sexual reproduction.)
Cloning is the activity of producing a clone, an individual or group
of individuals genetically virtually identical to the precursor
that is being "replicated."iii
Cloning-to-Produce-Children; Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research
In much of the current public discussion, we encounter a distinction
between two sorts of cloning: "reproductive" and "therapeutic."
The distinction is based entirely on the differing goals of the
cloners: in the first case, the goal is the production of a (cloned)
child; in the second case, the development of treatments for diseases
(suffered not by the clone, but by others). We recognize the distinction
and the need for terms to describe the difference. But the terms
currently in vogue have their difficulties. Both terms have been
criticized by partisans of several sides of the debate, and for
understandable reasons.
Some object to the term "reproductive cloning" used as a term of
distinction, because they argue that all cloning is reproductive.
Their reason: all human cloning intends and issues in the production
of a cloned human embryo, a being distinct from the components used
to generate it, a new human being in the earliest stage of development
or "reproduction." (This claim, we would suggest, is at this stage
a descriptive point, not yet a normative one; it does not necessarily
imply that such a being is fully human or "one of us," hence deserving
of the moral and social protection accorded "persons.") The
fact that only some of these embryonic cloned humans are wanted
for baby-producing purposes does not, in the view of these critics,
alter this fact about their being. In support of their claim that
cloning occurs (only) at the beginning, they note that once the
cloning act of nuclear transfer has occurred, all new influences
that act upon the new human organism cease to be "genetic" (nature)
and are now "environmental" (nurture). Instead of "reproductive
cloning," we shall speak of "cloning-to-produce-children."
Others object to the term "therapeutic cloning" for related reasons.
The act of cloning embryos may be undertaken with healing motives.
But it is not itself an act of healing or therapy.iv
The beneficiaries of any such acts of cloning are, at the moment,
hypothetical and in the future. And if medical treatments do eventually
result, the embryonic clone from which the treatment was derived
will not itself be the beneficiary of any therapy. On the contrary,
this sort of cloning actually takes apart (or destroys) the embryonic
being that results from the act of cloning.
To avoid the misleading implications of calling any cloning "therapeutic,"
we prefer the terms "research cloning" or "cloning for research,"
which also more accurately indicate the purpose of the activity.
Yet some may find fault with this replacement. Because it appears
to be a deliberate substitution for "therapeutic cloning," it may
seem to imply that the scientists have abandoned the pursuit of
medical cure in favor of research as an end in itself. Believing
that producing cloned embryos just for research would seem to be
less justifiable than producing them with healing motives, these
critics of the term "research cloning" want to avoid giving the
impression that scientists want to experiment on new life just to
satisfy their curiosity. We believe that this legitimate concern
can be addressed by appending the adjective "biomedical" to make
clear that the aim of the research is to seek cures and treatments
for human diseases. We therefore opt to use the term "cloning-for-biomedical-research."
Some proponents of the activity called "therapeutic cloning" also
now object to the term, but not because of the adjective. Though
it was proponents who originally coined and used the term, some
of them now want to shed the term "cloning," fearing that the bad
or distressing connotations of the latter will weigh against the
activity itself. Cloning, they insist, should be reserved for the
activity that produces live-born cloned babies; it should not apply
to the initial act that starts the process, which they would rather
call "somatic cell nuclear transfer" or "nuclear transplantation."1
The reason for such redescription is not wholly cosmetic and rhetorical;
because the researchers are primarily interested in obtaining pluripotentv
stem cells, their focus is on the somatic cell nucleus and what
must be done to it (transfer or transplantation) in order for it
to revert to the undifferentiated condition of the primordial stem
cell stage. Nevertheless, such terminological substitution is problematic,
for the following reasons.
Although as a scientific matter "somatic cell nuclear transfer"
or "nuclear transplantation" may accurately describe the technique
that is used to produce the embryonic clone, these terms fail to
convey the nature of the deed itself, and they hide its human significance.
The deed, fully described, is the production of a living human entity
(or "embryo" or "organism"; of the right name for the product, more
later) that is genetically virtually identical to the donor organism,
a fact or meaning not captured in the name for the technique or
method, the transfer of a somatic cell nucleus (into an unfertilized
egg whose own nucleus has been removed or inactivated).vi
As a name, SCNT is not a fully accurate description even of the
technique itself. It makes no reference to the intended and direct
result of the deed of nuclear transfer. It also omits mention of
the fact that the recipient of the transferred nucleus is an (enucleated)
egg cell (rather than another kind of cell), which then
can be made to initiate cell division as if it were just like a
zygote produced by fertilization. The further amendments, "somatic
cell nuclear transfer for stem cell research" or "nuclear
transplantation for regenerative medicine" or "nuclear
transplantation to produce stem cells" only compound the
difficulty, mixing in the purpose of the activity with its technique,
thus further obscuring the immediate meaning of the act itself,
the production of a living cloned human embryo.
Cloned Human Embryo: The Product of SCNT
What shall we call the product of SCNT? The technical description
of the cloning method (that is, SCNT) omits all reference not only
to cloning but also to the immediate product of the activity. This
obscurity enables some to argue that the immediate product
of SCNT is not an "embryo" but rather "an egg" or "an unfertilized
egg" or "an activated cell," and that the subsequent stages of development
should not be called embryos but "clumps of cells" or "activated
cells." To be sure, there are genuine difficulties and perplexities
regarding what names to use, for we are dealing with an entity new
in our experience. Partly for this reason, some people recommend
avoiding the effort to describe the nature of the product, preferring
instead to allow the uses we human beings have for it to
define its being, and hence its worth. But, for reasons of both
truth and ethical conduct, we reject this approach as improper.
We are all too familiar with instances in which some human beings
have defined downward the status of other beings precisely to exploit
them with impunity and with a clear conscience. Thus, despite the
acknowledged difficulties in coming to know it accurately, we insist
on making the effort to describe the product of SCNT as accurately
and as fairly as we can.
The initial product of SCNT is a single cell, but it is no ordinary
cell. It is also an "egg" and a "reconstituted egg." But even that
is not the whole story. The "reconstituted" egg is more
than reconstituted; it has been capacitated for development. Because
the egg now has a diploid nucleus, it has become something beyond
what it was before: it now contains in a single nucleus the full
complement of genetic material necessary for producing a new organism.
vii
And being an egg cell, it uniquely offers the cytoplasmic
environment that can support this development. The product of SCNT
thus resembles and can be made to act like a fertilized egg, a cell
that not only has the full complement of chromosomes but also is
capable (in animals) or may be capable (in humans) of developing
into a new organism. In other words, in terms of its future prospects,
it is a "zygote-like entity" or a (cloned) "zygote equivalent."
vii
The initial product of SCNT is, to be sure, not just a cell but
an active cell. (More precisely, it is a cell that can
be activated by electric stimulation.) But "activated cell" is much
too vague to describe the activity of which it is capable. For,
once stimulated, the activity of this "cell" produced by SCNT is
nothing other than human embryological development, initiated and
directed by the cell itself. The processes of cellular growth, chromosomal
replication, cell division, and (ultimately) differentiation into
the tissues and organs of the organism are coordinated processes
under the governance of the immanent developmental plan encoded
in the cell's genetic material. In other words, the product of SCNT
is an organism in its germinal stage, and its activities are those
of an integrated and self-developing whole.ix
Another suggested name, better than "activated cell," is "totipotent
cell" a cell that is "capable of all." But this too is ambiguous.
If what is meant is that it can (and will, should it be stimulated
to do so) become "any and all" of the different kinds of cells in
the body, then it is an insufficient meaning. For, as explained
in the previous paragraph, this totipotent cell may also
become the "all" that is the integrated whole (cloned)
mature organism itself (along with a portion of the placenta that
would give it nourishment). In this second and fuller meaning of
"totipotent," a totipotent cell is then just a functional
synonym for the "zygote": "zygote" etymologically reminds one of
the cell's origins in egg-joined-to-sperm; "totipotency" describes
what it is capable of. A fertilized egg is precisely a "totipotent"
cell; the product of human SCNT is, we assume, its equivalent.
In some discussions, the next few stages of the developing cloned
human entity have been described as "clumps of cells." Yet, for
reasons already given, this is only partially accurate. Viewed externally,
under the microscope, the developing embryo will appear as two,
then four, then eight cells "clumped" together, and the 100-to-200-cell
blastocyst stage will indeed appear as a "ball of cells." Yet there
is more here than meets the eye, for the "clump" is governed by
an internal principle of development that shapes and directs its
transformations. Thus, this ball or clump is not a mere heap or
aggregate; it is a primordial and unfolding whole that functions
as a whole and that is in the process of developing (or attempting
to develop) into a mature whole being. Of course, if development
is not pursued or not allowed to happen because of disruption, then
the "clump of cells" description may be rendered accurate not just
microscopically but also biologically. But as long as development
continues and the developing entity is intact, that is not the case.
It would seem, then, that whatever the reason for producing
it the initial product of somatic cell nuclear transfer is
a living (one-celled) cloned human embryo. The immediate
intention of transferring the nucleus is precisely to produce just
such an entity: one that is alive (rather than nonliving), one that
is human (rather than nonhuman or animal), and one that is an embryo,
an entity capable of developing into an articulated organismic whole
(rather than just a somatic cell capable only of replication into
more of the same cell type). This is the intended primary product
of performing SCNT, whether the ultimate motive or purpose is producing
a live-born child from the cloned embryo or conducting scientific
research on the cloned embryo. Also, the blastocyst stage that develops
from this one-celled cloned embryo will be the same being, whether
it is then transferred to a woman's uterus to begin a pregnancy
or is used as a source of stem cells for research and possible therapy
for others.
Yet, not surprisingly, objections have been raised to calling this
cloned entity an "embryo," objections having to do both with its
origins and with the uncertainty about the extent of its developmental
potential. There are also objections having to do not with the facts
but with public connotations and perceptions: for some members of
the public, the word "embryos" apparently conjures images of miniature
babies. If "nuclear transplantation to produce stem cells" seems
to some people to be unfairly morally neutered terminology,
"embryo" seems to other people to be unfairly morally loaded
terminology, especially when used to describe an entity barely visible
to the naked eye. We acknowledge this problem and recognize that,
despite our best efforts, such difficulties in public perception
probably cannot be simply corrected. But we do not regard this as
sufficient reason to scrap the use of a term if it is in fact most
appropriate. The other objections to calling the product of SCNT
an "embryo" are not about rhetoric and politics, but about the thing
itself. They should be addressed.
First, "human embryo," in the traditional scientific definition
of this term, refers to the earliest stages of human development,
from the zygote through roughly eight weeks of gestation, after
which time it is called a fetus. Because the product of SCNT is
technically not a zygote, not having come from egg and sperm, it
is argued that it cannot therefore be an embryo. Second, it is said
that it cannot be an embryo because it is an "artifact," something
produced entirely by human artifice, "made" rather than "begotten."
Third, we do not yet know for sure whether this entity can in fact
develop into a baby; hence, we do not know whether it has
the full developmental potential of a human embryo formed by fertilization.
There are, however, good responses to these objections. The first
product of SCNT is, on good biological grounds, quite properly regarded
as the equivalent of a zygote, and its subsequent stages
as embryonic stages in development. True, it is not technically
"zygotic" in origin, and it owes its existence to human artifice.
But these objections, dealing only with origins, ignore
the organization and powers of this entity, and the crucially important
fact of its capacity to undergo future embryological development
just like a sexually produced embryo. True, it originates
as a result of human artifice, and it lacks the natural bi-parental
(male-plus-female) precursors. But this particular "artifact" is
alive and self-developing, and should it eventually give rise to
a baby, that child would in its being and its capacities be indistinguishable
from any other human being hardly an artifact in the
same way that Dolly is a sheep. True, regarding its developmental
potential, we do not yet have incontrovertible proof that a cloned
human embryo can in fact do what embryos are "supposed" to do and
what animal cloned embryos have already done, namely, develop into
all the later stages of the organism, up to its full maturity (à
la Dolly). But if we do not assume this last possibility an
assumption based on the biological continuity of all mammalsx
there would be nothing to talk about in this whole matter
of human cloning. As we emphasized in the first chapter of this
report, this entire inquiry assumes that cloned human embryos
can someday be developed into live-born human beings.
Once we make this assumption, neither its artificial nor its uni-parental
source alters the decisive point: the product of SCNT is an entity
that is the first stage of a developing organism of a determinate
species (human), with a full genetic complement, and its own (albeit
near-replicated) individual genetic identity. It hence deserves on
functional grounds to be called an embryo. And that
is the heart of the reason why we in this report shall call it an
"embryo" (actually, for reasons soon to be discussed, a "cloned
embryo"): because the decisive questions to be addressed in our moral
reflections have to do not with the origin of the entity but with
its developmental potential, its embryonic character must
be kept centrally in mind.
This decision, based on what we believe comes closest to the truth
about the product of SCNT, is supported by other, more practical
considerations. We are disinclined to introduce other words to describe
the early product of human cloning that might deprive discussion
of the ethics of human cloning of its humanly significant context.
Despite the novelty of cloning and its products, their considerable
kinship to elements of normal reproduction and development means
that we enter upon the discussion equipped with existing and relevant
terms and notions. We do not start in a terminological vacuum or
with an empty dictionary. We observe that even people who prefer
not to call the one-celled product of SCNT a zygote or embryo use
terms like "blastocyst" and "embryo" to name the product a few cell
divisions later.xi
We think that using or coining other words will be more confusing
to members of the public as they try to follow and contribute to
the ethical discussion. And we clearly assume, as already stated,
that the product of human SCNT could someday be shown to be capable
of developing into a later-stage embryo, fetus, or live human being,
even though such capacity has yet to be documented.
There are also very important ethical reasons that support
our choice. We want to be very careful not to make matters easy
for ourselves. We do not want to define away the moral questions
of cloning-for-biomedical-research by denying to the morally crucial
element a name that makes clear that there is a moral question to
be faced. Yes, there is some ground for uncertainty about the being
of the product of SCNT. Yet because something is ambiguous to us
does not mean that it is ambiguous in itself. Where the
moral stakes are high, we should not allow our uncertainty to lead
us to regard the subject in question as being anything less than
it might truly be.
The product of "SCNT" is not only an embryo; it is also a clone,
genetically virtually identical to the individual that was the source
of the transferred nucleus, hence an embryonic clone of the donor.
There is, to be sure, much discussion about how close the genetic
relation is between donor and embryonic clone, and about the phenotypic
similarity of the clone to the donor. xii
Yet the goal in this process is in fact a blastocyst-stage cloned
embryo (in the case of cloning-for-biomedical-research) or a child
who is genetically virtually identical to the donor (in the case
of cloning-to-produce-children); otherwise there would be no reason
to produce a cloned embryo by SCNT rather than an (uncloned) embryo
by ordinary IVF. A full and fitting name of the developing entity
produced by human SCNT is "cloned human embryo," a term that also
allows us to remember that, thanks to its peculiar origins, this
embryo is not in all respects identical to an embryo produced by
fertilization of egg by sperm.
As if things were not difficult enough, a further complication
may soon arise, following reports of successful SCNT experiments
in which human somatic cells were fused with animal oocytes,
and the resulting product grown to the blastocyst stage of development.
What are we to call the product of this kind of cloning? And what
kind of species identity does it have? According to the advance
reports (based on a presentation at a scientific meeting), the stem
cells extracted from the blastocyst stage were demonstrated to be
human stem cells (somewhat surprisingly, the mitochondria were also
human in genotype). Is this, therefore, a cloned human embryo? The
only test that could settle the question implantation into
a woman's uterus for attempted gestation to see if a human child
results cannot ethically even be contemplated without already
assuming a positive answer. In the face of uncertainty, therefore,
and lest we err by overconfidence, there is prima facie
reason to include even these cross-species entities in the category
of "cloned human embryos." (When we come to the ethical issues of
cloning-for-biomedical-research, we can consider whether this terminological
judgment is matched by an ethical one.)
Conclusion
None of the terms available to us is entirely trouble-free. Yet
the foregoing analysis leads us to the following conclusion regarding
the terms best descriptive of the facts of the matter:
Human cloning (what it is): The asexual production of
a new human organism that is, at all stages of development, genetically
virtually identical to a currently existing or previously existing
human being.
Human cloning (how it is done): It would be accomplished
by introducing the nuclear material of a human somatic cell (donor)
into an oocyte (egg) whose own nucleus has been removed or inactivated,
yielding a product that has a human genetic constitution virtually
identical to the donor of the somatic cell. This procedure is known
as "somatic cell nuclear transfer" (SCNT).
Human cloning (why it is done): This same activity may
be undertaken for purposes of producing children or for purposes
of scientific and medical investigation and use, a distinction represented
in the popular discussion by the terms "reproductive cloning" and
"therapeutic cloning." We have chosen instead to use the following
designations:
Cloning-to-produce-children: Production of a cloned human
embryo, formed for the (proximate) purpose of initiating a pregnancy,
with the (ultimate) goal of producing a child who will be genetically
virtually identical to a currently existing or previously existing
individual.
Cloning-for-biomedical-research: Production of a cloned
human embryo, formed for the (proximate) purpose of using it in
research or for extracting its stem cells, with the (ultimate) goals
of gaining scientific knowledge of normal and abnormal development
and of developing cures for human diseases.
Cloned human embryo: (a) The immediate and developing
product of the initial act of cloning, accomplished by SCNT. (b)
A human embryo resulting from the somatic cell nuclear transfer
process (as contrasted with a human embryo arising from the union
of egg and sperm).
ENDNOTES
- Vogelstein, B., et al., "Please don't call it cloning!" Science,
295: 1237, 2002. Back
to Text
- Leggett, K. and A. Regalado, "China Stem Cell Research Surges
as Western Nations Ponder Ethics" Wall Street Journal, March 6,
2002, p. A1. Back
to Text
_____________________
- A more careful analysis of the what of this activity
would distinguish between the activity itself and the product
that results from it. Unlike nonproductive activities, such as
dancing ("How can we know the dancer from the dance?"), the work
(activity) of making or producing results in separable objects
or works (products). Although shoemaking completes itself in the
production of a shoe, the shoe as result is distinct
from the activity of shoemaking. Similarly, though fertilization
is an activity that is intelligible only as issuing in a fertilized
egg, the now-fertile egg as result or product
stands apart from the deed of IVF. One reason that the word "fertilization"
works so well in describing IVF is that it is a very rich term,
pointing both to cause and effect, backward to the deed and forward
to the future prospects of the product. Back
to Text
- Parthenogenesis (see Glossary of Terms), the development of
an organism directly from an unfertilized egg that has been artificially
induced to undergo development, is, in principle, another method
of asexual reproduction. Although parthenogenetic reproduction
has been successfully achieved in amphibians, in mammalian species
there are as yet no reports of live births following parthenogenesis.
Thus, there is at present little reason to believe that live-born
human beings can be produced via parthenogenesis. It is therefore
not the subject of this report, although many of the things said
about cloning via somatic cell nuclear transfer would be applicable
to asexual reproduction through parthenogenesis. Back
to Text
- Although cloning, like fertilization, is responsible for bringing
forth a new organism, the activities are named in very different
ways, yet in each case emphasizing the fundamental intention of
the activity. "Fertilization" describes the activity in terms
of the capacitation of the egg, as a result of which development
begins. "Cloning" describes the activity in terms of the relation
between the progenitor and the product. In cloning by
somatic cell nuclear transfer,the egg, though it is activated
as if it were fertilized, is not cloned; cloned rather is the
donor from whom the nucleus was taken, and the resulting organism
(at all stages of development) is a clone of the donor. The name
of the activity, "cloning," even more than "in vitro fertilization,"
refers to the product of the activity, an identical (or
nearly identical) entity. Back
to Text
- Compare, in this respect, what used to be called "therapeutic
abortion," an abortion undertaken in cases in which pregnancy
threatened the life of the pregnant woman and where abortion was
therefore intended to save the woman's life. Similarly, we might
call the removal of a cancerous kidney a "therapeutic nephrectomy";
we would never use the term to refer to the removal of a kidney
for donation to another person in transplantation. Back
to Text
- Pluripotent cells are those that can give rise to many different
types of differentiated cells. See Glossary of Terms. Back
to Text
- This reduction of an act to its mechanism is roughly analogous
to describing walking as "sequential alternate leg advancement"
(SALA). Back
to Text
- The original egg had a haploid nucleus, containing only half
the chromosomes necessary for development. The diploid nucleus
contains the full amount. See Chapter
Four. Back
to Text
- Technically, the term "zygote" (from a Greek root meaning "yoke")
refers to the primordial cell that forms from the union of egg
and sperm and the fusion (the yoking together) of their nuclei
as the first step in the development of a new life that has come
from the joining of its two parents. It is for this reason technically
inappropriate to call the product of an asexual initiation a "zygote,"
though it may be its functional equivalent. The term "clonote"
has been suggested as the strict analogue of "zygote," identifying
the primordial cell formed in cloning by its special origin: just
as a zygote arises from the "yoking together" of two
elements, so a "clonote" arises from the act of clonal propagation
from a single, already existing organism. (Similarly,
the term "parthenote" for the primary product of parthenogenesis
would accurately indicate that it arises from the "virgin" [unfertilized]
egg alone; parthenos, Greek for "virgin.") The term "clonote"
also has the merit of carrying the clonal character of the entity
in its name. Back
to Text
- For the reasons given in this paragraph, we reject the suggestion
that the immediate product of SCNT and the cells it gives rise
to should be considered "cells in tissue culture." Unlike somatic
cells grown in laboratory culture, the immediate product of SCNT,
although (like cultured tissues) it grows in culture media outside
the body, is the germ of a new organism, not merely of
other cells just like itself. Back
to Text
- A recent press report indicates that as-yet-unpublished work
in China by Sheng Huizhen involved insertion of human somatic
cell nuclei into enucleated rabbit eggs, and that the resulting
cloned embryos developed to a stage where human embryonic stem
cells could be isolated.2
And, of course, in other mammals the product of SCNT has been
grown all the way to live-born young that grow up to be able to
produce young of their own. Back
to Text
- Thus, for example, the report on Scientific and Medical
Aspects of Human Reproductive Cloning, released by the National
Academy of Sciences in January 2002, describes "nuclear transplantation
to produce stem cells" as "a very different procedure" from what
it calls "human reproductive cloning." Nevertheless, the report
falls quite naturally into our normal way of speaking, a way that
recognizes that the cloned product is, indeed, a human embryo
and that any stem cells obtained from it would be embryonic
stem cells. Thus, for example, the authors of the report can write
a sentence such as the following (p. 2-6): "The experimental procedures
required to produce stem cells through nuclear transplantation
would consist of the transfer of a somatic cell nucleus from a
patient into an enucleated egg, the in vitro culture of the embryo
to the blastocyst stage, and the derivation of a pluripotent ES
cell line from the inner cell mass of this blastocyst." Other
scientists clearly insist that the primary product of SCNT is
an embryo (see, for example, Dr. John Gearhart's presentation
to the Council on embryonic stem cells, April 25, 2002; transcript
on the Council's website, www.bioethics.gov). Back
to Text
- The environment in which the donor came to be and lives surely
differs from the one in which the cloned embryo may develop (if
it does develop). There may be imprinting or epigenetic reprogramming
differences in gene expression early on that may affect the physical
and mental characteristics of the clone. There is also the matter
of the mitochondrial genes (see Glossary of Terms), a small number
of protein-producing genes out of a total of some 30,000 to 60,000,
which are inherited from the female source of the egg (the clone
would be genetically identical only in those cases in which the
same woman donated both egg and somatic cell nucleus, to produce
an embryonic clone of herself). Back
to Text
Chapter Four
Scientific Background
Introduction
The purpose of this chapter is to provide
background on basic scientific aspects of human cloning for readers
of this report. Background on stem cell research is also included
to enable readers to understand how cloned embryos might be useful
in stem cell and other biomedical research. This limited treatment
only summarizes and highlights basic aspects of these topics, in part
because two major detailed reports, Scientific and Medical Aspects
of Human Reproductive Cloning1
and Stem Cells and the Future of Regenerative Medicine,2
have been recently published.
This review is based largely on scientific research papers published
through June 2002, supplemented by references to several articles
in the popular press. However, the research areas of cloning and
stem cell research are being very actively investigated, and significant
new developments are published frequently. Publication of new results
could change some of the interpretations and emphases in this review.
Use of unfamiliar technical terms has been avoided wherever possible.
Scientific names and terms used are described and defined in the
Glossary of Terms.
Some Basic Facts about Human Cell Biology and Sexual Reproduction
We begin with some basic facts about human cells, germ cells (egg
and sperm), and early embryonic development to provide the background
for understanding the mechanism of cloning and the differences between
sexual and asexual reproduction.
Normal human cells with nuclei contain forty-six chromosomes, twenty-two
pairs plus two X chromosomes if the individual is female, or twenty-two
pairs plus one X and one Y chromosome if the individual is male.
These chromosomes contain nearly all of the cell's DNA and, therefore,
the genes of the cell. During formation of sperm cells, a process
of specialized cell division produces mature sperm cells containing
twenty-three chromosomes (twenty-two unpaired chromosomes plus either
X or Y). During the formation of eggs (oocytes), a process of specialized
cell division produces a cell containing two pronuclei, each of
which contains twenty-two unpaired chromosomes plus an X. During
fertilization, a polar body containing one of these pronuclei is
ejected from the egg.
Fusion of egg and sperm cells and the subsequent fusion of their
nuclei (the defining acts of all sexual reproduction) produce a
zygote that again contains a nucleus with the adult cell complement
of forty-six chromosomes, half from each parent [See Figure 1].
The zygote then begins the gradual process of cell division, growth,
and differentiation. After four to five days, the developing embryo
attains the 100-200 cell (blastocyst) stage. In normal reproduction,
the blastocyst implants into the wall of the uterus, where, suitably
nourished, it continues the process of coordinated cell, tissue,
and organ differentiation that eventually produces the organized,
articulated, and integrated whole that is the newborn infant. According
to some estimates, about half of all early human embryos fail to
implant, and are expelled with the menses during the next menstrual
cycle.
Not quite all the DNA of a human cell resides in its nucleus. All
human cells, including eggs and sperm, contain small, energy-producing
organelles called mitochondria. Mitochondria contain a small piece
of DNA that specifies the genetic instructions for making several
essential mitochondrial proteins. When additional mitochondria are
produced in the cell, the mitochondrial DNA is replicated, and a
copy of it is passed along to the new mitochondria that are formed.
During fertilization, sperm mitochondria are selectively degraded
inside the zygote. Thus, the developing embryo inherits solely or
principally mitochondria (and mitochondrial DNA) from the egg.
Human reproduction has also been accomplished with the help of
in vitro fertilization (IVF) of eggs by sperm, and the subsequent
transfer of one or more early embryos to a woman for gestation and
birth. Even though such union of egg and sperm requires laboratory
assistance and takes place outside of the body, human reproduction
using IVF is still sexual in the biological sense: the new human
being arises from two biological parents through the union of egg
and sperm.
Egg and sperm cells combined in vitro have also been used to start
the process of animal development. Transfer of the resulting blastocysts
into the uterus of a female of the appropriate animal species is
widely used in animal husbandry with resulting successful live births.
Cloning (Asexual Reproduction) of Mammals
The startling announcement that Dolly the sheep had been produced
by cloning3
indicated that it was possible to produce live mammalian offspring
via asexual reproduction through cloning with adult donor cell nuclei.i
In outline form, the steps used to produce live offspring in the
mammalian species that have been cloned so far are:
- Obtain an egg cell from a female of a mammalian species.
- Remove the nuclear DNA from the egg cell, to produce an enucleated
egg.
- Insert the nucleus of a donor adult cell into the enucleated
egg, to produce a reconstructed egg.
- Activate the reconstructed egg with chemicals or electric current,
to stimulate the reconstructed egg to commence cell division.
- Sustain development of the cloned embryo to a suitable stage
in vitro, and then transfer the resulting cloned embryo to the
uterus of a female host that has been suitably prepared to receive
it.
- Bring to live birth a cloned animal that is genetically virtually
identical (except for the mitochondrial DNA) to the animal that
donated the adult cell nucleus.
Cloning to produce live offspring carries with it several possibilities
not available through sexual reproduction. Because the number of
presumably identical donor cells is very large, this process could
produce a very large number of genetically virtually identical individuals,
limited only by the supply of eggs and female animals that could
bear the young. In principle, any animal, male or female, newborn
or adult, could be cloned, and in any quantity. Because mammalian
cells can be frozen and stored for prolonged periods at low temperature
and grown again for use as donor cells in cloning, one may even
clone individuals who have died. In theory, a clone could be cloned
again, on and on, without limit. In mice, such "cloning of clones"
has extended out to six generations.4
Figure 1: Diagram of early stages of human fertilization,
cloning, and parthenogenesis.
[Modified from Rick Weiss and Patterson Clark, The Washington
Post.]
Since the report of the birth of Dolly the cloned sheep, attempts
have been made to clone at least nine other mammalian species. As
summarized in Table 1, live offspring have been produced in a low
percentage of cloned embryo transfer experiments with sheep, cattle,
goats, mice, pigs, cats5
and rabbits.6
According to a press report,7
attempts to clone rats, dogs, and primates using adult cell
DNA have not yet yielded live offspring. In experiments to clone
different mammalian species, many of the transferred cloned embryos
fail to develop normally and abort spontaneously in utero. In addition,
a variety of health problems have been reported in many of the cloned
animals that survived to live birth.8
However, some surviving cloned cattle appear physiologically similar
to their uncloned counterparts, and two cloned cows have given birth
to their own offspring.
9,10
Why is production of live cloned mammalian
offspring a relatively rare event? Several factors may play a role.
Enucleation of the egg may (variably from one attempt to the next)
remove or damage its "epigenetic reprogramming" (see Glossary of Terms)
capabilities. Isolating a nucleus from the donor cell and manipulating
it to insert it into the egg is also a traumatic process that may
damage the nucleus. An optimal in vitro nutritive environment for
the development of cloned animal embryos may not yet have been determined.
One interpretation11
attributes the early death of many cloned embryos to complete failure
or incompleteness of epigenetic reprogramming.
Epigenetic Modification and Reprogramming
Normal mammalian embryonic development results from selective expression
of some genes and repression of others. Tissue differentiation depends
upon several types of "epigenetic modifications" (see Glossary of
Terms) of DNA structure and spatial organization that selectively
turn genes on and off. The chromosomal DNAs of egg and sperm cells
are modified during their maturation, so that at fertilization,
both sets of DNA are ready for the complex pattern of gene expression
required for normal embryonic development. In order for the DNA
of a differentiated adult cell to direct embryonic development
in cloning, it must be "epigenetically reprogrammed." That is, the
epigenetic modifications that allowed the cell to express genes
appropriate for, for example, a differentiated skin cell must be
reduced, and the gene expression program required for full embryonic
development must be activated.
TABLE 1. SOME COMPARATIVE DATA ON LIVE BIRTHS FROM CLONING
OF ANIMALS
[For a more cmplete collection of data, see the NAS Report Scientific
and Medical Aspects of Human Cloning] |
Animal Species
|
Donor Cell
|
Number of Cloned Embryos Transferred
|
Number of Live Births
|
Live Births per Embryo Transfer
|
Reference
|
Sheep |
udder cells (frozen) |
29 |
1 |
3.4% |
1 |
Cattle |
fetal fibroblasts
cumullus & oviduct cells |
496
10 |
24-30#
4-8* |
4.8-6%
40-80% |
2a
2b |
Mice |
cumulus cells |
2468 |
31** |
1.3% |
3 |
Goats |
transgenic fetal fibroblasts
fetal fibroblasts
transgenic fetal fibroblasts |
97
85
184 |
5
3
5 |
5.2%
3.5%
2.7% |
4a
4b
4c |
Pigs |
fetal fibroblasts |
110
335 |
1
5 |
0.9%
1.5% |
5a
5b |
Cats |
cumulus cells |
87 |
1 |
1.1% |
6 |
Rabbits |
cumulus cells |
371 |
6 |
1.6% |
7 |
References:
1. Wilmut, I., et al., Nature, 385: 264-267 (1997)
2a. Cibelli, J.B., et al., Science, 280: 1256-1258 (1998)
2b. Kato, Y., et al., Science, 282: 2095-2098 (1998)
3. Wakayama, T., et al., Nature, 394: 369-374 (1998)
4a. Baguisi, A., et al., Nature Biotechnology, 17: 456-461 (1999)
4b. Keefer, C.L., et al., Biol Reprod, 64: 849-856 (2001)
4c. Reggio, B.C., et al., Biol Reprod, 65: 1528-33 (2001)
5a. Onishi, A., et al., Science, 289: 1188-90 (2000)
5b. Polejaeva, I.A., et al., Nature, 407: 86-90 (2000)
6. Shin, T., et al., Nature, 415: 859 (2002)
7. Chesne, P., et al., Nature Biotechnology, 20: 366-369 (2002)
# Six animals died shortly after birth; * four animals died
shortly after birth;
** 20 animals died at a young age [Ogonuki, N.K., et al., Nature
Genetics, 30: 253-4 (2002)]. |
During cloning, cytoplasmic factors in the egg cell reprogram the
chromosomal DNA of the somatic cell. In rare cases, this reprogramming
is sufficient to enable embryonic development to proceed all the
way to the birth of a live animal (for examples, see Table 1). In
many cloning experiments, epigenetic reprogramming probably fails
or is abnormal, and the developing animal dies. Incomplete epigenetic
reprogramming could also explain why some live-born cloned animals
suffer from subtle defects that sometimes do not appear for years.
12
The completeness of epigenetic reprogramming is crucial for successful
cloning-to-produce-children. It will also be important to assess
the impact of variation in epigenetic reprogramming on the biological
properties of cloned stem cell preparations. If the extent of epigenetic
reprogramming varies from one cloning event to the next, the protein
expression pattern and thus the biological properties of cloned
stem cell preparations may also vary. Thus, it may be necessary
to produce and test multiple cloned stem cell preparations before
preparations that are informative about human disease or useful
in cellular transplantation therapies can be identified.
Cloning-to-Produce-Children
At this writing, it is uncertain whether anyone has attempted cloning-to-produce-children.
Although claims of such attempts have been reported in the press,13,14
no credible evidence of any such experiments has been reported as
of June 2002. Thus, it is not yet known whether a transferred cloned
human embryo can progress all the way to live birth. However, the
steps in such an experiment would probably be similar to those described
for animal cloning [see above and references to Table 1]. After
a thorough review of the data on animal cloning, the NAS panel,
in its report Scientific and Medical Aspects of Human Cloning
[page ES-1], came to the following conclusion: "It [cloning-to-produce-children]
is dangerous and likely to fail."
Stem Cells and Regenerative Medicine
The subject of stem cell research is much too large to be covered
extensively here. Yet the following information on stem cells and
their possible uses in medical treatments should facilitate understanding
of the relationships between cloning-for-biomedical-research and
stem cells (see also the reports Scientific and Medical Aspects
of Human Reproductive Cloning and Stem Cells and the Future of Regenerative
Medicine).
Stem cells are undifferentiated multipotent precursor cells that
are capable both of perpetuating themselves as stem cells and of
undergoing differentiation into one or more specialized types of
cells (for example, kidney, muscle). Human embryonic stem cells
have been isolated from embryos at the blastocyst stage15
or from the germinal tissue of fetuses.16
Multipotent adult progenitor cells have been isolated from sources
such as human17
and rodent18
bone marrow. Such cell populations can be differentiated in vitro
into a number of different cell types, and thus are the subject
of much current research into their possible uses in regenerative
medicine. Cloned human embryonic stem cell preparations could be
produced using somatic cell nuclear transfer to produce a cloned
human embryo, and then taking it apart at the (100-200 cell) blastocyst
stage and isolating stem cells (see Figure 2). These stem cells
would be genetically virtually identical to cells from the nucleus
donor.
Scientists are pursuing the development of therapies based on transplantation
of cells for several human diseases, including Parkinson's disease
and Type I diabetes. In Parkinson's disease, particular brain cells
that produce the essential neurotransmitter dopamine die selectively.
Experimental clinical treatment involving transplantation of human
fetal brain cell populations, in which a small fraction
of the cells produce dopamine, has improved the condition of some
Parkinson's disease patients.19
Dopamine-producing neurons derived from mouse embryonic stem cells
have been shown to function in an animal model of Parkinson's disease.20
Thus, there is a possibility that transplantation of dopamine-producing
neural cells derived from embryonic or adult stem cell populations
might be a useful treatment for Parkinson's disease in the future.
However, to be effective as long-term treatments of Parkinson's
disease, Type I diabetes, and other diseases, cell transplantation
therapies will have to overcome the immune rejection problem. Cells
from one person transplanted into the body of another are usually
recognized as foreign and killed by the immune system. If cells
derived from stem cell preparations are to be broadly useful in
transplantation therapies for human diseases, some way or ways around
this problem will have to be found. For example, if the cells were
isolated from a cloned human embryo at the blastocyst stage, in
which the donor nucleus came from a patient with Parkinson's disease,
in theory these stem cells would produce the same proteins as the
patient. The hope is that dopamine-producing cells derived from
these "individualized" stem cell preparations would not be immunologically
rejected upon transplantation back into the Parkinson's disease
patient. Alternatively, if dopamine-producing cells could be derived
from the patient's own adult stem cell or multipotent adult precursor
cell populations, they could also be used in such therapies. Another
possibility is mentioned in a press report21
about work with a single Parkinson's disease patient, in which brain
cells were removed from the patient, expanded by growth in vitro,
stimulated to increase dopamine production, and transplanted back
into the brain of the same patient with an observed reduction in
disease symptoms.
By combining specific gene modification and cloned stem cell procedures,
Rideout et al.22
have provided a remarkable example of how some human genetic diseases
might someday be treated. Starting with a mouse strain that was
deficient in immune system function because of a gene mutation,
these investigators (1) produced a cloned stem cell line carrying
the gene mutation, (2) specifically repaired the gene mutation in
vitro, (3) differentiated the repaired cloned stem cell preparation
in vitro into bone marrow precursor cells, and (4) treated the mutant
mice with the repaired bone marrow precursor cells and observed
a restoration of immune cell function.
Although remarkably successful, the experimental results included
a caveat. The investigators also observed a tendency of even these
cloned bone marrow precursor cells to be recognized as foreign by
the recipient mice. Rideout et al. were led to conclude: "Our results
raise the provocative possibility that even genetically matched
cells derived by therapeutic cloning may still face barriers to
effective transplantation for some disorders."
Lanza et al.23
have also evaluated the potential for immune rejection of cloned
embryonic materials, while showing the potential therapeutic value
of tissues taken from cloned fetuses. Cloned cattle embryos at the
blastocyst stage were transferred to the uteri of surrogate mothers
and allowed to develop for five to eight weeks. Fetal heart, kidney,
and skeletal muscle tissues were isolated, and degradable polymer
vehicles containing these cloned cells were then transplanted back
into the animals that donated the nuclei for cloning. The investigators
observed no rejection reaction to the transplanted cloned cells
using two different immunological tests. More investigations with
cloned stem cell materials involving different stem cell preparations
of varying sizes, different sites of implantation, and sensitive
tests to detect low levels of immunological rejection will be required
for a complete assessment of the possibility of using cloned stem
cell populations to solve the immune rejection problem.
Figure 2: Stages in the development, isolation,
and transformation of embryonic stem cells.
[Modified from Rick Weiss and Patterson Clark, The Washington
Post.]
Human Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research
Producing cloned stem cell preparations for possible use in individual
patients suffering from diseases like Parkinson's disease and Type
I diabetes is one reason to pursue cloning-for-biomedical-research.24
In vitro production of cloned human embryos could also be important
to scientists interested in studying early human development. Stem
cells derived from cloned human embryos at the blastocyst stage
that were produced with nuclei from individuals with genetic diseases
could be useful in the study of the critical events that lead to
these diseases (for example, see Bahn et al.25
). Specific genes could be introduced into developing human embryos
to obtain information about the role or roles of these genes in
early human development.
One attempt at human cloning-for-biomedical-research has been published
in the scientific literature by Cibelli et al.26
as of the end of June 2002.ii
It involved the following steps (see Figure 1):
- Obtain human eggs from informed and consenting female volunteers.
- Remove the nuclear DNA from the egg cell, to produce an enucleated
egg.
- Insert the nucleus of a cell from an informed and consenting
adult donor into the enucleated egg, to produce a reconstituted
egg.
- Activate the reconstituted egg with chemicals or electricity
to stimulate it to commence cell division in vitro, producing
a cloned embryo.
- Use a microscope to follow the early cell divisions of the
cloned embryo.
In the experiments described by Cibelli et al., the stated intent
was to create cloned human embryos that would progress to the 100-200
cell stage, at which point the cloned embryo would be taken apart,
stem cells would be isolated from the inner cell mass, and an attempt
would be made to grow and preserve "individualized" human stem cells
(see Figure 2) for the possible future medical benefit of the somatic
cell donor. Because the cloned human embryos stopped dividing and
died at the six-cell stage, no stem cells were isolated in these
experiments. In light of results in other animal species and the
variable completeness of "epigenetic reprogramming," it is perhaps
not surprising that sixteen of the nineteen cloned human embryos
described by Cibelli et. al. did not undergo cell division and none
of the other three divided beyond the six-cell stage.
Although the steps these researchers followed in these experiments
were the same as those that would be used by those attempting human
cloning-to-produce-children, they distinguished their intent from
such cloning by stating: "Strict guidelines for the conduct of this
research have been established by Advanced Cell Technology's independent
Ethics Advisory Board (EAB). In order to prevent any possibility
of reproductive cloning, the EAB requires careful accounting of
all eggs and embryos used in the research. No embryo created by
means of NT [nuclear transfer] technology may be maintained beyond
14 days of development."
Parthenogenesis (Another Form of Asexual Reproduction)
Using chemical or electrical stimuli, it is also possible to stimulate
human eggs to undergo several rounds of cell division, as if they
had been fertilized (see Figure 1). In this case, the egg retains
all forty-six egg cell chromosomes and egg cell mitochondria. In
amphibians, this asexual reproduction process, known as parthenogenesis,
has produced live offspring that contain the same nuclear DNA as
the egg. These offspring are all necessarily female. Parthenogenesis
in mammals has not led reproducibly to the production of live offspring.
27
Cibelli et al.26
activated human eggs (obtained from informed and consenting donors)
by parthenogenesis, and obtained multiple cell divisions up to the
early embryo stage in six out of twenty-two attempts. Although there
was no report that stem cells were isolated in these experiments,
it is possible that parthenogenesis of human eggs could induce them
to develop to a stage where parthenogenetic stem cells could be
isolated. For example, Cibelli et al.28
derived a monkey parthenogenetic stem cell preparation from Macaca
fasicularis eggs activated by parthenogenesis. Whether cloned stem
cells resulting from parthenogenesis have been completely and correctly
epigenetically reprogrammed remains to be determined.
ENDNOTES
- National Academy of Sciences (NAS). Scientific and Medical
Aspects of Human Reproductive Cloning, Washing-ton, DC. National
Academy Press, 2002. Back
to Text
- National Research Council/Institute of Medicine (NRC/IOM). Stem
Cells and the Future of Regenerative Medicine. Washington
DC. National Academy Press, 2001. Back
to Text
- Wilmut, I., et al. "Viable offspring derived from fetal and
adult mammalian cells" Nature, 385: 810-813, 1997. Back
to Text
- Wakayama, T., et al. "Cloning of mice to six generations" Nature,
407: 318-319, 2000. Back
to Text
- Shin, T., et al. "A cat cloned by nuclear transplantation" Nature,
415: 859, 2002. Back
to Text
- Chesne, P., et al. "Cloned rabbits produced by nuclear transfer
from adult somatic cells" Nature Biotechnology, 20: 366-369,
2002. Back
to Text
- Kolata, G. "In Cloning, Failure Far Exceeds Success" New
York Times, December 11, 2001, page D1. Back
to Text
- See Table 2 in Reference 1. Back
to Text
- Lanza, R.P., et al. "Cloned cattle can be healthy and normal,"
Science, 294: 1893-1894, 2001. Back
to Text
- Cibelli, J.B., et al. "The health profile of cloned animals"
Nature Biotechnology, 20: 13-14, 2002. Back
to Text
- Rideout III, W.M., et al. "Nuclear cloning and epigenetic reprogramming
of the genome" Science, 293: 1093-1098, 2001. Back
to Text
- Ogonuki, N., et al. "Early death of mice cloned from somatic
cells" Nature Genetics, 30: 253-254, 2002. Back
to Text
- Weiss, R. "Human Cloning Bid Stirs Experts' Anger; Problems
in Animal Cases Noted" The Washington Post, April 11,
2001, page A1. Back
to Text
- Brown, D. "Human Clone's Birth Predicted; Delivery Outside U.S.
May Come By 2003, Researcher Says" The Washington Post,
May 16, 2002, p. A8. Back
to Text
- Thomson, J.A., et al. "Embryonic stem cell lines derived from
human blastocysts" Science, 282: 1145-1147, 1998. Back
to Text
- Shamblott, M.J., et al. "Derivation of pluripotent stem cells
from cultured human primordial germ cells" Proc Nat Acad Sci
U.S.A., 95: 13726-13731, 1998. Back
to Text
- Reyes, M., et al. "Origin of endothelial progenitors in human
postnatal bone marrow" Journal of Clinical Investigation,
109: 337-346, 2002. Back
to Text
- Jiang, Y., et al. "Pluripotency of mesenchymal stem cells derived
from adult marrow," Nature, 418: 41-49, 2002. Back
to Text
- Hagell, P., and P. Brundin, "Cell survival and clinical outcome
following intrastriatal transplantation in Parkinson's disease"
J Neuropathol Exp Neurol, 60: 741-752, 2001. Back
to Text
- Kim, J-H., et al. "Dopamine neurons derived from embryonic stem
cells function in an animal model of Parkinson's disease" Nature
418: 50-56, 2002. Back
to Text
- Weiss, R. "Stem Cell Transplant Works in Calif. Case, Parkinson's
Traits Largely Disappear," The Washington Post, April
9, 2002, p. A8. Back
to Text
- Rideout III, W.M., et al. "Correction of a genetic defect by
nuclear transplantation and combined cell and gene therapy" Cell,
109: 17-27, 2002. Back
to Text
- Lanza, R.P., et al. "Generation of histocompatible tissues using
nuclear transplantation" Nature Biotechnology, 20: 689-696,
2002. Back
to Text
- Lanza, R.P., et al. "Human therapeutic cloning" Nature Medicine,
5: 975-977, 1999. Back
to Text
- Bahn, S., et al. "Neuronal target genes of the neuron-restrictive
silencer factor in neurospheres derived from fetuses with Down's
syndrome: A gene expression study" The Lancet, 359: 310-315, 2002.
Back
to Text
- Cibelli, J.B., et al. "Somatic cell nuclear transfer in humans:
Pronuclear and early embryonic development" ebiomed: The Journal
of Regenerative Medicine, 2: 25-31, 2001. Back
to Text
- Rougier, N., and Z. Werb. "Minireview: Parthenogenesis in mammals"
Mol Reprod Devel 59: 468-474, 2001. Back
to Text
- Cibelli, J.B., et al. "Parthenogenetic stem cells in nonhuman
primates" Science, 295: 819, 2002. Back
to Text
_______________
- Previous experiments dating from the 1950s had shown that it
was possible to clone amphibians. Earlier experiments had also
produced clones of animals using embryonic donor cells. What made
the report of Dolly's birth stand out was the fact that a mammal
had been cloned, and from cells taken from an adult. Back
to Text
- According to a press report (Hall, C.T., "UCSF Admits Human
Clone Research: Work to Duplicate Embryos for Medical Purposes
on Hold" San Francisco Chronicle, May 25, 2002, p. A1), other
attempts to produce cloned human embryos for biomedical research
were carried out at the University of California-San Francisco
by Roger Pedersen and coworkers in 1999 and 2001. Another press
report (Leggett K., and A., Regalado "China Stem Cell Research
Surges as Western Nations Ponder Ethics," Wall Street Journal,
March 6, 2002, p. A1) indicates that as-yet-unpublished work in
China by Sheng Huizhen involved insertion of human somatic cell
nuclei into enucleated rabbit eggs, and that the resulting cloned
embryos developed to a stage where human embryonic stem cells
could be isolated. Back
to Text
Chapter Five
The Ethics of Cloning-to-Produce-Children
Cloning-to-produce-children has been the subject of two major
national reports in recent years first by the National Bioethics
Advisory Commission in June 1997,1
and more recently by the National Academy of Sciences in January
2002.2
Both reports concluded that attempts to clone a human being "at
this time" would be unethical, owing to questions about the safety
of the technique and the likelihood of physical harm to those involved.
But both reports also concluded that the nation required much deeper
reflection about the "ethical and social implications" of cloning-to-produce-children
beyond the scientific and medical aspects of the procedure. As the
National Academy of Sciences report stated:
Our present opposition to human reproductive cloning is
based on science and medicine, irrespective of broader considerations.
The panel stresses, however, that a broad ethical debate must be
encouraged so that the public can be prepared to make decisions
if human reproductive cloning is some day considered medically safe
for mothers and offspring.3
In this chapter we attempt to take up this charge to engage in
a broad ethical consideration of the merits of cloning-to-produce-children.
The prospect of cloning-to-produce-children raises a host of moral
questions, among them the following: Could the first attempts to
clone a human child be made without violating accepted moral norms
governing experimentation on human subjects? What harms might be
inflicted on the cloned child as a consequence of having been made
a clone? Is it significant that the cloned child would inherit a
genetic identity lived in advance by another and, in some
cases, the genetic identity of the cloned child's rearing parent?
Is it significant that cloned children would be the first human
beings whose genetic identity was entirely known and selected in
advance? How might cloning-to-produce-children affect relationships
within the cloning families? More generally, how might it affect
the relationship between the generations? How might it affect the
way society comes to view children? What other prospects would we
be tacitly approving in advance by accepting this practice? What
important human goods might be enhanced or sacrificed were we to
approve cloning-to-produce-children?
In what follows, we shall explicitly consider many of these questions.
But as we do so, we shall not lose sight of the larger and fundamental
human contexts discussed in Chapter
One namely, the meaning of human procreation and care
of children, the means and ends of biotechnology, and the relation
between science and society. Indeed, overarching our entire discussion
of the specific ethical issues is our concern for the human
significance of procreation as a whole and our desire to protect
what is valuable in it from erosion and degradation not just
from cloning but from other possible technological and nontechnological
dangers. Readers of this report are encouraged to consider the discussion
that follows in a similar light.
We will begin by formulating the best moral case for cloning-to-produce-children
describing both the specific purposes it might serve and the
philosophic and moral arguments made in its favor. From there we
will move to the moral case against cloning-to-produce-children.
Beginning with the safety objections that have dominated the debate
thus far, we will show how these concerns ultimately point beyond
themselves toward broader ethical concerns. Chief among these is
how cloning-to-produce-children would challenge the basic nature
of human procreation and the meaning of having children. We shall
also consider cloning's effects on human identity, how it might
move procreation toward a form of manufacture or toward eugenics,
and how it could distort family relations and affect society as
a whole.
* * *
I. The Case for Cloning-to-Produce-Children
Arguments in defense of cloning-to-produce-children often address
questions of reproduction, but they tend to focus on only a relatively
narrow sliver of the goods and principles involved. This certainly
does not mean that such arguments lack merit. Indeed, some of the
arguments in favor of cloning-to-produce-children appeal to the
deepest and most meaningful of our society's shared values.
A. Purposes
In recent years, in anticipation of
cloning-to-produce-children, proponents have articulated a variety
of possible uses of a perfected technology: providing a "biologically
related child" for an infertile couple; permitting reproduction
for single individuals or same-sex couples; avoiding the risk of
genetic disease; securing a genetically identical source of organs
or tissues perfectly suitable for transplantation; "replacing" a
loved spouse or child who is dying or has died; obtaining a child
with a genotype of one's own choosing (including one's own genotype);
replicating individuals of great genius, talent, or beauty, or individuals
possessing traits that are for other reasons attractive to the cloners;
and creating sets of genetically identical humans who might have
special advantages in highly cooperative ventures in both war and
peace.4
The desire to control or select the genomes of children-to-be through
cloning has charmed more than a few prospective users, in the United
States and around the world.
Although we appreciate that a perfected technology, once introduced
for one purpose, might then be used for any of these purposes, we
shall examine further only those stated purposes that seem to us
to merit serious consideration.
1. To Produce Biologically Related Children
Human cloning would allow individuals or couples with fertility
problems to have biologically related children. For example, if
a man could not produce sperm, cloning would allow him to have a
child who is "biologically related" to him. In addition, it would
allow married couples with fertility problems to avoid using donor
gametes, and therefore avoid raising children with genetic inheritances
from outside the marriage.
2. To Avoid Genetic Disease
Human cloning could allow couples at risk of generating children
with genetic disease to have healthy children. For example, if both
parents carried one copy of a recessive gene for the same heritable
disorder, cloning might allow them to ensure that their child does
not inherit the known genetic disease (without having to resort
to using donor gametes or practicing preimplantation or prenatal
genetic diagnosis and elimination of afflicted embryos or fetuses).
3. To Obtain "Rejection-Proof" Transplants
Human cloning could produce ideal transplant donors for people
who are sick or dying. For example, if no genetic match could be
found for a sick child needing a kidney or bone marrow transplant,
and the parents had planned to have another child, cloning could
potentially serve the human goods of beginning a new life and saving
an existing one.
4. To "Replicate" a Loved One
Human cloning would allow parents to "replicate" a dead or dying
child or relative. For example, one can imagine a case in which
a family mother, father, and child is involved in a
terrible car accident in which the father dies instantly and the
child is critically injured. The mother, told that her child will
soon die, decides that the best way to redeem the tragedy is to
clone her dying child. This would allow her to preserve a connection
with both her dead husband and her dying child, to create new life
as a partial human answer to the grievous misfortune of her child's
untimely death, and to continue the name and biological lineage
of her deceased husband.
5. To Reproduce Individuals of Great Genius, Talent, or Beauty
Human cloning would allow families or society to reproduce individuals
of great genius, talent, or beauty, where these traits are presumed
to be based on the individuals' desirable or superior genetic makeups.
For example, some admirers of great athletes, musicians, or mathematicians,
believing that the admired attributes are the result of a superior
genetic endowment, might want to clone these distinguished individuals.
Just as the cloning of cattle is being promoted as a means of perpetuating
champion milk- or meat-producing cows, so cloning-to-produce-children
has been touted as a means of perpetuating certain "superior" human
exemplars.
B. Arguments
The purposes or reasons for cloning-to-produce-children are, as
they are stated, clearly intelligible on their face. When challenged,
the defenders of these purposes often appeal to larger moral and
political goods. These typically fall within the following three
categories: human freedom, existence, and well-being.
1. The Goodness of Human Freedom
Strictly speaking, the appeal to human freedom is not so much a
defense of cloning itself as it is of the right to practice
it, asserted against those who seek to prohibit it. No one, we suspect,
would say that he wanted to clone himself or any one else in order
to be free or to vindicate the goodness of liberty. Nevertheless,
human freedom is a defense often heard in support of a "right" to
clone.
Those who defend cloning-to-produce-children on the grounds of
human freedom make two kinds of arguments. The first is that because
individuals in pluralistic societies have different definitions
of the good life and of right and wrong, society must protect individual
freedom to choose against the possible tyranny of the majority.
This means securing and even expanding the rights of individuals
to make choices so long as their choices do not directly infringe
on the rights (and especially the physical safety) of other rights-bearing
citizens. In Eisenstadt v. Baird (1972), the United States
Supreme Court enunciated what has been called a principle of reproductive
freedom: "If the right to privacy means anything, it is the right
of the individual, married or single, to be free from unwarranted
governmental intrusion into matters so affecting a person as a decision
whether to bear or beget a child."5
Defenders of cloning-to-produce-children argue that, in the event
that the physical risks to mother and future child were shown to
be ethically acceptable, the use of this new reproductive technology
would fall under the protective umbrella of reproductive freedom.
A second defense of human cloning on the grounds of freedom is
the claim that human existence is by its very nature "open-ended,"
"indeterminate," and "unpredictable." Human beings are always remaking
themselves, their values, and their ways of interacting with one
another. New technologies are central to this open-ended idea of
human life, and to shut down such technologies simply because they
change the "traditional" ways of doing things is unjustifiable.
As constitutional scholar Laurence Tribe has argued in reference
to human cloning: "A society that bans acts of human creation that
reflect unconventional sex roles or parenting models (surrogate
motherhood, in vitro fertilization, artificial insemination, and
the like) for no better reason than that such acts dare to defy
'nature' and tradition (and to risk adding to life's complexity)
is a society that risks cutting itself off from vital experimentation
and risks sterilizing a significant part of its capacity to grow."6
2. The Goodness of Existence
Like the appeal to freedom, the appeal to the goodness of existence
is not an argument for cloning, but an argument against
opponents who speak up in the name of protecting the cloned child-to-be
against the harms connected with its risky and strange origins as
a clone. This argument asserts that attempts to produce children
through cloning, like any attempt to produce a child, will
directly benefit the cloned child-to-be, since without the act of
cloning the child in question would not exist. Existence itself,
it is argued, is the first "interest" that makes all other interests
including the interests of safety and well-being possible.
Even taking into account the possibility of serious genetic or developmental
disorders, this position holds that a cloned individual, once born,
would prefer existence as a clone to no existence at all. There
is also a serious corollary about how, in the absence of a principle
that values existence as such, we will and should regard
and treat people born with disabilities or deformities: opponents
of cloning might appear in a position of intolerance of saying
to cloned individuals, "Better for us (and for you) had you never
existed."
3. The Goodness of Well-Being
The third moral argument for cloning-to-produce-children is that
it would contribute in certain cases to the fulfillment of human
goods that are widely honored and deeply rooted in modern democratic
society. These human goods include the health of newborn and existing
children, reproductive possibilities for infertile couples, and
the possibility of having a biologically related child. In all these
circumstances, human cloning could relieve existing suffering and
sorrow or prevent them in the future. Those who take this position
do not necessarily defend human cloning-to-produce-children as such.
Rather, they argue that a moral and practical line can be drawn
between cloning-to-produce-children that serves the "therapeutic"
aims of health (for the cloned child-to-be, for the infertile couple,
or for an existing child) and the "eugenic" aims of producing or
mass-producing superior people.
Some people argue more broadly that an existing generation has
a responsibility to ensure, to the extent possible, the genetic
quality and fitness of the next generation. Human cloning, they
argue, offers a new method for human control and self-improvement,
by allowing families to have children free of specific genetic diseases
or society to reproduce children with superior genetic endowments.
It also provides a new means for gaining knowledge about the age-old
question of nature versus nurture in contributing to human achievement
and human flourishing, and to see how clones of great geniuses measure
up against the "originals."
C. Critique and Conclusion
While we as a Council acknowledge merit in some of the arguments
made for cloning-to-produce-children, we are generally not persuaded
by them. The fundamental weakness of the proponents' case is found
in their incomplete view of human procreation and families, and
especially the place and well-being of children. Proponents of cloning
tend to see procreation primarily as the free exercise of a parental
right, namely, a right to satisfy parental desires for self-fulfillment
or a right to have a child who is healthy or "superior." Parents
seek to overcome obstacles to reproduction, to keep their children
free of genetic disease or disorder, and to provide them with the
best possible genetic endowment. The principles guiding such prospective
parents are freedom (for themselves), control (over their child),
and well-being (both for themselves and what they imagine is best
for their child). Even taken together, these principles provide
at best only a partial understanding of the meaning and entailments
of human procreation and child-rearing. In practice, they may prove
to undermine the very goods that the proponents of cloning aim to
serve, by undermining the unconditional acceptance of one's offspring
that is so central to parenthood.
There are a number of objections or at the very least limitations
to viewing cloning-to-produce-children through the prism of
rights. Basic human rights are usually asserted on behalf of the
human individual agent: for example, a meaningful right not to be
prevented from bearing a child can be asserted for each individual
against state-mandated sterilization programs. But the act of procreation
is not an act involving a single individual. Indeed, until human
cloning arrives, it continues to be impossible for any one person
to procreate alone. More important, there is a crucial third party
involved: the child, whose centrality to the activity exposes the
insufficiency of thinking about procreation in terms of rights.
After all, rights are limited in the following crucial way: they
cannot be ethically exercised at the expense of the rights of another.
But the "right to reproduce" cannot be ethically exercised without
at least considering the child that such exercise will bring into
being and who is at risk of harm and injustice from the exercise.
This obligation cannot be waived by an appeal to the absolutist
argument of the goodness of existence. Yes, existence is a primary
good, but that does not diminish the ethical significance of knowingly
and willfully putting a child in grave physical danger in the very
act of giving that child existence. It is certainly true that a
life with even severe disability may well be judged worth living
by its bearer: "It is better to have been born as I am than not
to be here at all." But if his or her disability was caused by behavior
that could have been avoided by parents (for example, by not drinking
or using drugs during pregnancy, or, arguably, by not cloning),
many would argue that they should have avoided it. A post-facto
affirmation of existence by the harmed child would not retroactively
excuse the parental misconduct that caused the child's disability,
nor would it justify their failure to think of the child's well-being
as they went about exercising their "right to procreate." Indeed,
procreation is, by its very nature, a limitation of absolute rights,
since it brings into existence another human being toward whom we
have responsibilities and duties.
In short, the right to decide "whether to bear or beget
a child" does not include a right to have a child by whatever
means. Nor can this right be said to imply a corollary
the right to decide what kind of child one is going to have. There
are at least some circumstances where reproductive freedom must
be limited to protect the good of the child (as, for instance, with
the ban on incest). Our society's commitment to freedom and parental
authority by no means implies that all innovative procedures and
practices should be allowed or accepted, no matter how bizarre or
dangerous.
Proponents of cloning, when they do take into account the interests
of the child, sometimes argue that this interest justifies and even
requires thoroughgoing parental control over the procreative process.
Yet this approach, even when well-intentioned, may undermine the
good of the child more than it serves the child's best interests.
For one thing, cloning-to-produce-children of a desired or worthy
sort overlooks the need to restrain the parental temptation to total
mastery over children. It is especially morally dubious for this
project to go forward when we know so little about the unforeseen
and unintended consequences of exercising such genetic control.
In trying by cloning to circumvent the risk of genetic disease or
to promote particular traits, it is possible perhaps likely
that new risks to the cloned child's health and fitness would
be inadvertently introduced (including the forgoing of genetic novelty,
a known asset in the constant struggle against microbial and parasitic
diseases). Parental control is a double-edged sword, and proponents
seem not to acknowledge the harms, both physical and psychological,
that may befall the child whose genetic identity is selected in
advance.
The case for cloning in the name of the child's health and well-being
is certainly the strongest and most compelling. The desire that
one's child be free from a given genetic disease is a worthy aspiration.
We recognize there may be some unusual or extreme cases in which
cloning might be the best means to serve this moral good, if other
ethical obstacles could somehow be overcome. (A few of us also believe
that the desire to give a child "improved" or "superior" genetic
equipment is not necessarily to be condemned.) However, such aspirations
could endanger the personal, familial, and societal goods supported
by the character of human procreation. We are willing to grant that
there may be exceptional cases in which cloning-to-produce-children
is morally defensible; however, that being said, we would also argue
that such cases do not justify the harmful experiments and social
problems that might be entailed by engaging in human cloning. Hard
cases are said to make bad law. The same would be true for succumbing
to the rare, sentimentally appealing case in which cloning seems
morally plausible.i
Finally, proponents do not adequately face up to the difficulty
of how "well-being" is to be defined. Generally, they argue that
these matters are to be left up to the free choices of parents and
doctors. But this means that the judgments of "proper" and "improper"
will be made according to subjective criteria alone, and under such
circumstances, it will be almost impossible to rule out certain
"improvements" as unacceptable.
In the sections that follow, we shall explain more fully why Members
of the Council are not convinced by the arguments for cloning-to-produce-children,
even in the most defensible cases. To see why this is so, we need
to consider cloning-to-produce-children from the broadest possible
moral perspective, beginning with ethical questions regarding experiments
on human subjects. What we hope to show is that the frequently made
safety arguments strike deeper than we usually realize, and that
they point beyond themselves toward more fundamental moral objections
to cloning-to-produce-children.
* * *
II. The Case against Cloning-to-Produce-Children
A. The Ethics of Human Experimentation
We begin with concerns regarding the safety of the cloning procedure
and the health of the participants. We do so for several reasons.
First, these concerns are widely, indeed nearly unanimously, shared.
Second, they lend themselves readily to familiar modes of ethical
analysis including concerns about harming the innocent, protecting
human rights, and ensuring the consent of all research subjects.
Finally, if carefully considered, these concerns begin to reveal
the important ethical principles that must guide our broader assessment
of cloning-to-produce-children. They suggest that human beings,
unlike inanimate matter or even animals, are in some way inviolable,
and therefore challenge us to reflect on what it is about
human beings that makes them inviolable, and whether cloning-to-produce-children
threatens these distinctly human goods.
In initiating this analysis, there is perhaps no better place to
start than the long-standing international practice of regulating
experiments on human subjects. After all, the cloning of a human
being, as well as all the research and trials required before such
a procedure could be expected to succeed, would constitute experiments
on the individuals involved the egg donor, the birthing mother,
and especially the child-to-be. It therefore makes sense to consider
the safety and health concerns that arise from cloning-to-produce-children
in light of the widely shared ethical principles that govern experimentation
on human subjects.
Since the Second World War, various
codes for the ethical conduct of human experimentation have been
adopted around the world. These codes and regulations were formulated
in direct response to serious ethical lapses and violations committed
by research scientists against the rights and dignity of individual
human beings. Among the most important and widely accepted documents
to emerge were the Nuremberg Code of 19477
and the Helsinki Declaration of 1964.8
Influential in the United States is also the Belmont Report, published
in 1978 by the National Commission for the Protection of Human Subjects
of Biomedical and Behavioral Research.9
The Nuremberg Code laid out ten principles for the ethical conduct
of experiments, focusing especially on voluntary consent of research
subjects, the principle that experiments should be conducted only
with the aim of providing a concrete good for society that is unprocurable
by other methods, and with the avoidance of physical or mental harm.
The Helsinki Declaration stated, among other things, that research
should be undertaken only when the prospective benefit clearly outweighs
the expected risk, when the research subject has been fully informed
of all risks, and when the research-subject population is itself
likely to benefit from the results of the experiment.
Finally, the Belmont Report proposed three basic ethical principles
that were to guide the treatment of human subjects involved in scientific
research. The first of these is respect for persons, which
requires researchers to acknowledge the autonomy and individual
rights of research subjects and to offer special protection to those
with diminished autonomy and capacity. The second principle is beneficence.
Scientific research must not only refrain from harming those involved
but must also be aimed at helping them, or others, in concrete and
important ways. The third principle is justice, which involves
just distribution of potential benefits and harms and fair selection
of research subjects. When applied, these general principles lead
to both a requirement for informed consent of human research subjects
and a requirement for a careful assessment of risks and benefits
before proceeding with research. Safety, consent, and the rights
of research subjects are thus given the highest priority.
It would be a mistake to view these codes in narrow or procedural
terms, when in fact they embody society's profound sense that human
beings are not to be treated as experimental guinea pigs for scientific
research. Each of the codes was created to address a specific disaster
involving research science whether the experiments conducted
by Nazi doctors on concentration camp prisoners, or the Willowbrook
scandal in which mentally retarded children were infected with hepatitis,
or the Tuskegee scandal in which underprivileged African-American
men suffering from syphilis were observed but not treated by medical
researchers and each of the codes was an attempt to defend
the inviolability and dignity of all human beings in the face of
such threats and abuses. More simply stated, the codes attempt to
defend the weak against the strong and to uphold the equal dignity
of all human beings. In taking up the application of these codes
to the case of cloning-to-produce-children, we would suggest that
the proper approach is not simply to discover specific places where
human cloning violates this or that stipulation of this or that
code, but to grapple with how such cloning offends the spirit of
these codes and what they seek to defend.
The ethics of research on human subjects suggest three sorts of
problems that would arise in cloning-to-produce-children: (1) problems
of safety; (2) a special problem of consent; and (3) problems of
exploitation of women and the just distribution of risk. We shall
consider each in turn.
1. Problems of Safety
First, cloning-to-produce-children is not now safe. Concerns about
the safety of the individuals involved in a cloning procedure are
shared by nearly everyone on all sides of the cloning debate. Even
most proponents of cloning-to-produce-children generally qualify
their support with a caveat about the safety of the procedure. Cloning
experiments in other mammals strongly suggest that cloning-to-produce-children
is, at least for now, far too risky to attempt.10
Safety concerns revolve around potential dangers to the cloned child,
as well as to the egg donor and the woman who would carry the cloned
child to birth.
(a) Risks to the child. Risks to the cloned child-to-be
must be taken especially seriously, both because they are most numerous
and most serious and because unlike the risks to the egg donor
and birth mother they cannot be accepted knowingly and freely
by the person who will bear them. In animal experiments to date,
only a small percentage of implanted clones have resulted in live
births, and a substantial portion of those live-born clones have
suffered complications that proved fatal fairly quickly. Some serious
though nonfatal abnormalities in cloned animals have also been observed,
including substantially increased birth-size, liver and brain defects,
and lung, kidney, and cardiovascular problems.11
Longer-term consequences are of course not known, as the oldest
successfully cloned mammal is only six years of age. Medium-term
consequences, including premature aging, immune system failure,
and sudden unexplained death, have already become apparent in some
cloned mammals. Some researchers have also expressed concerns that
a donor nucleus from an individual who has lived for some years
may have accumulated genetic mutations that if the nucleus
were used in the cloning of a new human life may predispose
the new individual to certain sorts of cancer and other diseases.12
(b) Risks to the egg donor and the birth mother. Accompanying
the threats to the cloned child's health and well-being are risks
to the health of the egg donors. These include risks to her future
reproductive health caused by the hormonal treatments required for
egg retrieval and general health risks resulting from the necessary
superovulation.13
Animal studies also suggest the likelihood of health risks to the
woman who carries the cloned fetus to term. The animal data suggest
that late-term fetal losses and spontaneous abortions occur substantially
more often with cloned fetuses than in natural pregnancies. In humans,
such late-term fetal losses may lead to substantially increased
maternal morbidity and mortality. In addition, animal studies have
shown that many pregnancies involving cloned fetuses result in serious
complications, including toxemia and excessive fluid accumulation
in the uterus, both of which pose risks to the pregnant animal's
health.14
In one prominent cattle cloning study, just under one-third of the
pregnant cows died from complications late in pregnancy.15
Reflecting on the dangers to birth mothers in animal cloning studies,
the National Academy report concluded:
Results of animal studies suggest that reproductive cloning
of humans would similarly pose a high risk to the health of both
fetus or infant and mother and lead to associated psychological
risks for the mother as a consequence of late spontaneous abortions
or the birth of a stillborn child or a child with severe health
problems. 16
(c) An abiding moral concern. Because of these risks,
there is widespread agreement that, at least for now, attempts at
cloning-to-produce-children would constitute unethical experimentation
on human subjects and are therefore impermissible. These safety
considerations were alone enough to lead the National Bioethics
Advisory Commission in June 1997 to call for a temporary prohibition
of human cloning-to-produce-children. Similar concerns, based on
almost five more years of animal experimentation, convinced the
panel of the National Academy of Sciences in January 2002 that the
United States should ban such cloning for at least five years.
Past discussions of this subject have often given the impression
that the safety concern is a purely temporary one that can be allayed
in the near future, as scientific advances and improvements in technique
reduce the risks to an ethically acceptable level. But this impression
is mistaken, for considerable safety risks are likely to be enduring,
perhaps permanent. If so, there will be abiding ethical difficulties
even with efforts aimed at making human cloning safe.
The reason is clear: experiments to develop new reproductive technologies
are necessarily intergenerational, undertaken to serve the reproductive
desires of prospective parents but practiced also and always upon
prospective children. Any such experiment unavoidably involves risks
to the child-to-be, a being who is both the product and
also the most vulnerable human subject of the research.
Exposed to risk during the extremely sensitive life-shaping processes
of his or her embryological development, any child-to-be is a singularly
vulnerable creature, one maximally deserving of protection against
risk of experimental (and other) harm. If experiments to learn how
to clone a child are ever to be ethical, the degree of risk to that
child-to-be would have to be extremely low, arguably no greater
than for children-to-be who are conceived from union of egg and
sperm. It is extremely unlikely that this moral burden can be met,
not for decades if at all.
In multiple experiments involving six of the mammalian species
cloned to date, more than 89 percent of the cloned embryos transferred
to recipient females did not come to birth, and many of the live-born
cloned animals are or become abnormal.17
If success means achieving normal and healthy development not just
at birth but throughout the life span, there is even less reason
for confidence. The oldest cloned mammal (Dolly) is only six years
old and has exhibited unusually early arthritis. The reasons for
failure in animal cloning are not well understood. Also, no nonhuman
primates have been cloned. It will be decades (at least) before
we could obtain positive evidence that cloned primates might live
a normal healthy (primate) life.
Even a high success rate in animals would not suffice by itself
to make human trials morally acceptable. In addition to the usual
uncertainties in jumping the gap from animal to human research,
cloning is likely to present particularly difficult problems of
interspecies difference. Animal experiments have already shown substantial
differences in the reproductive success of identical cloning techniques
used in different species.18
If these results represent species-specific differences in, for
example, the ease of epigenetic reprogramming and imprinting of
the donor DNA, the magnitude of the risks to the child-to-be of
the first human cloning experiments would be unknown and potentially
large, no matter how much success had been achieved in animals.
There can in principle be no direct experimental evidence sufficient
for assessing the degree of such risk.ii
Can a highly reduced risk of deformity, disease, and premature
death in animal cloning, coupled with the inherently unpredictable
risk of moving from animals to humans, ever be low enough to meet
the ethically acceptable standard set by reproduction begun with
egg and sperm? The answer, as a matter of necessity, can never be
better than "Just possibly." Given the severity of the possible
harms involved in human cloning, and given that those harms fall
on the very vulnerable child-to-be, such an answer would seem to
be enduringly inadequate.
Similar arguments, it is worth noting, were made before the first
attempts at human in vitro fertilization. People suggested that
it would be unethical experimentation even to try to determine whether
IVF could be safely done. And then, of course, IVF was accomplished.
Eventually, it became a common procedure, and today the moral argument
about its safety seems to many people beside the point. Yet the
fact of success in that case does not establish precedent in this
one, nor does it mean that the first attempts at IVF were not in
fact unethical experiments upon the unborn, despite the fortunate
results.iii
Be this as it may, the case of cloning is genuinely different.
With IVF, assisted fertilization of egg by sperm immediately releases
a developmental process, linked to the sexual union of the two gametes,
that nature has selected over millions of years for the entire mammalian
line. But in cloning experiments to produce children, researchers
would be transforming a sexual system into an asexual one, a change
that requires major and "unnatural" reprogramming of donor DNA if
there is to be any chance of success. They are neither enabling
nor restoring a natural process, and the alterations involved are
such that success in one species cannot be presumed to predict success
in another. Moreover, any new somatic mutations in the donor cell's
chromosomal DNA would be passed along to the cloned child-to-be
and its offspring. Here we can see even more the truly intergenerational
character of cloning experimentation, and this should justify placing
the highest moral burden of persuasion on those who would like to
proceed with efforts to make cloning safe for producing children.
(By reminding us of the need to protect the lives and well-being
of our children and our children's children, this broader analysis
of the safety question points toward larger moral objections to
producing cloned children, objections that we shall consider shortly.)
It therefore appears to us that, given the dangers involved and
the relatively limited goods to be gained from cloning-to-produce-children,
conducting experiments in an effort to make cloning-to-produce-children
safer would itself be an unacceptable violation of the norms of
the ethics of research. There seems to be no ethical way to
try to discover whether cloning-to-produce-children can become safe,
now or in the future.
2. A Special Problem of Consent
A further concern relating to the ethics of human research revolves
around the question of consent. Consent from the cloned child-to-be
is of course impossible to obtain, and because no one consents to
his or her own birth, it may be argued that concerns about consent
are misplaced when applied to the unborn. But the issue is not so
simple. For reasons having to do both with the safety concerns raised
above and with the social, psychological, and moral concerns to
be addressed below, an attempt to clone a human being would potentially
expose a cloned individual-to-be to great risks of harm, quite distinct
from those accompanying other sorts of reproduction. Given the risks,
and the fact that consent cannot be obtained, the ethically correct
choice may be to avoid the experiment. The fact that those engaged
in cloning cannot ask an unconceived child for permission places
a burden on the cloners, not on the child. Given that anyone considering
creating a cloned child must know that he or she is putting a newly
created human life at exceptional risk, the burden on the would-be
cloners seems clear: they must make a compelling case why the procedure
should not be avoided altogether. iv
Reflections on the purpose and meaning of seeking consent support
this point. Why, after all, does society insist upon consent as
an essential principle of the ethics of scientific research? Along
with honoring the free will of the subject, we insist on consent
to protect the weak and the vulnerable, and in particular to protect
them from the powerful. It would therefore be morally questionable,
at the very least, to choose to impose potentially grave harm on
an individual, especially in the very act of giving that individual
life. Giving existence to a human being does not grant one the right
to maim or harm that human being in research.
3. Problems of Exploitation of Women and Just Distribution of
Risk
Cloning-to-produce-children may also lead to the exploitation
of women who would be called upon to donate oocytes. Widespread
use of the techniques of cloning-to-produce-children would require
large numbers of eggs. Animal models suggest that several hundred
eggs may be required before one attempt at cloning can be successful.
The required oocytes would have to be donated, and the process of
making them available would involve hormonal treatments to induce
superovulation. If financial incentives are offered, they might
lead poor women especially to place themselves at risk in this way
(and might also compromise the voluntariness of their "choice" to
make donations). Thus, research on cloning-to-produce-children could
impose disproportionate burdens on women, particularly low-income
women.
4. Conclusion
These questions of the ethics of research particularly the
issue of physical safety point clearly to the conclusion that
cloning-to-produce-children is unacceptable. In reaching this conclusion,
we join the National Bioethics Advisory Commission and the National
Academy of Sciences. But we go beyond the findings of those distinguished
bodies in also pointing to the dangers that will always
be inherent in the very process of trying to make cloning-to-produce-children
safer. On this ground, we conclude that the problem of safety is
not a temporary ethical concern. It is rather an enduring moral
concern that might not be surmountable and should thus preclude
work toward the development of cloning techniques to produce children.
In light of the risks and other ethical concerns raised by this
form of human experimentation, we therefore conclude that cloning-to-produce-children
should not be attempted.
For some people, the discussion of ethical objections to cloning-to-produce-children
could end here. Our society's established codes and practices in
regard to human experimentation by themselves offer compelling reasons
to oppose indefinitely attempts to produce a human child by cloning.
But there is more to be said.
First, many people who are repelled by or opposed to the prospect
of cloning human beings are concerned not simply or primarily because
the procedure is unsafe. To the contrary, their objection is to
the use of a perfected cloning technology and to a society
that would embrace or permit the production of cloned children.
The ethical objection based on lack of safety is not really an objection
to cloning as such. Indeed, it may in time become a vanishing
objection should people be allowed to proceed despite insuperable
ethical objections such as the ones we have just offered with
experiments to perfect the technique.v
Should this occur, the ethical assessment of cloning-to-produce-children
would need to address itself to the merits (and demerits) of cloning
itself, beyond the safety questions tied to the techniques used
to produce cloned children. Thus, anticipating the possibility of
a perfected and usable technology, it is important to delineate
the case against the practice itself.
Moreover, because the Council is considering cloning within a
broad context of present and projected techniques that can affect
human procreation or alter the genetic makeup of our children, it
is important that we consider the full range and depth of ethical
issues raised by such efforts.
How should these issues be raised, and within what moral framework?
Some, but by no means all, of the deepest moral concerns connected
to human cloning could be handled by developing a richer consideration
of the ethics of human experimentation. Usually and regrettably
we apply the ethical principles governing research on human
subjects in a utilitarian spirit, weighing benefits versus harms,
and moreover using only a very narrow notion of "harm." The calculus
that weighs benefits versus harms too often takes stock only of
bodily harm or violations of patient autonomy, though some serious
efforts have been made in recent years to consider broader issues.
In addition, we often hold a rather narrow view of what constitutes
"an experiment." Yet cloning-to-produce-children would be a "human
experiment" in many senses, and risks of bodily harm and inadequate
consent do not exhaust the ways in which cloning might do damage.
As we have described, cloning-to-produce-children would be a biological
experiment with necessary uncertainties about the safety
of the technique and the possibility of physical harm. But it would
also be an experiment in human procreation substituting
asexual for sexual reproduction and treating children not as gifts
but as our self-designed products. It would be an experiment
in human identity creating the first human beings to
inherit a genetic identity lived in advance by another. It would
be an experiment in genetic choice and design producing
the first children whose entire genetic makeup was selected in advance.
It would be an experiment in family and social life
altering the relationships within the family and between the generations,
for example, by turning "mothers" into "twin sisters" and "grandparents"
into "parents," and by having children asymmetrically linked biologically
to only one parent. And it would represent a social experiment
for the entire society, insofar as the society accepted, even if
only as a minority practice, this unprecedented and novel mode of
producing our offspring.
By considering these other ways in which cloning would constitute
an experiment, we could enlarge our analysis of the ethics of research
with human subjects to assess possible nonbodily harms
of cloning-to-produce-children. But valuable as this effort might
be, we have not chosen to proceed in this way. Not all the important
issues can be squeezed into the categories of harms and benefits.
People can be mistreated or done an injustice whether they know
it or not and quite apart from any experienced harm. Important human
goods can be traduced, violated, or sacrificed without being registered
in anyone's catalogue of harms. The form of bioethical inquiry we
are attempting here will make every effort not to truncate the moral
meaning of our actions and practices by placing them on the Procrustean
bed of utilitarianism. To be sure, the ethical principles governing
human research are highly useful in efforts to protect vulnerable
individuals against the misconduct or indifference of the powerful.
But a different frame of reference is needed to evaluate the human
meaning of innovations that may affect the lives and humanity of
everyone, vulnerable or not.
Of the arguments developed below, some are supported by most Council
Members, while other arguments are shared by only some Members.
Even among the arguments they share, different Members find different
concerns to be weightier. Yet we all believe that the arguments
presented in the sections that follow are worthy of consideration
in the course of trying to assess fully the ethical issues
involved. We have chosen to err on the side of inclusion rather
than exclusion of arguments because we acknowledge that concerns
now expressed by only a few may turn out in the future to be more
important than those now shared by all. Our fuller assessment begins
with an attempt to fathom the deepest meaning of human procreation
and thus necessarily the meaning of raising children. Our analysis
will then move onto questions dealing with the effects of cloning
on individuals, family life, and society more generally.
B. The Human Context: Procreation and Child-Rearing
Were it to take place, cloning-to-produce-children would represent
a challenge to the nature of human procreation and child-rearing.
Cloning is, of course, not only a means of procreation. It is also
a technology, a human experiment, and an exercise of freedom, among
other things. But cloning would be most unusual, consequential,
and most morally important as a new way of bringing children into
the world and a new way of viewing their moral significance.
In Chapter One
we outlined some morally significant features of human procreation
and raised questions about how these would be altered by human cloning.
We will now attempt to deepen that analysis, and begin with the
salient fact that a child is not made, but begotten. Procreation
is not making but the outgrowth of doing. A man and woman give themselves
in love to each other, setting their projects aside in order to
do just that. Yet a child results, arriving on its own, mysterious,
independent, yet the fruit of the embrace.vi
Even were the child wished for, and consciously so, he or she is
the issue of their love, not the product of their wills; the man
and woman in no way produce or choose a particular child,
as they might buy a particular car. Procreation can, of course,
be assisted by human ingenuity (as with IVF). In such cases, it
may become harder to see the child solely as a gift bestowed upon
the parents' mutual self-giving and not to some degree as a product
of their parental wills. Nonetheless, because it is still sexual
reproduction, the children born with the help of IVF begin
as do all other children with a certain genetic independence
of their parents. They replicate neither their fathers nor their
mothers, and this is a salutary reminder to parents of the independence
they must one day grant their children and for which it is their
duty to prepare them.
Gifts and blessings we learn to accept as gratefully as we can.
Products of our wills we try to shape in accord with our desires.
Procreation as traditionally understood invites acceptance, rather
than reshaping, engineering, or designing the next generation. It
invites us to accept limits to our control over the next generation.
It invites us even to put the point most strongly to
think of the child as one who is not simply our own, our possession.
Certainly, it invites us to remember that the child does not exist
simply for the happiness or fulfillment of the parents.
To be sure, parents do and must try to form and mold their children
in various ways as they inure them to the demands of family life,
prepare them for adulthood, and initiate them into the human community.
But, even then, it is only our sense that these children are not
our possessions that makes such parental nurture which always threatens
not to nourish but to stifle the child safe.
This concern can be expressed not only in language about the relation
between the generations but also in the language of equality. The
things we make are not just like ourselves; they are the products
of our wills, and their point and purpose are ours to determine.
But a begotten child comes into the world just as its parents once
did, and is therefore their equal in dignity and humanity.
The character of sexual procreation shapes the lives of children
as well as parents. By giving rise to genetically new individuals,
sexual reproduction imbues all human beings with a sense of individual
identity and of occupying a place in this world that has never belonged
to another. Our novel genetic identity symbolizes and foreshadows
the unique, never-to-be-repeated character of each human life. At
the same time, our emergence from the union of two individuals,
themselves conceived and generated as we were, locates us immediately
in a network of relation and natural affection.
Social identity, like genetic identity, is in significant measure
tied to these biological facts. Societies around the world have
structured social and economic responsibilities around the relationship
between the generations established through sexual procreation,
and have developed modes of child-rearing, family responsibility,
and kinship behavior that revolve around the natural facts of begetting.
There is much more to be said about these matters, and they are
vastly more complicated than we have indicated. There are, in addition,
cultural differences in the way societies around the world regard
the human significance of procreation or the way children are to
be regarded and cared for. Yet we have said enough to indicate that
the character and nature of human procreation matter deeply. They
affect human life in endless subtle ways, and they shape families
and communities. A proper regard for the profundity of human procreation
(including child-rearing and parent-child relations) is, in our
view, indispensable for a full assessment of the ethical implications
of cloning-to-produce-children.
C. Identity, Manufacture, Eugenics, Family, and Society
Beyond the matter of procreation itself, we think it important
to examine the possible psychological and emotional state of individuals
produced by cloning, the well-being of their families, and the likely
effects on society of permitting human cloning. These concerns would
apply even if cloning-to-produce-children were conducted on a small
scale; and they would apply in even the more innocent-seeming cloning
scenarios, such as efforts to overcome infertility or to avoid the
risk of genetic disease. Admittedly, these matters are necessarily
speculative, for empirical evidence is lacking. Nevertheless, the
importance of the various goods at stake justifies trying to think
matters through in advance.
Keeping in mind our general observations about procreation, we
proceed to examine a series of specific ethical issues and objections
to cloning human children: (1) problems of identity and individuality;
(2) concerns regarding manufacture; (3) the prospect of a new eugenics;
(4) troubled family relations; and (5) effects on society.
1. Problems of Identity and Individuality
Cloning-to-produce-children could create serious problems of identity
and individuality. This would be especially true if it were used
to produce multiple "copies" of any single individual, as in one
or another of the seemingly far-fetched futuristic scenarios in
which cloning is often presented to the popular imagination. Yet
questions of identity and individuality could arise even in small-scale
cloning, even in the (supposedly) most innocent of cases, such as
the production of a single cloned child within an intact family.
Personal identity is, we would emphasize, a complex and subtle psychological
phenomenon, shaped ultimately by the interaction of many diverse
factors. But it does seem reasonably clear that cloning would at
the very least present a unique and possibly disabling challenge
to the formation of individual identity.
Cloned children may experience concerns about their distinctive
identity not only because each will be genetically essentially identical
to another human being, but also because they may resemble in appearance
younger versions of the person who is their "father" or "mother."
Of course, our genetic makeup does not by itself determine our identities.
But our genetic uniqueness is an important source of our sense of
who we are and how we regard ourselves. It is an emblem of independence
and individuality. It endows us with a sense of life as a never-before-enacted
possibility. Knowing and feeling that nobody has previously possessed
our particular gift of natural characteristics, we go forward as
genetically unique individuals into relatively indeterminate futures.
These new and unique genetic identities are rooted in the natural
procreative process. A cloned child, by contrast, is at risk of
living out a life overshadowed in important ways by the life of
the "original" general appearance being only the most obvious.
Indeed, one of the reasons some people are interested in cloning
is that the technique promises to produce in each case a particular
individual whose traits and characteristics are already known. And
however much or little one's genotype actually shapes one's
natural capacities, it could mean a great deal to an individual's
experience of life and the expectations that those who
cloned him or her might have. The cloned child may be constantly
compared to "the original," and may consciously or unconsciously
hold himself or herself up to the genetic twin that came before.
If the two individuals turned out to lead similar lives, the cloned
person's achievements may be seen as derivative. If, as is perhaps
more likely, the cloned person departed from the life of his or
her progenitor, this very fact could be a source of constant scrutiny,
especially in circumstances in which parents produced their cloned
child to become something in particular. Living up to parental hopes
and expectations is frequently a burden for children; it could be
a far greater burden for a cloned individual. The shadow of the
cloned child's "original" might be hard for the child to escape,
as would parental attitudes that sought in the child's very existence
to replicate, imitate, or replace the "original."
It may reasonably be argued that genetic individuality is not
an indispensable human good, since identical twins share a common
genotype and seem not to be harmed by it. But this argument misses
the context and environment into which even a single human clone
would be born. Identical twins have as progenitors two biological
parents and are born together, before either one has developed and
shown what his or her potential natural or otherwise
may be. Each is largely free of the burden of measuring up to or
even knowing in advance the genetic traits of the other, because
both begin life together and neither is yet known to the world.
But a clone is a genetic near-copy of a person who is already living
or has already lived. This might constrain the clone's sense of
self in ways that differ in kind from the experience of identical
twins. Everything about the predecessor from physical height
and facial appearance, balding patterns and inherited diseases,
to temperament and native talents, to shape of life and length of
days, and even cause of death will appear before the expectant
eyes of the cloned person, always with at least the nagging concern
that there, notwithstanding the grace of God, go I. The crucial
matter, again, is not simply the truth regarding the extent to which
genetic identity actually shapes us though it surely does
shape us to some extent. What matters is the cloned individual's
perception of the significance of the "precedent life"
and the way that perception cramps and limits a sense of self and
independence.
2. Concerns regarding Manufacture
The likely impact of cloning on identity suggests an additional
moral and social concern: the transformation of human procreation
into human manufacture, of begetting into making. By using the terms
"making" and "manufacture" we are not claiming that cloned children
would be artifacts made altogether "by hand" or produced in factories.
Rather, we are suggesting that they would, like other human "products,"
be brought into being in accordance with some pre-selected genetic
pattern or design, and therefore in some sense "made to order" by
their producers or progenitors.
Unlike natural procreation or even most forms of assisted
reproduction cloning-to-produce-children would set out to
create a child with a very particular genotype: namely, that of
the somatic cell donor. Cloned children would thus be the first
human beings whose entire genetic makeup is selected in advance.
True, selection from among existing genotypes is not yet design
of new ones. But the principle that would be established by human
cloning is both far-reaching and completely novel: parents, with
the help of science and technology, may determine in advance the
genetic endowment of their children. To this point, parents have
the right and the power to decide whether to have a child.
With cloning, parents acquire the power, and presumably the right,
to decide what kind of a child to have. Cloning would thus
extend the power of one generation over the next and the power
of parents over their offspring in ways that open the door,
unintentionally or not, to a future project of genetic manipulation
and genetic control.
Of course, there is no denying that we have already taken steps
in the direction of such control. Preimplantation genetic diagnosis
of embryos and prenatal diagnosis of fetuses both now used
to prevent the birth of individuals carrying genes for genetic diseases
reflect an only conditional acceptance of the next generation.
With regard to positive selection for desired traits, some
people already engage in the practice of sex selection, another
example of conditional acceptance of offspring. But these precedents
pale in comparison to the degree of control provided by cloning
and, in any case, do not thereby provide a license to proceed with
cloning. It is far from clear that it would be wise to proceed still
farther in our attempts at control.
The problem with cloning-to-produce-children is not that artificial
technique is used to assist reproduction. Neither is it that genes
are being manipulated. We raise no objection to the use of the coming
genetic technologies to treat individuals with genetic diseases,
even in utero though there would be issues regarding the protection
of human subjects in research and the need to find boundaries between
therapy and so-called enhancement (of this, more below). The problem
has to do with the control of the entire genotype and the production
of children to selected specifications.
Why does this matter? It matters because human dignity is at stake.
In natural procreation, two individuals give life to a new human
being whose endowments are not shaped deliberately by human will,
whose being remains mysterious, and the open-endedness of whose
future is ratified and embraced. Parents beget a child who enters
the world exactly as they did as an unmade gift, not as a
product. Children born of this process stand equally beside their
progenitors as fellow human beings, not beneath them as made objects.
In this way, the uncontrolled beginnings of human procreation endow
each new generation and each new individual with the dignity and
freedom enjoyed by all who came before.
Most present forms of assisted reproduction imitate this natural
process. While they do begin to introduce characteristics of manufacture
and industrial technique, placing nascent human life for the first
time in human hands, they do not control the final outcome. The
end served by IVF is still the same as natural reproduction-the
birth of a child from the union of gametes from two progenitors.
Reproduction with the aid of such techniques still implicitly expresses
a willingness to accept as a gift the product of a process we do
not control. In IVF children emerge out of the same mysterious process
from which their parents came, and are therefore not mere creatures
of their parents.
By contrast, cloning-to-produce-children and the forms of
human manufacture it might make more possible in the future
seems quite different. Here, the process begins with a very specific
final product in mind and would be tailored to produce that product.
Even were cloning to be used solely to remedy infertility, the decision
to clone the (sterile) father would be a decision, willy-nilly,
that the child-to-be should be the near-twin of his "father." Anyone
who would clone merely to ensure a "biologically related child"
would be dictating a very specific form of biological relation:
genetic virtual identity. In every case of cloning-to-produce-children,
scientists or parents would set out to produce specific individuals
for particular reasons. The procreative process could come to be
seen increasingly as a means of meeting specific ends, and the resulting
children would be products of a designed manufacturing process,
products over whom we might think it proper to exercise "quality
control." Even if, in any given case, we were to continue to think
of the cloned child as a gift, the act itself teaches a different
lesson, as the child becomes the continuation of a parental
project. We would learn to receive the next generation less with
gratitude and surprise than with control and mastery.
One possible result would be the industrialization and commercialization
of human reproduction. Manufactured objects become commodities in
the marketplace, and their manufacture comes to be guided by market
principles and financial concerns. When the "products" are human
beings, the "market" could become a profoundly dehumanizing force.
Already there is commerce in egg donation for IVF, with ads offering
large sums of money for egg donors with high SAT scores and particular
physical features.
The concerns expressed here do not depend on cloning becoming
a widespread practice. The introduction of the terms and ideas of
production into the realm of human procreation would be troubling
regardless of the scale involved; and the adoption of a market mentality
in these matters could blind us to the deep moral character of bringing
forth new life. Even were cloning children to be rare, the moral
harms to a society that accepted it could be serious.
3. Prospect of a New Eugenics
For some of us, cloning-to-produce-children also raises concerns
about the prospect of eugenics or, more modestly, about genetic
"enhancement." We recognize that the term "eugenics" generally refers
to attempts to improve the genetic constitution of a particular
political community or of the human race through general policies
such as population control, forced sterilization, directed mating,
or the like. It does not ordinarily refer to actions of particular
individuals attempting to improve the genetic endowment of their
own descendants. Yet, although cloning does not in itself point
to public policies by which the state would become involved in directing
the development of the human gene pool, this might happen in illiberal
regimes, like China, where the government already regulates procreation.vii
And, in liberal societies, cloning-to-produce-children could come
to be used privately for individualized eugenic or "enhancement"
purposes: in attempts to alter (with the aim of improving) the genetic
constitution of one's own descendants and, indirectly, of
future generations.
Some people, in fact, see enhancement as the major purpose of
cloning-to-produce-children. Those who favor eugenics and genetic
enhancement were once far more open regarding their intentions to
enable future generations to enjoy more advantageous genotypes.
Toward these ends, they promoted the benefits of cloning: escape
from the uncertain lottery of sex, controlled and humanly directed
reproduction. In the present debate about cloning-to-produce-children,
the case for eugenics and enhancement is not made openly, but it
nonetheless remains an important motivation for some advocates.
Should cloning-to-produce-children be introduced successfully, and
should it turn out that the cloned humans do in fact inherit many
of the natural talents of the "originals," some people may become
interested in the prospects of using it to produce "enhanced children"
especially if other people's children were receiving comparable
advantages.
Cloning can serve the ends of individualized enhancement either
by avoiding the genetic defects that may arise when human reproduction
is left to chance or by preserving and perpetuating outstanding
genetic traits. In the future, if techniques of genetic enhancement
through more precise genetic engineering became available, cloning
could be useful for perpetuating the enhanced traits and for keeping
any "superior" manmade genotype free of the flaws that sexual reproduction
might otherwise introduce.
"Private eugenics" does not carry with it the dark implications
of state despotism or political control of the gene pool that characterized
earlier eugenic proposals and the racist eugenic practices of the
twentieth century. Nonetheless, it could prove dangerous to our
humanity. Besides the dehumanizing prospects of the turn toward
manufacture that such programs of enhancement would require, there
is the further difficulty of the lack of standards to guide the
choices for "improvement." To this point, biomedical technology
has been applied to treating diseases in patients and has been governed,
on the whole, by a commonsense view of health and disease. To be
sure, there are differing views about how to define "health." And
certain cosmetic, performance enhancing, or hedonistic uses
of biomedical techniques have already crossed any plausible boundary
between therapy and enhancement, between healing the sick and "improving"
our powers.viii
Yet, for the most part, it is by some commonsense views of health
that we judge who is in need of medical treatment and what sort
of treatment might be most appropriate. Even today's practice of
a kind of "negative" eugenics through prenatal genetic diagnosis
and abortion of fetuses with certain genetic abnormalities
is informed by the desire to promote health.
The "positive" eugenics that could receive a great boost from
human cloning, especially were it to be coupled with techniques
of precise genetic modification, would not seek to restore sick
human beings to natural health. Instead, it would seek to alter
humanity, based upon subjective or arbitrary ideas of excellence.
The effort may be guided by apparently good intentions: to improve
the next generation and to enhance the quality of life of our descendants.
But in the process of altering human nature, we would be abandoning
the standard by which to judge the goodness or the wisdom of the
particular aims. We would stand to lose the sense of what is and
is not human.
The fear of a new eugenics is not, as is sometimes alleged, a
concern born of some irrational fear of the future or the unknown.
Neither is it born of hostility to technology or nostalgia for some
premodern pseudo-golden age of superior naturalness. It is rather
born of the rational recognition that once we move beyond therapy
into efforts at enhancement, we are in uncharted waters without
a map, without a compass, and without a clear destination that can
tell us whether we are making improvements or the reverse. The time-honored
and time-tested goods of human life, which we know to be good, would
be put in jeopardy for the alleged and unknowable goods of a post-human
future.
4. Troubled Family Relations
Cloning-to-produce-children could also prove damaging to family
relations, despite the best of intentions. We do not assume that
cloned children, once produced, would not be accepted, loved, or
nurtured by their parents and relatives. On the contrary, we freely
admit that, like any child, they might be welcomed into the cloning
family. Nevertheless, the cloned child's place in the scheme of
family relations might well be uncertain and confused. The usually
clear designations of father and brother, mother and sister, would
be confounded. A mother could give birth to her own genetic twin,
and a father could be genetically virtually identical to his son.
The cloned child's relation to his or her grandparents would span
one and two generations at once. Every other family relation would
be similarly confused. There is, of course, the valid counter-argument
that holds that the "mother" could easily be defined as the person
who gives birth to the child, regardless of the child's genetic
origins, and for social purposes that may serve to eliminate some
problems. But because of the special nature of cloning-to-produce-children,
difficulties may be expected.
The crucial point is not the absence of the natural biological
connections between parents and children. The crucial point is,
on the contrary, the presence of a unique, one-sided, and replicative
biological connection to only one progenitor. As a result, family
relations involving cloning would differ from all existing family
arrangements, including those formed through adoption or with the
aid of IVF. A great many children, after all, are adopted, and live
happy lives in loving families, in the absence of any biological
connections with their parents. Children conceived by artificial
insemination using donor sperm and by various IVF techniques may
have unusual relationships with their genetic parents, or no genetic
relationships at all. But all of these existing arrangements attempt
in important ways to emulate the model of the natural family (at
least in its arrangement of the generations), while cloning runs
contrary to that model.
What the exact effects of cloning-to-produce-children might be
for families is highly speculative, to be sure, but it is still
worth flagging certain troubling possibilities and risks. The fact
that the cloned child bears a special tie to only one parent may
complicate family dynamics. As the child developed, it could not
help but be regarded as specially akin to only one of his or her
parents. The sins or failings of the father (or mother), if reappearing
in the cloned child, might be blamed on the progenitor, adding to
the chances of domestic turmoil. The problems of being and rearing
an adolescent could become complicated should the teenage clone
of the mother "reappear" as the double of the woman the father once
fell in love with. Risks of competition, rivalry, jealousy, and
parental tension could become heightened.ix
Even if the child were cloned from someone who is not a member
of the family in which the child is raised, the fact would remain
that he or she has been produced in the nearly precise genetic image
of another and for some particular reason, with some particular
design in mind. Should this become known to the child, as most likely
it would, a desire to seek out connection to the "original" could
complicate his or her relation to the rearing family, as would living
consciously "under the reason" for this extra-familial choice of
progenitor. Though many people make light of the importance of biological
kinship (compared to the bonds formed through rearing and experienced
family life), many adopted children and children conceived by artificial
insemination or IVF using donor sperm show by their actions that
they do not agree. They make great efforts to locate their "biological
parents," even where paternity consists in nothing more than the
donation of sperm. Where the progenitor is a genetic near-twin,
surely the urge of the cloned child to connect with the unknown
"parent" would be still greater.
For all these reasons, the cloning family differs from the "natural
family" or the "adoptive family." By breaking through the natural
boundaries between generations, cloning could strain the social
ties between them.
5. Effects on Society
The hazards and costs of cloning-to-produce-children may not be
confined to the direct participants. The rest of society may also
be at risk. The impact of human cloning on society at large may
be the least appreciated, but among the most important, factors
to consider in contemplating the morality of this activity.
Cloning is a human activity affecting not only those who are cloned
or those who are clones, but also the entire society that allows
or supports such activity. For insofar as the society accepts cloning-to-produce-children,
to that extent the society may be said to engage in it. A society
that allows dehumanizing practices especially when given an
opportunity to try to prevent them risks becoming an accomplice
in those practices. (The same could be said of a society that allowed
even a few of its members to practice incest or polygamy.) Thus
the question before us is whether cloning-to-produce-children is
an activity that we, as a society, should engage in. In addressing
this question, we must reach well beyond the rights of individuals
and the difficulties or benefits that cloned children or their families
might encounter. We must consider what kind of a society we wish
to be, and, in particular, what forms of bringing children into
the world we want to encourage and what sorts of relations between
the generations we want to preserve.
Cloning-to-produce-children could distort the way we raise and
view children, by carrying to full expression many regrettable tendencies
already present in our culture. We are already liable to regard
children largely as vehicles for our own fulfillment and ambitions.
The impulse to create "designer children" is present today
as temptation and social practice. The notion of life as a gift,
mysterious and limited, is under siege. Cloning-to-produce-children
would carry these tendencies and temptations to an extreme expression.
It advances the notion that the child is but an object of our sovereign
mastery.
A society that clones human beings thinks about human beings (and
especially children) differently than does a society that refuses
to do so. It could easily be argued that we have already in myriad
ways begun to show signs of regarding our children as projects on
which we may work our wills. Further, it could be argued that we
have been so desensitized by our earlier steps in this direction
that we do not recognize this tendency as a corruption. While some
people contend that cloning-to-produce-children would not take us
much further down a path we have already been traveling, we would
emphasize that the precedent of treating children as projects cuts
two ways in the moral argument. Instead of using this precedent
to justify taking the next step of cloning, the next step might
rather serve as a warning and a mirror in which we may discover
reasons to reconsider what we are already doing. Precisely because
the stakes are so high, precisely because the new biotechnologies
touch not only our bodies and minds but also the very idea of our
humanity, we should ask ourselves how we as a society want to approach
questions of human dignity and flourishing.
D. Conclusion
Cloning-to-produce-children may represent a forerunner of what
will be a growing number of capacities to intervene in and alter
the human genetic endowment. No doubt, earlier human actions have
produced changes in the human gene pool: to take only one example,
the use of insulin to treat diabetics who otherwise would have died
before reproducing has increased the genes for diabetes in the population.
But different responsibilities accrue when one sets out to make
such changes prospectively, directly, and deliberately. To do so
without regard for the likelihood of serious unintended and unanticipated
consequences would be the height of hubris. Systems of great complexity
do not respond well to blunt human intervention, and one can hardly
think of a more complex system both natural and social
than that which surrounds human reproduction and the human genome.
Given the enormous importance of what is at stake, we believe that
the so-called "precautionary principle" should be our guide in this
arena. This principle would suggest that scientists, technologists,
and, indeed, all of us should be modest in claiming to understand
the many possible consequences of any profound alteration of human
procreation, especially where there are not compelling reasons to
proceed. Lacking such understanding, no one should take action so
drastic as the cloning of a human child. In the absence of the necessary
human wisdom, prudence calls upon us to set limits on efforts to
control and remake the character of human procreation and human
life.
It is not only a matter of prudence. Cloning-to-produce-children
would also be an injustice to the cloned child from the imposition
of the chromosomes of someone else, to the intentional deprivation
of biological parents, to all of the possible bodily and psychological
harms that we have enumerated in this chapter. It is ultimately
the claim that the cloned child would be seriously wronged
and not only harmed in body that would justify government
intervention. It is to this question the public policy question
of what the government should and can do to prevent such injustice
that we will turn in Chapter
Seven. But, regarding the ethical assessment, Members of the
Council are in unanimous agreement that cloning-to-produce-children
is not only unsafe but also morally unacceptable and ought not to
be attempted.x
ENDNOTES
- National Bioethics Advisory Commission, Cloning Human Beings
Bethesda, MD, 1997. Back
to Text
- National Academy of Sciences (NAS) Scientific and Medical
Aspects of Human Reproductive Cloning, Washington, DC: National
Academy Press, 2002. (Referred to in subsequent citations as NAS
Report.) Back
to Text
- NAS Report, pp. 6-7. Back
to Text
- Lederberg, J. "Experimental Genetics and Human Evolution" The
American Naturalist, September-October 1966. Back
to Text
- Supreme Court of the United States. Eisenstadt v. Baird,
405 US 438, 1972. Back
to Text
- Tribe, L. "On Not Banning Cloning for the Wrong Reasons" in
Nussbaum, M., and C. R. Sunstein. Clones and Clones: Facts
and Fantasies about Human Cloning. New York: Norton, 1998,
p. 321. Back
to Text
- Nuremberg Report. Trials of War Criminals before the Nuremberg
Military Tribunals under Control Council Law No. 10, Vol. 2, pp.
181-182. Washington, DC: Government Printing Office, 1949.
Back
to Text
- Helsinki Declaration. 18th World Medical Association General
Assembly Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving
Human Subjects, adopted in Helsinki, Finland, June 1964,
and amended in October 1975, October 1983, September 1989, October
1996, and October 2000. Back
to Text
- Belmont Report. The National Commission for the Protection of
Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. The
Belmont Report: Ethical Principles and Guidelines for the Protection
of Human Subjects of Research. Bethesda, MD: Government Printing
Office, 1978. Back
to Text
- See, for instance, Chapter
Four of the present report, as well as Chapter 3 of the NAS
Report. Back
to Text
- These issues are discussed in the NAS Report (3-2) as well as
in Wilmut, I., Roslin Institute, Scotland. "Application of animal
cloning data to human cloning," paper presented at Workshop:
Scientific and Medical Aspects of Human Cloning, National Academy
of Sciences, Washington, DC August 7, 2001; and Hill, J.,
Cornell University. "Placental defects in nuclear transfer (cloned)
animals," paper presented at Workshop: Scientific and Medical
Aspects of Human Cloning, National Academy of Sciences, Washington,
DC, August 7, 2001. Back
to Text
- See, for instance, Chapter 3 of the NAS Report, and Kolata,
G. "In Cloning, Failure Far Exceeds Success" New York Times,
December 11, 2001, p. D1. Back
to Text
- See, for instance, Rimington, M., et al. "Counseling patients
undergoing ovarian stimulation about the risks of ovarian hyper-stimulation
syndrome." Human Reproduction, 14: 2921-2922, 1999; and
Wakeley, K., and E. Grendys. "Reproductive technologies and risk
of ovarian cancer." Current Opinion in Obstetrics and Gynecology,
12: 43-47, 2000. Back
to Text
- These issues are discussed in greater detail in Chapter 3 of
the NAS Report. Back
to Text
- Hill J.R., et al. "Clinical and pathologic features of cloned
transgenic calves and fetuses (13 case studies)" Theriogenology
8: 1451-1465, 1999. Back
to Text
- NAS Report, p. 3-2. Back
to Text
- NAS Report, Figure 3. Back
to Text
- See for instance the NAS Report, Appendix B, tables 1, 3, and
4. Back
to Text
_____________________
- Consider the following analogy: We would not allow a rare sympathetic
case for brother-sister marriage-where, say, the two children
were separated at birth and later fell in love, ignorant of their
kinship-to overturn the taboo on incest. Whatever their merit,
the goals of well-being and health do not outweigh the moral and
social harms that cloning would entail. Back
to Text
- It is of course true that there is always uncertainty about
moving from animal to human experimentation or therapy. But in
the usual case, what justifies the assumption of this added unknown
risk is that the experimental subject is a likely beneficiary
of the research, either directly or indirectly. And where this
is not the case, risk may be assumed if there is informed and
voluntary consent. Neither of these conditions applies for the
child-to-be in human cloning experiments. Back
to Text
- Surprisingly, there has been very little systematic study of
the offspring of in vitro fertilization. One recently published
study has suggested that IVF (and especially intracytoplasmic
sperm injection [ICSI]) may not be as benign as we had thought
(Hansen, M., et al., "The Risk of Major Birth Defects after Intracytoplasmic
Sperm Injection and In Vitro Fertilization," New Eng. J. Med.
346: 725-730, 2002). Back
to Text
- The argument made in this paragraph is not unique to cloning.
There may be other circumstances in which prospective parents,
about to impose great risk of harm on a prospective child-to-be,
might bear a comparable burden. Back
to Text
- Such improvements in technique could result in part from the
practice of cloning-for-biomedical-research, were it to be allowed
to go forward. This possibility is one of the issues we shall
consider in evaluating the ethics of cloning-for-biomedical-research
in Chapter Six.
Back
to Text
- We are, of course, well aware that many children are conceived
in casual, loveless, or even brutal acts of sexual intercourse,
including rape and incest. Back
to Text
- According to official Chinese census figures for 2000, more
than 116 male births were recorded for every 100 female births.
It is generally believed that this is the result of the widespread
use of prenatal sex selection and China's one-child policy, though
it should be noted that even in a country such as South Korea,
which has no such policy, the use of prenatal sex selection has
skewed the sex ratio in favor of males. Back
to Text
- One thinks of certain forms of plastic surgery or recreational
uses of euphoriant drugs, and the uses in athletics and schools
of performance-enhancing drugs, such as anabolic steroids, erythropoietin,
and Ritalin. Back
to Text
- And there might be special complications in the event of divorce.
Does the child rightfully or more naturally belong to the "genetic
parent"? How would a single parent deal with a child who shares
none of her genes but carries 100 percent of the genes of the
person she chose to divorce? Whether such foreseeable complications
would in fact emerge is, of course, an empirical question that
cannot be answered in advance. But knowledge of the complexities
of family life lead us not to want to dismiss them. Back
to Text
- Not surprisingly, some of us feel more strongly than others
about this conclusion. One or two of us might someday be willing
to see cloning-to-produce-children occur in the rare defensible
case, but then only if means were available to confine its use
to such cases. Back
to Text
Chapter Six
The Ethics of Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research
I. The Manner and Spirit of This Inquiry
The question of whether or not to proceed with human cloning-for-biomedical-research
is a morally serious and difficult one. On the one hand, there is
the promise that such research could lead to important knowledge
of human embryological development and gene action, especially in
cases in which there are genetic abnormalities that lead to disease.
There is also the promise that such research could contribute to
producing transplantable tissues and organs that could be effective
in curing or reversing many dreaded illnesses and injuries
including Parkinson's disease, Alzheimer's disease, juvenile diabetes,
and spinal cord injury. On the other hand, there are the morally
relevant facts that this research involves the deliberate production,
use, and ultimate destruction of cloned human embryos, and that
the cloned embryos produced for research are no different from cloned
embryos that could be used in attempts to produce cloned children.
Complicating the moral assessment are questions about the likelihood
that this research will deliver its promised benefits and about
the possibility of equally promising, yet morally less problematic,
approaches to the same scientific and medical goals. Finally, there
is the ever-present danger of creating false hope among patients,
and the risk of allowing the goodness of the end (finding cures
for disease) to justify moral indifference to the means used to
achieve it. Morally serious people may differ in their final judgment
of the ethics of cloning-for-biomedical-research. But they do
or should agree on this: that fidelity both to the highest
moral and human aspirations of science and medicine and to the moral
standards of the wider community requires that we consider not only
why and how to proceed with new lines of research, but also whether
there might be compelling reasons not to do so or certain limits
that should be observed. Both the facts (scientific and moral) and
our ethical principles must be consulted in trying to judge what
is best.
Yet despite this general agreement, it is difficult to know how
best to proceed in the present case. There are multiple questions
about the right context for considering the ethics of cloning-for-biomedical-research.
First, we must weigh whether to take up this matter in the context
of deciding what to do about cloning-to-produce-children or in the
somewhat different context of the ethics of embryo and stem cell
research more generally. The issue has in fact emerged in the public
moral debate over anti-cloning legislation, as a complication in
the effort to stop cloning-to-produce-children. Generally speaking,
the most effective way to prevent cloning-to-produce-children would
arguably be to stop the process at the initial act of cloning, the
production (by an act of somatic cell nuclear transfer [SCNT]) of
the embryonic human clone. Yet such a measure would rule out cloning-for-biomedical-research,
and many scientists and patient advocacy groups have argued that
the human and moral costs of doing so are too great. Alternatively,
we could take up this matter in what seems philosophically to be
its more natural context, namely, as a sub-species of a larger inquiry
into the ethics of embryo and stem cell research.
Each of these contexts what to do about cloning-to-produce-children
and what to do about embryo research is certainly plausible.
Yet each, by itself, is less than satisfactory. The first risks
giving excessive weight to the fact that the embryos wanted for
research are cloned embryos; the second, ignoring the aspect
(central to cloning) of genetic manipulation, risks the
opposite error by requiring that the ethics of cloning-for-biomedical-research
be argued entirely in terms of what it is proper to do with embryos
as such. We can imagine, in advance of any discussion, a variety
of moral opinions that would emerge, influenced in part by how the
question is formulated: one person could defend stem cell research
performed using embryos produced by IVF but oppose research using
cloned embryos for reasons of prudence (such as decreasing the likelihood
of cloning-to-produce-children). Another person, holding IVF embryos
in higher regard than cloned embryos, could reach precisely the
opposite conclusion. Some people will hold that research on any
human embryo, cloned or not, is always morally unacceptable (or
acceptable), independent of whether ethical or legal guidelines
are in place, while others will judge one way or another depending
on whether appropriate guidelines and effective regulations have
been established.
We have decided to discuss the ethics of cloning-for-biomedical-research
in the broader moral philosophical context, rather than the
narrower moral political one that has taken shape around the
current debate over anti-cloning legislation. Though we are mindful
of the importance of these public policy debates and will
consider them in the following chapter we do not want our
moral analysis to be skewed by the specific legal or policy questions
at issue, especially as the moral questions discussed here have
implications beyond the current political debate and even beyond
the question of human cloning itself. We opt to take up the moral
questions in their fullness.
A second question about context is even more difficult to assess.
Should we regard cloning-for-biomedical-research as just the latest
and continuous step in trying to unlock the secrets
of human development and to discover cures for diseases? Or should
it be seen instead or also as the earliest stage of
a revolutionary new science of enhancement or eugenics, which will
go beyond treating individuals with disease and disability to attempt
engineered improvements in human genetic endowments? Because innovations
like cloning come to us gradually and piecemeal, and because it
cannot be known in advance how exactly they will be used or where
they might lead, there is a temptation to stay close to the present
and to ignore possible future implications.
Yet the alleged perils of going ahead with the research are arguably
no more speculative than the promised benefits. And it would be
morally and prudently shortsighted for this Council, charged with
investigating "the human and moral significance of advances in biomedical
science and technology," to refuse to think about where this research
might lead. We will therefore consider, even if we cannot know in
advance, whether and how the sort of genetic manipulation of embryos
exemplified by cloning-for-biomedical-research is new or "revolutionary."
Genetic therapy for existing diseases and non-therapeutic genetic
modifications of our native endowments raise profoundly different
questions. Accordingly, we will keep in sight not only the moral
questions surrounding the means of cloning-for-biomedical-research
which is to say, the significance of using or not using nascent
human life as a resource but also the possible ends
to which our expanding knowledge and capacities might be put. At
the same time, we will be careful not to equate genetic medicine
that is truly in the service of human life with genetic manipulation
that is not, and to avoid both the unjustified fear and exaggerated
promises that sometimes accompany biomedical progress.
A third difficulty concerns the relation between the ethics of
research on embryos (cloned or not) and the ethics of abortion.
For many people, these issues are linked, and there is doubtless
an overlap in the moral questions involved. Yet the issues are,
in important respects, quite distinct. In the case of abortion,
the fetuses whose fate is at issue are unwanted and (usually) the
result of unintended conception. The embryos produced for research
are wanted, indeed deliberately created, with certain knowledge
and intent that they will be used and destroyed. More important
perhaps, the extra-corporeal embryo (whether produced specially
for research or left-over in IVF procedures) does not exist in conflict
with the wishes, interests, or rights of a woman who is pregnant.
Also, although abortion is widely practiced, each decision to abort
is made one at a time, case by case. In contrast, to embark on creating
cloned embryos only for purposes of research is to countenance at
one stroke the large-scale production of developing human life for
routinized use and destruction. For these reasons, we shall try
to consider the question of the ethics of research on embryos in
its own terms, distinct from the ethical questions about abortion.
Finally, there is the question of the spirit in which this examination
should be conducted. Reflecting the situation in American society,
there are major differences within the Council regarding the morality
of research involving early human (cloned) embryos. These differences
turn largely, though not exclusively, on different judgments regarding
the nature and moral status of the early human (cloned) embryo:
namely, to what extent is it, or is it not, "one of us," a human
life in process? Having explored these questions collegially among
ourselves, we have come to think that all parties to this
debate have something vital to defend, something vital not only
to themselves but also to their opponents in the debate,
and indeed to all human beings. No human being and no human society
can afford to be callous to the needs of suffering humanity, cavalier
regarding the treatment of nascent human life, or indifferent to
the social effects of adopting in these matters one course of action
rather than another.
We believe, therefore, that we can make our best contribution to
a truthful and appropriate moral understanding of the issue by developing,
in a single document, the moral cases both for and against
proceeding with cloning-for-biomedical-research (and also articulating,
where necessary and as clearly as possible, important differences
within each of these cases). Each Member of the Council has been
asked to help strengthen the case made for both sides, regardless
of which side he or she inclines toward. By proceeding in this way,
we hope to make clear to the President and the nation exactly what
is morally and humanly at stake in the controversy and what may
be gained and lost in whatever choice is finally made.
Thus, notwithstanding our differences, we stand together as the
authors of the entire chapter, hoping by this means to shed light
rather than heat on this most vexing of moral and policy questions.
At the same time, we have tried fully and fairly to articulate our
differences, and to do so by speaking, in the first person, as members
of a deliberative body called upon to make our own best judgments.
This means that the "we" that now embraces all Members of the
Council will stand in the particular sections presenting the moral
case for and the moral case against cloning-for-biomedical-research
(Parts III and IV, respectively), only for
those among us who subscribe to the specific arguments being made
in those sections. In other words, each opinion is a self-contained
brief, representing not the Council as a whole but only a portion
of the Council. And even within the cases for and against, Members
of the Council disagree over matters of substance and emphasis.
But while the Council has strong differences of opinion, as delineated
in the sections that follow, the Council speaks in a single voice
in its affirmation that the debate must not be won by dismissing,
ridiculing, or demonizing the other side. Important human goods
are to be found on all sides of the debate, a fact too often overlooked.
We begin, in Part II, with a discussion of the human meaning of
healing, for it is only by an analysis of this uniquely human activity
that the contours of the debate over cloning-for-biomedical-research
can be properly traced and understood. Here the Council speaks as
one. What follows this framing discussion are two separate opinions:
in Part III, a portion of Council Members make the moral case for
biomedical research; in Part IV, a portion make the opposing moral
case against. Going beyond just listing the arguments, pro and con,
each opinion is a sustained attempt at moral suasion. Yet each opinion,
by self-imposed stricture, has tried to respect and respond to the
legitimate moral concerns of the other side and to indicate how
it means to do them justice. Each has tried to address what is owed
to embryonic human life, what is owed to suffering humanity, and
what is owed to the moral well-being of society. This approach to
public moral discourse is, we are well aware, an experiment. Whether
it is successful or not is for the reader to judge.
* * *
II. The Human Meaning of Healing
Before presenting the two opinions, we will place the moral questions
surrounding cloning-for-biomedical-research in their larger human
context. Just as we did in discussing the ethics of cloning-to-produce-children,
we step back from the particular technological possibility at hand
to look carefully at the larger human goods that we seek both to
serve and defend. We look specifically at the human meaning of healing
the sick and aiding the suffering, as well as the spirit and practice
of biomedical research that aims to make such healing possible.
This exploration will better prepare us to see what is humanly at
stake in our moral judgment about cloning-for-biomedical-research,
and to face soberly both what is gained and what is lost in either
proceeding or not proceeding. The subsequent moral arguments, both
pro and con, are informed by these larger reflections.
To be human is to be mortal. To be alive is to be vulnerable to
suffering. No one is better situated to appreciate these truths
than the physician. To understand what it means to heal, one must
therefore understand the doctor's special encounter with human suffering
as both an experience (a crying out) of the patient who lies
before him and as a central mystery of human existence. Why do human
beings suffer? Why do they suffer in ways that cannot be explained
entirely or perhaps at all with human notions of justice?
In this role, the doctor is sometimes a messenger of human
finitude. He must tell patients that their days are numbered or
that their time has come; he must tell grieving family members that
death is at the door. But the healer is also and more importantly
in the eyes of both doctor and patient a deliverer.
Not only is he well armed to deliver us from specific maladies and
miseries. He is also a much needed ally against the deadly disease
traditionally regarded as a sin of despair. Because
of the moral aspirations of his calling, the physician is a trusted
source of hope that the living might yet still live and that in
his skill and the powerful techniques of modern medicine might lie
the possibility of renewal. The doctor is, at different times, a
reminder of the intractable sadness of human life, but also explicitly
a conqueror who beats back suffering and disease with the saving
hand of medical knowledge and technique, and who inspirits us with
hope to go forward even in the absence of cure and relief.
Until roughly the second half of the twentieth century, physicians
delivered more hope than cure, and they conquered few diseases.
Since then, their arsenal against disease (at least in technologically
advanced nations) has grown enormously, and it promises to grow
greater in the decades ahead. New healing powers will surely emerge
from the work of medicine's ally, biomedical research, firmly grounded
in the principles and methods of modern biomedical science. This
noble field of human endeavor also has a context in the larger domain
of human life. Celebrating its achievements and eager for its gifts
to human welfare, modern societies embrace and invest heavily in
medical research and grant scientists great freedom to inquire and
experiment. Because of the way science advances, freedom is crucial
to the successful realization of its goals.
Dr. William Osler, one of the founding figures of modern medicine,
described the aspirations of biomedical research as follows:
To wrest from nature the secrets which have perplexed
philosophers in all ages, to track to their sources the causes of
disease, to correlate the vast stores of knowledge that they may
be quickly available for the prevention and cure of disease
These are our ambitions.1
It is in the very nature of a "secret" that one cannot know in
advance which areas of research and discovery will prove the most
fruitful. One proceeds by trial and error. One makes hypotheses
grounded in what is already known, in the effort to discover what
remains a mystery. One begins with basic research into disease processes
and mechanisms, in the hope that new knowledge will yield new medicines
and new cures.
One motive for such research is simply the love of knowledge itself
the distinctively human desire to know, to see, to understand
more than one already does. But biomedical research is also guided,
above all, by the humanitarian desire to apply new knowledge in
the service of those who suffer, to correlate knowledge that it
"may be quickly available for the prevention and cure of disease."
Biomedical scientists aim to weld the virtues of charity, beneficence,
and responsibility to the human ambition to "wrest from nature"
her secrets. This is the moral heart of both the medical profession
and the research tradition that supports it: to do everything in
our power, consistent with law and morals, to provide cures, amelioration,
and relief to those who need them.
"Consistent with law and morals": this requirement qualifies "everything
in our power." This limitation has been traditionally understood
to be part of the healing vocation. Moral philosophers and philosophers
of medicine have long held that the duty to heal is an "imperfect
duty," meaning that it does not trump all other considerations.
Physicians perhaps understand this best of all, learning their limits
empirically from their encounters with patients whom they cannot
save or even comfort. The duty to heal this patient, at
this time, is also an imperfect one. After all, a cure for
one person at the direct expense of another for example, harvesting
a vital organ from someone who is living to save someone else who
is dying would violate the first principle of medicine to
"do no harm."
It is also true that scientific freedom and medical progress are
not the only human goods worthy of our commitment and protection.
Research must be judged both by the means it employs and by the
ends it serves (both those that were intended and those that were
not). The Nuremberg Code, the Helsinki Declaration, and the Belmont
Report, discussed in the last chapter, are all efforts to set moral
limits on biomedical research and to ensure that science serves
human beings rather than the other way around. Among other things,
these ethical codes embody the recognition that those who do research
about human beings can never escape (nor should they) their
status as human beings. Those who investigate human biology
are always both the knowers and the subject that
is known, both the potential healers and the potentially afflicted.
And therefore they must never treat that which is their equal
their fellow human beings as something less than human.
But in the end, however imperfect it is as a duty and whatever
its less than supreme place among all other human goods, the obligation
to heal and to seek remedies is a powerful one. It is a mark both
of man's natural limits (as the being in need of healing) and his
capacity for goodness (as the being who heals). And so, the freedom
of inquiry that makes biomedical research possible should be restricted
only for the most important reasons, lest we do damage to the entire
enterprise, or to the human beings and the society that benefit
from the "vast stores of knowledge" it creates.
At the same time, however, those who have accepted the "healer's
covenant" and those who defend, engage in, and benefit from
the research that improves and expands the human capacity to heal
must avoid the seduction of medical triumphalism: the belief
that all human suffering, both physical and psychic, can be conquered
by modern technique, and therefore that no form of biomedical research
should be opposed. Doctors and scientists must not become partial
human beings who evade moral responsibility by claiming that they
are not qualified to judge the moral implications of their own medical
research or, worse, that medically beneficial research is always
self-justifying, and hence that there are no real moral dilemmas
at all. In addition, they must avoid the cruelty of creating false
hopes among patients and their loved ones, and the folly of creating
messianic or utopian visions of what science and medicine can accomplish.
And patients, even as they heroically fight against suffering, must
not forget their own mortality including the often unpredictable
nature of how and when death comes.
These reflections point to the following conclusions: In judging
the moral beneficence and moral hazards of medical research, we
must remember that suffering should not be opposed by any means
possible. We would be less than human if we did not desire to alleviate
such suffering, but we would be imagining ourselves to be more than
human if we thought and acted as if we could alleviate it once and
for all. Rather, we must acknowledge that as human beings we live
in a difficult "in-between." Whether as doctors, scientists, or
as patients, we all wish for the possible renewal of life through
medicine, but also acknowledge that suffering and mortality are
part of being alive. We are morally obliged to seek relief of suffering,
but only in ways that preserve our humanity.
With these realities in mind, this chapter will now take up the
ethics of cloning-for-biomedical-research, and specifically the
moral and human questions raised above: What is owed to those who
suffer from debilitating injuries and diseases? What is owed to
nascent human life? And what is owed to the moral well-being of
society? These are the central questions in the debate, questions
that Members of the Council over the past year struggled to answer,
and that indeed every member of society must ponder when considering
the ethics of cloning-for-biomedical-research.
* * * A note about how the remainder of the chapter proceeds:
Part III, delivered in the voice of some Members of the Council, makes
the case for going forward with cloning-for-biomedical-research. Part
IV, delivered in the voice of other Members of the Council, presents
the opposing case, the argument against cloning-for-biomedical-research.
* * *
III. The Moral Case for Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research
The moral case for cloning-for-biomedical-research can be stated
in the following straightforward way: American society and human
communities in general have an obligation to try to heal the sick
and relieve their suffering. This obligation, deeply rooted in the
moral teaching of "love of neighbor," lies heaviest on physicians
and health-care professionals who attend to individual patients.
But it guides also the activities of biomedical scientists and biotechnologists
whose pioneering research and discoveries provide new and better
means of healing and relieving those who suffer. Research on cloned
human embryos is one more path to discovering such means. Like embryonic
stem cell research, to which it is partially related, it offers
a promising approach to gaining knowledge and techniques that could
lead to new treatments for chronic genetic or acquired degenerative
diseases and disabilities.2
If successful, it could help save countless human lives and ameliorate
untold human suffering.
It is true that human cloning-for-biomedical-research raises ethical
questions, mainly because it involves the production, use, and destruction
of cloned human embryos. It is also true that cloned embryos produced
for research could be used in attempts to produce cloned human children,
and the availability of such cloned embryos for research and the
perfection of cloning techniques might increase the likelihood that
people will succeed in cloning children. We appreciate the concerns
of people who voice these objections and risks, and we are prepared
to accept certain limits and safeguards against possible abuses.
Yet we believe that, on balance, the objections to cloning-for-biomedical-research
are outweighed by the good that can be done for current and future
individuals who suffer. The moral balance lies on the side of endorsing
and encouraging this activity.
We who endorse cloning-for-biomedical-research will attempt to
make a version of this case here. But we will do so, for the most
part, in a somewhat different spirit, one that is informed by the
discussion of healing just concluded. In moral debates about these
matters, people often speak as if saving lives is the only value
that counts and that everything else must be sacrificed to advancing
potentially beneficial research. Others speak as if any failure
to prevent death or suffering from disease is sinful. Our defense
of cloning-for-biomedical-research is more complex and nuanced and,
we believe, more true to the merits of the case in question. As
we make our case, we will also confront-and accept-the burden of
what it means to proceed with such research, just as those who oppose
it must accept the burden of what it means not to proceed.
In making our case, we begin in Section A by summarizing the specific
medical benefits that might be achieved by proceeding with this
avenue of research. We then consider in Section B the moral dilemmas
of this research. However, among those of us who believe the research
should go forward there is disagreement about how seriously to take
certain moral objections, and thus two distinct positions for proceeding
are presented.
A. The Medical Promise of Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research
Many people suffer from chronic debilitating diseases and disabilities,
including, among others, juvenile diabetes, Parkinson's disease,
Alzheimer's disease, spinal cord injuries, heart disease, and amyotrophic
lateral sclerosis. These terrible diseases shorten life, limit activity
(often severely), and cause great suffering both for the afflicted
and their families. The inspiring example of exceptional persons
who bear bravely the great burdens of illness or injury should not
blind us to the powerful warrants for research and therapy that
might lift these burdens. The likelihood of premature death, in
particular, can shadow the life of the patient and the patient's
family even before it arrives, and its advent can impoverish and
devastate families, dash hopes, and cast a chill on the lives of
survivors. It is certainly admirable to confront, endure, and redeem
these unchosen afflictions. But it is also admirable, where possible,
to ameliorate through research and medicine the diseases and injuries
that cause them.
Cloning-for-biomedical-research may offer unique ways of investigating
and possibly treating several of these diseases. To unlock the secrets
of a disease, scientists must explore its specific molecular and
cellular mechanisms, carefully observing both normal and pathological
development. This research could be greatly facilitated by in vitro
cellular models of human disease. It is here that the potentially
most valuable and unique benefits of research on cloned human embryos
may lie. This section summarizes some of these benefits, with specific
examples.
1. Cloning to Improve Understanding of Human Disease
The creation of cloned embryos using nuclei from individuals carrying
genetic mutations specifically, genes that predispose them
to particular diseases might be used to better understand
and treat those diseases. Consider, for example, Parkinson's disease.
A characteristic of Parkinson's disease is the aggregation in dying
brain cells of a protein called alpha-synuclein. Two different mutations
in the alpha-synuclein gene produce forms of the protein that aggregate
more readily. Individuals carrying these gene mutations suffer from
early-onset Parkinson's disease.
To study how genetic disease develops, scientists look for suitable
laboratory models. One strategy for producing such disease models
is to inject the disease-causing human genes into human or animal
cells in tissue culture to produce a cell-system expressing the
abnormality. Although it has been possible to introduce copies of
mutant genes into various kinds of human and animal cells, the resulting
in vitro cell-systems imperfectly model the human disease. In part
this is because the behavior of specific proteins within cells is
influenced by their interactions with other cellular proteins. For
example, human alpha-synuclein in a mouse cell cytoplasm interacting
with mouse proteins is unlikely to behave the same way that it does
in a human cell surrounded by human proteins. To study human disease,
it is generally preferable to work with human cells and tissues.
A preferable alternative to introducing mutant genes into normal
cells is to begin with human cells that are already abnormal
in this case, cells carrying the mutant genes that predispose their
bearers to Parkinson's disease. If one could obtain embryonic stem
cells derived from cloned embryos produced using nuclei from individuals
carrying these mutant genes, one could then stimulate them to differentiate
into dopamine producing nerve cells in vitro. These cells
would provide a vastly improved model for understanding the metabolism
of alpha-synuclein and its role in the development of Parkinson's
disease.<i
In this example, the availability of improved in vitro models for
genetic and neurodegenerative diseases could shorten the time required
to understand them and to devise new treatments.
It is true that adult stem cells (or multipotent adult progenitor
cells 3,4
), isolated from patients carrying the mutant genes that predispose
them to Parkinson's disease, might also be stimulated to become
dopamine-producing neurons in vitro. But there are unanswered questions
about the ease of culture and long-term viability of such cells,
and the likelihood of success with cellular models of disease derived
from adult stem cells remains unknown. In the absence of a certain
and superior alternative, it would be wrong to forgo the possibly
unique benefits of cloning for disease research.
2. Cloning to Devise New Treatments for Human Diseases
The same cellular model systems used to study disease processes
are also potentially useful for assessing and developing chemical
or pharmaceutical treatments for the disease in question. To continue
with the Parkinson's disease example, neurons derived from stem
cells containing the alpha-synuclein aggregation mutations would
be very useful for testing compounds that might prevent aggregation
of this protein. Chemicals that effectively prevented aggregation
in this model system could be useful starting points for the development
of new drugs for the specific treatment of Parkinson's disease.
Here, too, neuronal cell-systems derived from adult stem cells carrying
the mutations might serve as well as those derived from cloned embryonic
stem cells. But there is no way of knowing in advance which of the
alternative routes is more promising. From a medical and scientific
point of view, research on cloned embryos may offer unique benefits.
3. Cloning to Produce Immune-Compatible Tissues for Transplantation
Some animal studies suggest that tissues derived from embryonic
stem cells can, if injected under certain conditions, populate disease-stricken
areas and differentiate so as to compensate for the loss of function
caused by the diseased tissue. For example, liver or heart muscle
cells injected into an animal with liver or heart disease could
help regenerate the diseased tissues and restore normal function.
But these cells would have a chance to do this only if they can
survive the normal immunological rejection response to foreign material.
Cloning-for-biomedical-research offers the possibility that scientists
could someday generate individualized, "rejection-proof" replacement
cells and tissues to help patients fight disease and restore health.
Stem cells and tissues derived from an embryonic clone of the patient
would have the same genes as the patient, and so, hypothetically,
would not be rejected by the patient's body as foreign.
It is true that this possibility (what is sometimes called "therapeutic
cloning") remains unproved.ii
As before, there may be alternative (nonembryonic or adult) sources
of such "rejection-proof" stem cells and tissues derived from them.
And there is ongoing research to circumvent the rejection problem
altogether, by, for example, modifying the surface of an unrelated
(embryonic) stem cell so as to enable it to escape detection as
"foreign" tissue when transferred to patients for therapy. But,
once again, it is too early to say which approach will work, and
therefore it is important, from a medical and scientific perspective,
not to close off any avenue of promise. The only way to verify this
hypothesis is to try it first in animals, then in human volunteers.
4. Cloning to Assist in Gene Therapy
Cloning techniques could also be combined with precise genetic
manipulation to devise genetic treatments for genetic diseases.
For example, a cloned embryo produced from a patient with severe
combined immunodeficiency could be genetically modified to correct
and repair the disease-causing mutation. Stem cells taken from the
genetically modified cloned embryo might then be used to develop
bone marrow stem cells to transplant back into the patient. This
combined approach to gene therapy has shown early promise in one
attempt to correct a genetic abnormality in the immune system of
mice.5
B. Possible Moral Dilemmas of Proceeding
The potentially unique medical benefits of cloning-for-biomedical-research
are, to those of us who favor it, abundantly clear. Yet the moral
meaning of proceeding, still to be considered, is the subject of
some debate among us. Most of us who favor proceeding believe that
this area of promising research is nonetheless fraught with moral
quandaries and ethical trade-offs; a minority of us do not share
these concerns. The minority view, labeled Position Number Two,
follows the principal moral case for cloning-for-biomedical-research
under strict limits, designated here as Position Number One. Each
opinion is presented in turn.
1. Position Number One
What makes this research morally controversial is that it involves
the production, use, and intentional destruction of cloned human
embryos. To determine whether or not the science should proceed
or, if it does, what limits should be placed on this research
it must be asked what, if anything, is owed this nascent form
of human life. Only then can an evaluation be made of whether the
possible benefits of this research justify its potential human cost.
Other moral hazards must be considered that are either inherent
in, or possible consequences of, this line of research. These hazards
include the following: the possibility that cloned embryos will
be developed and experimented upon beyond the blastocyst stage (the
stage from which stem cells are taken); the possible exploitation
of women who would be donors of eggs; the possibility that the production
of cloned human embryos will lead intentionally or unintentionally
to cloning-to-produce-children; and the possibility that engaging
in such research will weaken or undermine society's respect for
human life, and therefore undermine the very good (life) that it
is meant to serve. Each of these moral challenges will now be addressed.
(a) What is owed to the cloned embryo? The subject of
the moral status of developing human life is a difficult and controversial
matter, one about which American society is and appears likely to
remain deeply divided. We are well aware of the fact that we cannot
do it full justice in the present context. Yet we believe that the
moral defense of cloning-for-biomedical-research requires a consideration
of what is owed nascent human life (cloned or not). There is also
the question considered at great length in Chapter
Three of whether cloned embryos are the moral equivalent
of fertilized embryos, or whether the different nature of their
origins and the uncertainty of their capacity to become full human
beings means that our moral duties to them are somehow different.
Nevertheless, those who wish to defend cloning-for-biomedical-research-as
we do here must consider what is owed to embryos as such
as well as the significance of the fact that the embryos in question
would be cloned. That said, the relevant arguments,
especially in this subsection and the next, are in most crucial
respects the same as those regarding the treatment of embryos produced
by IVF.
Let us be clear about what we are talking about when we speak of
cloned embryos. We are talking about the very earliest
stages in development, from the single cell product of SCNT, through
the early cleavage stages, up to the blastocyst stage. This is a
structure comprising some 100 to 200 cells not yet differentiated
into specific tissues, let alone organs (though there is differentiation
into inner cell mass and trophoblast; see Chapter
Four). It is true that the embryos at the blastocyst stage,
if implanted in a woman's uterus or (hypothetically) an animal or
artificial womb, could be made to develop to later stages, and this
potentiality must be taken into account. But it is important to
keep in mind the primitive and undifferentiated condition of the
embryonic stage that is relevant for the research in question.
We begin with a series of questions: Is destroying an embryo or
cloned embryo at the blastocyst stage morally the same as killing
a child? Is it the same as clipping a fingernail? Is it more like
one of these acts than the other? Is it like neither? Does the moral
status of an embryo depend on whether it is implanted in a woman's
uterus or remains in a laboratory? Does the moral status of an embryo
depend on its origins, or how it was produced? Does it depend on
the motives of those who create it?
In our view, embryos have a developing and intermediate moral worth,
such that the early human embryo has a moral status somewhere between
that of ordinary human cells and that of a full human person. We
acknowledge the difficulty of setting perfectly clear lines marking
when an embryo's moral status goes from "less than a human person"
to "like a human person" to "fully a human person." But we believe
there are sound moral reasons for not regarding the embryo in its
earliest stages (certainly in the first fourteen days) as the moral
equivalent of a human person, though it does command significantly
more respect than other human cells. We also hold that the embryo
can be used for life-saving or potentially life-saving research
while still being accorded the "special respect" it deserves, and
while still preventing abuses such as research on later-stage embryos
or fetuses or the production of cloned children. We will develop
this view by taking up the significance of (i) twinning, (ii) implantation,
(iii) the human form, and (iv) the notion of "special respect."
- (i) The possibility of twinning. First, it is still
unclear in the initial fourteen-day period whether an embryo will
develop into one or more human beings. The possibility for "twinning"
is still present, suggesting that the earliest-stage embryo is
either not yet an individual or is a being that is not
confined to becoming only one individual. There are continuing
philosophical debates about how to understand what happens in
twinning: for example, whether one individual embryo "clones"
itself to produce a second, or whether an organism that resembles
(but is not yet) an individual embryo divides into two
truly individual beings.3
Nevertheless, the biological and we believe moral
significance of the possibility for twinning is clear: after fourteen
days (or after the primitive streak is formed), the being in question
can no longer be anything but a single being that
is to say, no embryo after this stage, and thus no fetus or live-born
baby, can replicate or divide to form another identical being.
Before fourteen days, this possibility remains.
- (ii) The moral significance of pregnancy and implantation.
Both IVF embryos and cloned embryos in vitro differ from comparable
embryos conceived through sexual intercourse, for two reasons.
First, the possibility for pregnancy with IVF or cloned embryos
requires human assistance that is, it requires the medical
procedure of transferring an embryo into the woman's uterus. There
is thus no possibility of the IVF or cloned embryo becoming a
human child in its original in vitro environment. Second, embryos
that are conceived through sexual intercourse have a direct physical
connection with the individual women who carry them, whereas an
in vitro embryo (cloned or not) has no such connection unless
it is transferred into a woman's uterus. Thus, transfer of cloned
or IVF embryos into a woman's uterus is a significant moral step,
insofar as such embryos cannot be removed they can never
again be held in human hands without a direct physical intrusion
or violation of the pregnant woman. Of course, it might become
technologically possible in the future for in vitro embryos to
develop beyond the blastocyst stage and perhaps even to
birth without implantation into a woman's uterus (that is,
in an artificial womb). Moreover, just because those embryos (cloned
or not) that exist in vitro cannot continue to develop in a self-directed
way beyond the blastocyst stage that is, they require human
artifice of some kind to develop further does not mean that
the preimplantation embryo is morally insignificant. But implantation
does mark a significant point in these two respects: after implantation,
self-direction toward birth (without external human artifice)
becomes possible and external human control of embryos
becomes impossible without intruding upon or violating
the pregnant woman.
- (iii) The significance of the developed human form.
Generally speaking, our moral sentiments respond very differently
to the prospect or the sight of the destruction of
an embryo and the murder of a child. In other words, there is
a difference between what we respect and what we consider
inviolable. The destruction of embryos might inspire concern
or solemnity. In contrast, our reaction to the murder of a child
would be one of horror, outrage, grief, and violation. James Q.
Wilson has discussed how these two fundamentally different moral
reactions change as the embryo develops into a fetus and then
into a child and correspondingly, how our concern and solemnity
transform into horror and outrage.6
Specifically, human beings exhibit a distinctly different moral
sympathy for, and therefore greater willingness to protect, those
organisms that have begun to resemble human beings in their developed
form. The practice of sacrificing the life of the unborn in order
to save the life of the pregnant woman while not a moral
parallel to the case of using cloned embryos for biomedical research
shows that there is some moral precedent for subordinating
nascent human life to more developed human life. Of course, taken
to an extreme, such a principle would justify the most grotesque
uses of developing human fetuses for scientific experiments. Moreover,
the case is not strictly analogous, for in the case of the pregnant
woman, two lives are in conflict, a confrontation absent with
free-standing embryos. We do not take the life of woman A's unborn
fetus to save the life of woman B, not even with consent. But
these difficulties notwithstanding, there is (again) a moral insight
in this example. It demonstrates the important moral obligation
of caring for those who already dwell among us, and the inevitable
moral complexity of weighing different forms of human life, especially
nascent and developed human life, against one another. It also
suggests ways in which the claim on our protection may increase
with the emergence of powers of awareness and suffering. Of course,
such examples and our moral sentiments in general
are not by themselves decisive. They are the beginning, not the
end, of reasoning about our moral responsibilities. But they should
also not be ignored for what they reveal about the nature of particular
beings and particular acts and in this case, for what they
suggest about both the developing and intermediate
status of the early human embryo.
- (iv) The meaning of "special respect." Finally, there
is the question of whether it is possible to accord early-stage
embryos "special respect" while still using them for biomedical
research. We might reason here by an admittedly imperfect analogy.
Various religions have rules governing the killing of animals
for food. These exist in part to restrain cruelty. But they also
serve to demonstrate respect for beings that command our affections
and our wonder, because they are (like us) part of the mystery
of existence. In a similar way, many hunters have a deep-rooted
respect and even affection for the animals they kill. This is
not to say that human embryos are the same as animals, because,
in our opinion, they are indeed human organisms, if not fully
developed human beings. But it is to show that there might be
ways both to respect beings and to use them for serious,
not frivolous, reasons, and as part of our place in the order
of being, not simply as an extension of our subjective will.
For the above-stated reasons, we would assign an intermediate and
developing status to the human embryo. Those who treat the developing
early embryo as nothing more than "mere cells" (see Position Number
Two below) are in danger of ignoring its direct and inherent connection
to the profound mystery of the origins of human life and seem willing
to ignore the fact that an embryo will (and a cloned embryo might)
eventually become one (or more) human being(s). This view greatly
underestimates the moral seriousness of the question of whether
to proceed with research on nascent human life. And it gravely mischaracterizes
the meaning of potentiality specifically, the difference between
having the capacity to become anything at all (a pile of building
materials, for example) and the capacity to become something in
particular (an individuated human person or persons).
At the same time, those who believe that early-stage embryos are
the moral equivalent of a human person (see Part IV below) are also,
we believe, misguided. Just as we must listen to and then
articulate the moral meaning of our disquiet at the idea of
cloning-to-produce-children, we must listen to and articulate our
fundamentally different moral responses to the destruction of an
embryo on the one hand and the murder of a child on the other. While
no single criterion like "appearance," "self-consciousness," "the
capacity to express needs and desires," or "the capacity to feel
pain" can by itself be decisive in conferring human dignity, the
absence of all such criteria in the early-stage embryo or cloned
embryo suggests that it is not a truly human being, but something
different, commanding our respect because of what it is and may
become, but yet not fully one of us.
In sum, what is owed the embryo is not the same protections, attachments,
and rights as a human person; nor is it no respect at all. In making
the decision to proceed with research on embryos or cloned embryos,
we must do so only for the most compelling reasons namely,
the reasonable expectation that such research will save human lives
and only with eyes open to the moral burden of doing what
we believe to be morally best. Even as we establish the biological
and moral grounds for using human embryos in certain forms of research,
we must face and accept the solemnity of what we propose. Finally,
we must proceed with the paradox that accompanies all human suffering
and human imperfection in full view: that sometimes we seem morally
obligated to do morally troubling things, and that sometimes doing
what is good means living with a heavy heart in doing it.
(b) The problem of deliberate creation for use in research.
We next address whether the creation of embryos explicitly for the
purposes of biomedical research presents additional ethical problems,
beyond those just examined. In the case of research on cloned embryos,
this form of deliberate production and destruction rather
than the use of leftover embryos initially created for reproductive
purposes is the only means of proceeding, if, at the same
time, society prohibits cloning-to-produce-children. It is one thing
to overcome the respect owed to an already existing embryo that
would die even if not used for research. It is, some argue, quite
another thing to bring the embryo into being solely for use and
exploitation in research. Willing to accept the first, they reject
the second.iv
In this connection, three issues seem worth considering.
First, the fundamental moral judgment about whether to proceed
with cloning-for-biomedical-research must be grounded in our judgment
about the moral status of the embryos themselves, not the purpose
of their creation. If an embryo or a cloned embryo had no moral
standing, then creation for research and eventual destruction would
present no moral problem. If the embryo or cloned embryo were morally
the equivalent of a child, then regardless of how or why it was
produced, experiments upon it would be morally abhorrent. But if,
as we have just argued, an embryo or a cloned embryo has a developing
and intermediate moral status, certain worthy uses of them may be
justified regardless of how and why they were produced. Because
the use of stem cells from cloned embryos may in the future provide
treatment for serious human diseases, the creation of cloned embryos
and their subsequent disaggregation to isolate stem cells can be
justified.
Second, the moral responsibilities for producing new embryos solely
for research and for producing extra IVF embryos later used
in research are not really so different. In the case of IVF and
leftover embryos, the individuals who create them for reproductive
purposes typically and deliberately create more embryos than they
are likely to use, and therefore know in advance that some will
probably be destroyed. It is true that they are produced with the
intent of initiating a pregnancy and that the embryo wastage is
not all that different from what obtains in efforts to conceive
in vivo. But the moral responsibility for production, use, and destruction
of leftover embryos are finally no less than for deliberate production
for use (and subsequent destruction in research). (We acknowledge
that some who accept this logic come to the opposite conclusion
namely, not that cloning-for-biomedical-research is morally
permissible but that IVF should be morally restricted to creating
one embryo at a time, if permitted at all.)
Third, in both cases creating embryos to aid fertility or
creating embryos for biomedical research the ultimate goal
is something humanly good: a child for an infertile couple or research
that holds promise for curing debilitating diseases and easing suffering.
Thus, in the case of cloning-for-biomedical-research, it is wrong
to argue, as some do, that embryos are being "created for destruction."
Certainly, their destruction is a known and unavoidable effect,
but the embryos are ultimately created for research in the service
of life and medicine.
In the end, while we acknowledge the risk of turning nascent human
life into a "resource" fully separate from its intrinsic connection
to human procreation we hold that the concern over deliberate
creation and destruction is misplaced. What matters instead is whether
a proper regard is shown for the created embryos, and therefore
whether a proper moral and legal framework can be established that
limits and governs their use in accordance with the respect they
are owed as human cloned embryos.
(c) Development and use of cloned embryos beyond the earliest
stages. A perceived danger of allowing cloning-for-biomedical-research
is that some researchers will develop cloned embryos beyond the
blastocyst stage for research purposes. There are good scientific
reasons and even moral arguments for doing so: one could learn much
more about development, normal and abnormal, by going to later stages;
and differentiated tissues taken from cloned fetuses would likely
be more useful in regenerative medicine than stem cells. There is
already at least one animal study showing the potential of this
approach.7
Transplantable functioning kidney tissue has been attained from
six-week-old cloned cow fetuses, developed from cloned cow embryos
transferred into a cow's uterus for partial gestation. Cloned human
embryos might be developed past the blastocyst stage by implantation
into an animal or human uterus, by the development of artificial
wombs, or by advances in sustaining nascent human life in vitro.
This is a serious concern for those of us who believe that the
cloned embryo has only an intermediate moral status and who also
recognize the difficulty of drawing bright lines for when developing
human life changes from "less than a human person" to "like a human
person" to a "fully developed person." Clearly, the longer cloned
embryos are allowed to develop, the more severe the moral burden
in using them. And at some point, the moral burden of proceeding
becomes a moral obligation not to proceed even if significant
medical benefits might be gained from doing so. In such circumstances,
the medical principle of "do no harm" must override the researcher's
desire to do good, lest we undermine the humanistic principles and
spirit of the entire medical enterprise.
The moral tradition of "erecting a fence around the law"v
may provide a useful guide in this case. We recommend that research
on cloned embryos be strictly limited to the first fourteen days
of development a point just about when the primitive streak
is formed and before organ differentiation occurs. We acknowledge
that by erecting the fence more widely, we might be more certain
to prevent this particular abuse (developing cloned embryos beyond
the blastocyst stage). We also acknowledge that relaxing this limit
to permit research beyond fourteen days might yield additional medical
benefits. There is a moral burden in both directions. But we hold
that there is a point of development beyond which research on nascent
human life is morally intolerable no matter what the potential medical
benefits. By raising a permanent fence at fourteen days, the dignity
of human life will be sufficiently protected.
(d) Exploitation of women who are egg donors. Additional
concerns in proceeding with cloning-for-biomedical-research are the
possible dangers to, and exploitation of, women who are egg donors.
The removal of eggs remains an unpleasant and (owing to the hormone
treatments needed to hyperstimulate the ovaries) a risky medical procedure
for women. It is therefore restricted mostly to circumstances where
such a procedure is necessary to treat infertility that is,
where the women themselves are the beneficiaries of the procedure.
Moreover, one possible avenue of cloning-for-biomedical-research-namely,
the creation and future use of individualized stem cells would
potentially require, if it became feasible, a very large and indefinite
number of eggs.
These are genuine concerns. But they can be addressed by strictly
adhering to the established body of ethics for research on human
subjects. These ethical codes suggest the following requirements:
regulation to prevent the creation of improper financial incentives
for participating in such research; full disclosure by the users
of human eggs of their practices; a commitment to consider using
nonhuman eggs, so as to decrease the need for human egg donorsvi
; and strict limits on the uses of cloned embryos for only those
investigations that uniquely require them.
(e) The connection to cloning-to-produce-children. The
final moral concern is that cloning-for-biomedical-research will
lead intentionally or not to cloning-to-produce-children.
For the reasons described in Chapter
Five, we believe that the creation of cloned human children
would be unethical and that society has a moral responsibility to
ensure that this does not happen. Thus we are obliged to consider
whether the pursuit of cloning-for-biomedical-research is consistent
with a serious commitment to stopping cloning-to-produce-children.
A number of points must be considered.
First, the production of cloned embryos, even for research purposes,
crosses a new line by bringing into existence for the first time
forms of nascent human life that are asexually produced. Second,
experience with producing cloned embryos for biomedical research
might well improve the technique of cloning itself, and therefore
result in the greater perfection of the first step toward cloning-to-produce-children.
Third, cloning-for-biomedical-research means that cloned embryos
would exist in laboratories where they could be available for efforts
to initiate a pregnancy. Finally, a society that allows cloning-for-biomedical-research,
while setting strict legal limits on cloning-to-produce-children,
will likely require the mandatory destruction of nascent human life.
The first concern is intrinsic to cloning-for-biomedical-research
in itself. Are we a different society because we have brought asexually
produced human embryos into existence? In some ways, perhaps we
are. We are confronted by the scope of our powers to change human
life, to alter human procreation, and to modify the nature of human
origins and the genetic makeup of new life. But we are also reminded
of what should be the animating purpose of that power: to cure disease
and relieve suffering. We are reminded of both new and unique possibilities
for human harm (from the production of human clones) and new and
unique possibilities for human benefit (from research on cloned
embryos). This is, we suggest, the meaning of crossing this line.
The second and third concerns are connected to where this research
might lead: namely, to a perfected cloning technique and to the
intentional production of cloned children. This is indeed a genuine
concern. It is perhaps the case that the best way to prevent the
production of cloned children is to prohibit the creation of cloned
embryos. But in the end, we are not convinced that cloning-for-biomedical-research
will inevitably lead to cloning-to-produce-children; rather, we
believe that the best approach is a system of regulation that prevents
such an abuse. Such a system would include: a legal ban on the implantation
of cloned embryos in any uterus (human, animal, or artificial);
a prohibition on developing cloned embryos beyond fourteen days;
a requirement that any individual or group engaging in cloning-for-biomedical-research
register with proper regulatory authorities; prior scientific review
of all proposed uses of cloned embryos to judge their medical and
scientific benefits; and strict accounting of all cloned embryos
that are produced to prevent their removal from the lab of origin
or their use in attempts at cloning-to-produce-children.
Of course, no system of regulation is perfect. There is always
the possibility of malfeasance or error. The prudential question
in this case is whether the likelihood of cloning-to-produce-children
is increased at all, slightly, or significantly by allowing
the production and use of cloned embryos for biomedical research.
But there is also the question of whether some additional risk of
cloning-to-produce-children is justified or tolerable given the
human goods that might be achieved through cloning-for-biomedical-research.
In our view, it is.
The final concern is that to pursue research on cloned embryos
while preventing cloning-to-produce-children would require laws
that mandated the destruction of nascent human life. In assessing
the moral significance of this fact, we return to our judgment about
the moral status of cloned embryos, what is owed to them, and whether
the human goods that can be achieved by cloning-for-biomedical-research
justify the real and potential human costs. In our view, the possible
existence of a law requiring the destruction of cloned embryos at
or before fourteen days of development would force moral clarity
about what we are doing and the burdens of doing it. Such
a law might remind society of the ambiguity and limits of the efforts
to "heal the world," and therefore the dangers of trying to do so
by any means possible. The need for such a law requiring the destruction
of nascent human life would also remind us that there is a burden
in acting just as there is a burden in not acting.
(f) Conclusion. The case for cloning-for-biomedical-research
as with all research that involves the use of nascent human
life should not consist simply of guessing how many people
might be saved and how many embryos might be lost. The moral concerns
cannot so simply be taken up, addressed, and retired. They are permanent
concerns and permanent burdens.
We believe, in this particular case, that the promise of cloning-for-biomedical-research
justifies proceeding, but that the genuine possibility of moral
harm requires strict regulations of how we proceed. We have tried
to articulate what such a system of regulation might include: (1)
a legal requirement not to develop cloned embryos beyond fourteen
days of development and not to implant cloned embryos in any uterus,
human, animal, or artificial; (2) the creation of a governmental
oversight body to regulate individuals and groups who engage in
this research, and to account for all cloned embryos that are produced
so as to prevent their removal from the lab of origin or their use
in cloning-to-produce-children; (3) a ban on commerce in living
cloned human embryos; (4) adherence to the highest standards of
the ethics of research on human subjects, especially when it comes
to procuring eggs; (5) a prior scientific review of the proposed
uses of cloned embryos to judge their unique medical and scientific
benefits; and (6) continued research into possible non-embryonic
sources of stem cells and tissues for developmental studies, and
ways other than cloning to solve the immune rejection problem. Such
regulations amount to much more than mere bureaucratic red tape.
They embody a profound ethical insight namely, that the means
of serving human beings must never corrupt our responsibilities
to human beings.
2. Position Number Two
A few of us who favor proceeding with cloning-for-biomedical-research
have few of the ethical qualms expressed by our colleagues in Position
Number One. It is our view that this research, at least in the forms
and for the purposes presently contemplated, presents no special
moral problems, and therefore should be endorsed with enthusiasm
as a potential new means of gaining knowledge to serve humankind.
Because we accord no special moral status to the early-stage cloned
embryo, we believe that the moral issues involved in this research
are no different from those that accompany many existing forms of
biomedical research, requiring mainly the usual commitment to high
standards for the quality of research, scientific integrity, and
the need to obtain informed consent from, and to protect the health
of, donors of the eggs and somatic cells used in nuclear transfer.
It is also our view that there are no sound reasons for treating
the early-stage human embryo or cloned human embryo as anything
special, or as having moral status greater than human somatic cells
in tissue culture. A blastocyst (cloned or not), because it lacks
any trace of a nervous system, has no capacity for suffering or
conscious experience in any form the special properties that,
in our view, spell the difference between biological tissue and
a human life worthy of respect and rights. Additional biological
facts suggest that a blastocyst should not be identified with a
unique individual person, even if the argument that it lacks sentience
is set aside. A single blastocyst may, until the primitive streak
is formed at around fourteen days, split into twins; conversely,
two blastocysts may fuse to form a single (chimeric) organism. Moreover,
most early-stage embryos that are produced naturally (that is, through
the union of egg and sperm resulting from sexual intercourse) fail
to implant and are therefore wasted or destroyed.
There is a moral precedent for using materials from early human
embryos in the widely accepted practice of using organs from brain-dead
human beings. Upon determination of death, and with permission from
the next of kin, surgeons routinely harvest organs to save the lives
of sick or dying patients. In a similar way, donors of somatic cells
and human oocytes could justifiably grant a biomedical scientist
permission to use cells derived from the resulting cloned five-to-six-day-old
blastocyst, which also completely lacks a brain and a capacity for
consciousness.
Some argue that the transplantation analogy is misleading, because
a blastocyst has the potential to become a fetus and ultimately
a child, whereas the brain-dead individual does not. But the potential
to become something (or someone) is hardly the same as being
something (or someone), any more than a pile of building materials
is the same as a house. A cloned embryo's potential to become a
human person can be realized, if at all, only by the further human
act of implanting the cloned blastocyst into the uterus of a woman.
Such implantation is not a part of cloning-for-biomedical-research,
whose aims and actual practice do not require it.
Moreover, thanks to the results of nuclear transplantation research,
there is reason to believe that every human cell has the genetic
potential to develop into a complete human being, if used in cloning
efforts to produce a child. If mere potentiality to develop into
a human being is enough to make something morally human, then every
human cell has a special or inviolable moral status, a view that
is patently absurd.
"Slippery slope" warnings that the use of early-stage cloned embryos
for research would lead necessarily either to the production of
cloned children or to research on later-stage cloned fetuses should
be treated with skepticism. Appropriate regulations can easily be
established and enforced to prevent any such abuses. Although the
continuity of biological development means that there is no naturally
given moment after which an embryo or fetus becomes a person, defensible
boundaries can be set. It is perfectly possible to treat a blastocyst
as a clump of cells usable for lifesaving research, while prohibiting
any such use of a later-stage embryo or fetus.
Where to set the boundary is a matter for prudent judgment. For
the foreseeable future, the moral line might be safely drawn at
fourteen days of development, when no nervous system has developed
and when a distinct identity as a single individual has not yet
been preordained. Also, derivation of the valuable stem cells can
be accomplished well before fourteen days. Whether society will
be faced, in the future, with reason to reconsider such a line is
for now a matter of speculation. If such an occasion ever arose,
it would require an evaluation of the proposed scientific use and
its likely medical benefits and a moral consideration of whether
the research in question justified using embryos beyond the fourteen-day
point.
* * *
IV. The Moral Case against Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research
Our colleagues who joined in Part III in making the case for cloning-for-biomedical-research
began their analysis by describing the medical promise of such research.
Those of us who maintain for both principled and prudential
reasons that cloning-for-biomedical-research should not
be pursued similarly begin by acknowledging that substantial human
goods might be gained from this research. Although it would be wrong
to speak in ways that encourage false hope in those who are ill,
as if a cure were likely in the near future, we who oppose such
research take seriously its potential for one day yielding substantial
(and perhaps unique) medical benefits. Even apart from more distant
possibilities for advances in regenerative medicine, there are more
immediate possibilities for progress in basic research and for developing
models to study different diseases. All of us whose lives benefit
enormously from medical advances that began with basic research
know how great is our collective stake in continued scientific investigations.
Only for very serious reasons to avoid moral wrongdoing, to
avoid harm to society, and to avoid foolish or unnecessary risks
should progress toward increased knowledge and advances that
might relieve suffering or cure disease be slowed.
We also observe, however, that the realization of these medical
benefits like all speculative research and all wagers about
the future remains uncertain. There are grounds for questioning
whether the proposed benefits of cloning-for-biomedical-research
will be realized. And there may be other morally unproblematic ways
to achieve similar scientific results and medical benefits. For
example, promising results in research with non-embryonic and adult
stem cells suggest that scientists may be able to make progress
in regenerative medicine without engaging in cloning-for-biomedical-research.
We can move forward with other, more developed forms of human stem
cell research and with animal cloning. We can explore other routes
for solving the immune rejection problem or to finding valuable
cellular models of human disease.vii
Where such morally innocent alternatives exist, one could argue
that the burden of persuasion lies on proponents to show not only
that cloned embryo research is promising or desirable but that it
is necessary to gain the sought-for medical benefits. Indeed, the
Nuremberg Code of research ethics enunciates precisely this principle
that experimentation should be "such as to yield fruitful
results for the good of society, unprocurable by other methods or
means of study." Because of all the scientific uncertainties
and the many possible avenues of research that burden cannot
at present be met.
But, we readily concede, these same uncertainties mean that no
one not the scientists, not the moralists, and not the patients
whose suffering we all hope to ameliorate can know for certain
which avenues of research will prove most successful. Research using
cloned embryos may in fact, as we said above, yield knowledge and
benefits unobtainable by any other means.
With such possible benefits in view, what reasons could we have
for saying "no" to cloning-for-biomedical-research? Why not leave
this possible avenue of medical progress open? Why not put the cup
to our lips? In The Winter's Tale, Shakespeare has Leontes, King
of Silicia, explain why one might not.8
There may be in the cup
A spider steep'd, and one may drink, depart,
And yet partake no venom, for his knowledge
Is not infected; but if one present
The abhorr'd ingredient to his eye, make known
How he hath drunk, he cracks his gorge, his sides
With violent hefts. I have drunk, and seen the spider.
To discern the spider in the cup is to see the moral reality of
cloning-for-biomedical-research differently. It is to move beyond
questions of immediately evident benefits or harms alone toward
deeper questions about what an ongoing program of cloning-for-biomedical-research
would mean. In part, this approach compels us to think about embryo
research generally, but cloning (even for research purposes alone)
raises its own special concerns, since only cloned embryos could
one day become cloned children. We need to consider and articulate
the reasons why, despite the possibility of great benefits, society
should nevertheless turn away and not drink from this cup, and why
the reasons for "drinking with limits" (offered by our colleagues
in Position Number One above) are finally not persuasive.
Our analysis proceeds along three pathways: what we owe to the
embryo; what we owe to society; and what we owe to the suffering.
We differ, among ourselves, on the relative importance of the various
arguments presented below. But we all agree that moral objections
to the research itself and prudential considerations about where
it is likely to lead suggest that we should oppose cloning-for-biomedical-research,
albeit with regret.
A. What We Owe to the Embryo
The embryo is, and perhaps will always be, something of a puzzle
to us. In its rudimentary beginnings, it is so unlike the human
beings we know and live with that it hardly seems to be one of us;
yet, the fact of our own embryonic origin evokes in us respect for
the wonder of emerging new human life. Even in the midst of much
that is puzzling and uncertain, we would not want to lose that respect
or ignore what we owe to the embryo.
The cell synthesized by somatic cell nuclear transfer, no less
than the fertilized egg, is a human organism in its germinal stage.viii
It is not just a "clump of cells" but an integrated, self-developing
whole, capable (if all goes well) of the continued organic development
characteristic of human beings. To be sure, the embryo does not
yet have, except in potential, the full range of characteristics
that distinguish the human species from others, but one need not
have those characteristics in evidence in order to belong to the
species. And of course human beings at some other stages of development
early in life, late in life, at any stage of life if severely
disabled do not forfeit their humanity simply for want of
these distinguishing characteristics. We may observe different points
in the life story of any human being a beginning filled mostly
with potential, a zenith at which the organism is in full flower,
a decline in which only a residue remains of what is most distinctively
human. But none of these points is itself the human being. That
being is, rather, an organism with a continuous history. From zygote
to irreversible coma, each human life is a single personal history.
But this fact still leaves unanswered the question of whether all
stages of a human being's life have equal moral standing. Might
there be sound biological or moral reasons for according the early-stage
embryo only partial human worth or even none at all? If
so, should such embryos be made available or even explicitly created
for research that necessarily requires their destruction especially
if very real human good might come from it? Some of us who oppose
cloning-for-biomedical-research hold that efforts to assign to the
embryo a merely intermediate and developing moral status that
is, more humanly significant than other human cells, but less deserving
of respect and protection than a human fetus or infant are
both biologically and morally unsustainable, and that the embryo
is in fact fully "one of us": a human life in process, an equal
member of the species Homo sapiens in the embryonic stage
of his or her natural development. All of us who oppose going forward
with cloning-for-biomedical-research believe that it is incoherent
and self-contradictory for our colleagues (in Position Number One)
to claim that human embryos deserve "special respect" and to endorse
nonetheless research that requires the creation, use, and destruction
of these organisms, especially when done routinely and on a
large scale.
The case for treating the early-stage embryo as simply the moral
equivalent of all other human cells (Position Number Two, above)
is entirely unconvincing: it denies the continuous history of human
individuals from zygote to fetus to infant to child; it misunderstands
the meaning of potentiality and, specifically, the difference
between a "being-on-the-way" (such as a developing human embryo)
and a "pile of raw materials," which has no definite potential and
which might become anything at all; and it ignores the hazardous
moral precedent that the routinized creation, use, and destruction
of nascent human life would establish for other areas of scientific
research and social life.
The more serious questions are raised about individuality,
potentiality, and "special respect" by those who assign an
intermediate and developing moral status to the human embryo, and
who believe that cloned embryos can be used (and destroyed) for
biomedical research while still according them special human worth
(Position Number One, above). But the arguments for this position
both biological and moral are not convincing. For attempts
to ground the special respect owed to a maturing embryo in certain
of its developmental features do not succeed. And the invoking of
a "special respect" owed to nascent human life seems to have little
or no operative meaning once one sees what those who take this position
are willing to countenance.
We are not persuaded by the argument that fourteen days marks a
significant difference in moral status. Because the embryo's human
and individual genetic identity is present from the start, nothing
that happens later during the continuous development that follows
at fourteen days or any other time is responsible for
suddenly conferring a novel human individuality or identity. The
scientific evidence suggests that the fourteen day marker
does not represent a biological event of moral significance; rather,
changes that occur at fourteen days are merely the visibly evident
culmination of more subtle changes that have taken place earlier
and that are driving the organism toward maturity. Indeed, many
advocates of cloning-for-biomedical-research implicitly recognize
the arbitrariness of the fourteen-day line. The medical benefits
to be gained by conducting research beyond the fourteen-day line
are widely appreciated, and some people have already hinted that
this supposed moral and biological boundary can be moved should
the medical benefits warrant doing so (see Position Number Two,
above).
There are also problems with the claim that its capacity for "twinning"
proves that the early embryo is not yet an individual or that the
embryo's moral status is more significant after the capacity for
twinning is gone. There is the obvious rejoinder that if one locus
of moral status can become two, its moral standing does not thereby
diminish but rather increases. More specifically, the possibility
of twinning does not rebut the individuality of the early embryo
from its beginning. The fact that where "John" alone once was there
are now both "John" and "Jim" does not call into question the presence
of "John" at the outset. Hence, we need not doubt that even the
earliest cloned embryo is an individual human organism in its germinal
stage. Its capacity for twinning may simply be one of the characteristic
capacities of an individual human organism at that particular stage
of development, just as the capacity for crawling, walking, and
running, or cooing, babbling, and speaking are capacities that are
also unique to particular stages of human development. Alternatively,
from a developmental science perspective, twinning may not turn
out to be an intrinsic process within embryogenesis. Rather, it
may be a response to a disruption of normal development from which
the embryo recovers and then forms two. Twinning would thus be a
testament to the resilience of self-regulation and compensatory
repair within early life, not the lack of individuation in the early
embryo. From this perspective, twinning is further testimony to
the potency of the individual (in this case two) to fullness of
form.
We are also not persuaded by the claim that in vitro embryos (whether
created through IVF or cloning) have a lesser moral status than
embryos that have been implanted into a woman's uterus, because
they cannot develop without further human assistance. The suggestion
that extra-corporeal embryos are not yet individual human organisms-on-the-way,
but rather special human cells that acquire only through implantation
the potential to become individual human organisms-on-the-way, rests
on a misunderstanding of the meaning and significance of potentiality.
An embryo is, by definition and by its nature, potentially a fully
developed human person; its potential for maturation is a characteristic
it actually has, and from the start. The fact that embryos
have been created outside their natural environment which
is to say, outside the woman's body and are therefore limited
in their ability to realize their natural capacities, does not affect
either the potential or the moral status of the beings themselves.
A bird forced to live in a cage its entire life may never learn
to fly. But this does not mean it is less of a bird, or that it
lacks the immanent potentiality to fly on feathered wings. It means
only that a caged bird-like an in vitro human embryo has been
deprived of its proper environment. There may, of course, be good
human reasons to create embryos outside their natural environments
most obviously, to aid infertile couples. But doing so does
not obliterate the moral status of the embryos themselves.
As we have noted, many proponents of cloning-for-biomedical-research
(and for embryo research more generally) do not deny that we owe
the human embryo special moral respect. Indeed, they have wanted
positively to affirm it.ix
But we do not understand what it means to claim that one is treating
cloned embryos with special respect when one decides to create them
intentionally for research that necessarily leads to their destruction.
This respect is allegedly demonstrated by limiting such research
and therefore limiting the numbers of embryos that may be
created, used, and destroyed to only the most serious purposes:
namely, scientific investigations that hold out the potential for
curing diseases or relieving suffering. But this self-limitation
shows only that our purposes are steadfastly high-minded; it does
not show that the means of pursuing these purposes are
respectful of the cloned embryos that are necessarily violated,
exploited, and destroyed in the process. To the contrary, a true
respect for a being would nurture and encourage it toward its own
flourishing.
It is, of course, possible to have reverence for a life that one
kills. This is memorably displayed, for example, by the fisherman
Santiago in Ernest Hemingway's The Old Man and the Sea,
who wonders whether it is a sin to kill fish even if doing so would
feed hungry people. But it seems difficult to claim even in
theory but especially in practice the presence of reverence
once we run a stockyard or raise calves for veal that is,
once we treat the animals we kill (as we often do) simply as resources
or commodities. In a similar way, we find it difficult to imagine
that biotechnology companies or scientists who routinely engaged
in cloning-for-biomedical-research would evince solemn respect for
human life each time a cloned embryo was used and destroyed. Things
we exploit even occasionally tend to lose their special value. It
seems scarcely possible to preserve a spirit of humility and solemnity
while engaging in routinized (and in many cases corporately competitive)
research that creates, uses, and destroys them.
The mystery that surrounds the human embryo is undeniable. But
so is the fact that each human person began as an embryo, and that
this embryo, once formed, had the unique potential to become a unique
human person. This is the meaning of our embodied condition and
the biology that describes it. If we add to this description a commitment
to equal treatment the moral principle that every human life
deserves our equal respect we begin to see how difficult it
must be to suggest that a human embryo, even in its most undeveloped
and germinal stage, could simply be used for the good of others
and then destroyed. Justifying our intention of using (and destroying)
human embryos for the purpose of biomedical research would force
us either to ignore the truth of our own continuing personal histories
from their beginning in embryonic life or to weaken the commitment
to human equality that has been so slowly and laboriously developed
in our cultural history.
Equal treatment of human beings does not, of course, mean identical
treatment, as all parents know who have more than one child. And
from one perspective, the fact that the embryo seems to amount to
so little seems to be little more than a clump of cells
invites us to suppose that its claims upon us can also not amount
to much. We are, many have noted, likely to grieve the death of
an embryo less than the death of a newborn child. But, then, we
are also likely to grieve the death of an eighty-five-year-old father
less than the death of a forty-five-year-old father. Perhaps, even,
we may grieve the death of a newborn child less than the death of
a twelve-year-old. We might grieve differently at the death of a
healthy eighty-year-old than at the death of a severely demented
eighty-year-old. Put differently, we might note how even the researcher
in the laboratory may react with excitement and anticipation as
cell division begins. Thus, reproductive physiologist Robert Edwards,
who, together with Dr. Patrick Steptoe, helped produce Louise Brown,
the first "test-tube baby," said of her: "The last time I saw her,
she was just eight cells in a test-tube. She was beautiful then,
and she's still beautiful now."9
The embryo seems to amount to little; yet it has the capacity to
become what to all of us seems very much indeed. There is a trajectory
to the life story of human beings, and it is inevitable and
appropriate that our emotional responses should be different
at different points in that trajectory. Nevertheless, these emotions,
quite naturally and appropriately different, would be misused if
we calibrated the degree of respect we owe each other on the basis
of such responses. In fact, we are obligated to try to shape and
form our emotional responses and our moral sentiments
so that they are more in accord with the moral respect we owe to
those whose capacities are least developed (or those whom society
may have wrongly defined as "non-persons" or "nonentities").
In short, how we respond to the weakest among us, to those who
are nowhere near the zenith of human flourishing, says much about
our willingness to envision the boundaries of humanity expansively
and inclusively. It challenges in the face of what we can
know and what we cannot know about the human embryo the depth
of our commitment to equality. If from one perspective the fact
that the embryo seems to amount to little may invite a weakening
of our respect, from another perspective its seeming insignificance
should awaken in us a sense of shared humanity. This was once our
own condition. From origins that seem so little came our kin, our
friends, our fellow citizens, and all human beings, whether known
to us or not. In fact, precisely because the embryo seems to amount
to so little, our responsibility to respect and protect its life
correspondingly increases. As Hans Jonas once remarked, a true humanism
would recognize "the inflexible principle that utter helplessness
demands utter protection."10
B. What We Owe to Society
Having acknowledged all that, we would miss something if we stopped
with what is owed to the embryo with the language of respect,
claims, or rights. An embryo may seem to amount to little or nothing,
but that very insignificance tests not the embryo's humanity but our
own. Even those who are uncertain about the precise moral status of
the human embryo indeed, even those who believe that it has
only intermediate and developing status have sound ethical
prudential reasons to refrain from using embryos for utilitarian purposes.
Moreover, when the embryos to be used have been produced by cloning,
there are additional moral dilemmas that go beyond the ethics of embryo
research alone. There are principled reasons why people who accept
research on leftover IVF embryos created initially for reproductive
purposes should oppose the creation and use of cloned embryos
explicitly for research. And there are powerful reasons to worry about
where this research will lead us. All these objections have their
ground not only in the embryo's character but also in our own, and
in concern not only for the fate of nascent human life but for the
moral well-being of society as a whole. One need not believe the
embryo is fully human to object vigorously to cloning-for-biomedical-research.
We are concerned especially about three ways in which giving our
moral approval to such research would harm the character of our
common life and the way of life we want to transmit to future generations:
(i) by crossing the boundary from sexual to asexual reproduction,
in the process approving, whether recognized or not, genetic manipulation
and control of nascent human life; (ii) by allowing and endorsing
the complete instrumentalization of human embryos; and (iii) by
opening the door to other for some of us, far greater
moral hazards, such as cloning-to-produce-children or research on
later-stage human embryos and fetuses.
1. Asexual Reproduction and the Genetic Manipulation of Embryos
It is worth noting that human cloning-including cloning-for-biomedical-research
itself and not simply cloning-to-produce-children-would cross a
natural boundary between sexual and asexual reproduction, reducing
the likelihood that we could either retrace our steps or keep from
taking further steps. Cloning-for-biomedical-research and cloning-to-produce-children
both begin with the same act of cloning: the production of a human
embryo that is genetically virtually identical to its progenitor.
The cloned embryo would therefore be the first human organism with
a single genetic "parent" and, equally important, with a genetic
constitution that is known and selected in advance. Both uses of
cloning mark a significant leap in human power and human control
over our genetic origins. Both involve deliberate genetic manipulation
of nascent human life. It is, of course, precisely this genetic
control that makes cloned embryos uniquely appealing and perhaps
uniquely useful to those who seek to conduct research on them. But
we should not be deceived about what we are agreeing to if we agree
to start to clone: saying yes to cloned embryos in laboratories
means saying yes in principle to an ever-expanding genetic
mastery of one generation over the next.
2. The Complete Instrumentalization of Nascent Human Life
By approving the production of cloned embryos for the sole purpose
of research, society would transgress yet another moral boundary:
that separating the different ways in which embryos might become
available for human experimentation. It is one thing, as some have
argued, to conduct research on leftover embryos from IVF procedures,
which were created in attempts to have a child and, once no longer
needed or wanted, are "destined" for destruction in any case. It
is quite another to create embryos solely for research
that will unavoidably and necessarily destroy them. Thus, for example,
the National Bioethics Advisory Commission (in its report on stem
cell research) reasoned that in circumstances where embryos were
going to be discarded anyway, it did not undermine the moral respect
owed to them if they were destroyed in one way (through research)
rather than another (by being discarded when no longer wanted for
IVF).11
By contrast, the Commission reasoned that it was much harder to
embrace the language of respect for the embryo if it were produced
solely for purposes of research and, having been used, then destroyed.
This argument maintained the following moral and practical distinction:
that embryos created for reproduction but no longer desired could,
with proper consent, be used as research subjects, but that embryos
ought not be produced solely in order to be used as research subjects.
So long as we oppose morally and may perhaps one day prohibit legally
the production of cloned children, it is in the very nature of the
case that cloned human embryos will not be acquirable as "spare"
embryos left over from attempts at reproduction. To the contrary,
they will have to be produced solely and explicitly for the purpose
of biomedical research, with no other end in view.
Some have argued that there is no significant moral difference
between creating excess IVF embryos for reproduction knowing
in advance that some will be discarded and creating cloned
embryos for research that leads necessarily to their destruction.
Because in both cases embryos are wittingly destroyed, there is,
so the argument goes, no moral difference here.
When viewed simply in terms of the fates of embryos once they are
created, the distinction between using leftover embryos and creating
embryos solely for research may indeed be morally insignificant.
But when viewed in terms of the different effects these two activities
might have on the moral fabric of society and the different
moral dispositions of those who decide to produce embryos for these
different purposes the issue is more complex. In the eyes
of those who create IVF embryos to produce a child, every embryo,
at the moment of its creation, is a potential child. Even
though more eggs are fertilized than will be transferred to a woman,
each embryo is brought into being as an end in itself, not simply
as a means to other ends. Precisely because one cannot tell which
IVF embryo is going to reach the blastocyst stage, implant itself
in the uterine wall, and develop into a child, the embryo "wastage"
in IVF is more analogous to the embryo wastage in natural sexual
intercourse practiced by a couple trying to get pregnant than it
is to the creation and use of embryos that requires (without exception)
their destruction.
Those who minimize or deny this distinction between producing
embryos hoping that one of them will become a child and producing
embryos so that they can be used (and destroyed) in research
demonstrate the very problem we are worried about. Having become
comfortable with seeing embryos as a means to noble ends (be it
having a child or conducting biomedical research), they have lost
sight of the fact that the embryos that we create as potential children
are not means at all. Even those who remain agnostic about whether
the human embryo is fully one of us should see the ways in which
conducting such research would make us a different society: less
humble toward that which we cannot fully understand, less willing
to extend the boundaries of human respect ever outward, and more
willing to transgress moral boundaries that we have, ourselves,
so recently established, once it appears to be in our own interests
to do so. We find it disquieting, even somewhat ignoble, to treat
what are in fact seeds of the next generation as mere raw material
for satisfying the needs of our own. Doing so would undermine the
very prudence and humility to which defenders of limited embryo
research often appeal: the idea that, while a human embryo may not
be fully one of us, it is not humanly nothing and therefore should
not be treated as a resource alone. But that is precisely what cloning-for-biomedical-research
would do.
3. Opening the Door to Other Moral Hazards
This leads directly to our third concern that the cloning
of human embryos for research will open the door to additional (and
to some of us, far greater) moral hazards. Human suffering from
horrible diseases never comes to an end, and, likewise, our willingness
to use embryonic life in the cause of research, once permitted,
is also unlikely to find any natural stopping point. To set foot
on this slope is to tempt ourselves to become people for whom the
use of nascent human life as research material becomes routinized
and everyday. That much is inherent in the very logic of what we
would do in cloning-for-biomedical-research.
In addition, the reasons justifying production of cloned embryos
for research can be predicted to expand. Today, the demand is for
stem cells; tomorrow it may be for embryonic and fetal organs. The
recent experiments with cloned cow embryos implanted in a cow's
uterus12
already suggest that there may be greater therapeutic potential
using differentiated tissues (for example, kidney primordia) harvested
from early fetuses than using undifferentiated stem cells taken
from the very early embryo. Should this prove to be the case, pressure
will increase to grow cloned human blastocysts to later stages
either in the uteruses of suitably prepared animal hosts or (eventually)
using artificial placenta like structures in the laboratory
in order to obtain the more useful tissues. One can even imagine
without difficulty how a mother might be willing to receive into
her womb as a temporary resident the embryonic clone of her desperately
ill child, in order to harvest for that child life saving
organs or tissues. In such ways the coarsening of our moral sensibilities
can be the fruit of understandable desires. Indeed, to refuse such
further steps in the name of moral wisdom might come to seem increasingly
sentimental, and, even if we were reluctant to give our approval,
we might be hard-pressed to say why.
We should not be self-deceived about our ability to set limits
on the exploitation of nascent life. What disturbs us today we quickly
or eventually get used to; yesterday's repugnance gives way to tomorrow's
endorsement. A society that already tolerates the destruction of
fetuses in the second and third trimesters will hardly be horrified
by embryo and fetus farming (including in animal wombs), if this
should turn out to be helpful in the cure of dreaded diseases.
We realize, of course, that many proponents of cloning-for-biomedical-research
will recommend regulations designed to prevent just such abuses
(that is, the expansion of research to later-stage cloned embryos
and fetuses). Refusing to erect a red light to stop research cloning,
they will propose various yellow lights intended to assure ourselves
that we are proceeding with caution, limits, or tears. Paradoxically,
however, the effect might actually be to encourage us to continue
proceeding with new (or more hazardous) avenues of research; for,
believing that we are being cautious, we have a good conscience
about what we do, and we are unable to imagine ourselves as people
who could take a morally disastrous next step. We are neither wise
enough nor good enough to live without clear limits.
Cloning-for-biomedical-research could require thousands of human
eggs and would, as presently contemplated, give rise, as we have
said, to a new industry of embryo manufacture. This industry would
depend on eggs procured from women, themselves participants in the
research, who would need to take drugs stimulating ovulation and
to submit to the egg retrieval procedure. One might wonder whether
their informed consent is sufficient to permit this in circumstances
where, in the very nature of the case, the research is so preliminary
that it cannot possibly provide effective therapies for patients.
We might also worry lest women who are potential donors (because,
for example, they have sought in vitro fertilization) might be vulnerable
to pressure to participate in this research or financial inducements
to do so. Even if such pressure does not rise to the level of coercion,
we should acknowledge that there are inducements a just society
would not offer and risks it would not ask potential research subjects
themselves vulnerable for a variety of reasons to accept.
To get around the shortage of human eggs and the ethical dilemmas
it could produce, scientists are exploring the possibility of substituting
animal eggs in the initial cloning step of SCNT. Experiments creating
animal-human hybrid-embryos, produced by inserting human DNA into
enucleated rabbit oocytes, have already been conducted in China,
with development up to the blastocyst stage.13
Yet far from solving our ethical dilemma, the use of animal eggs
raises new concerns about animal-human hybrids. We have no idea
where these and later interspecies experiments might lead. Yet the
creation of such chimeras, even in embryonic form, shows how ready
we seem to be to blur further the boundary biological and
moral between human being and animal.
Finally, if we accept even limited uses of cloning-for-biomedical-research,
we significantly increase the likelihood of cloning-to-produce-children.
The technique will gradually be perfected and the cloned embryos
will become available, and those who would be interested in producing
cloned children will find it much easier to do so. The only way
to prevent this from happening would be to prohibit, by law, the
implantation of cloned embryos for the purpose of producing children.
To do so, however, the government would find itself in the unsavory
position of designating a class of embryos that it would be a felony
not to destroy. It would require, not just permit, the
destruction of cloned embryos which seems to us the very opposite
of showing such cloned embryos "special respect."
4. Conclusion: What Prudence Requires
As history so often demonstrates, powers gained for one purpose
are often used for other, less noble ones. We are about to harness
powers over our own (human) nature to be used for our own well-intentioned
purposes. But the knowledge that provides this power does not teach
us how to use it. And given our fallibility, that should give us
pause. We should consider, in making our moral judgment about cloning-for-biomedical-research,
not simply the origin of these cells, but their possible uses (and
misuses), as well as their place in the larger story of our increasing
technological powers. We must keep in mind not simply where we took
these cells from, but where they might take us, and what might be
done with them.
In light of these moral and prudential dangers namely, the
crossing of the boundary from sexual to asexual reproduction; the
possible misuse of our new genetic powers over embryonic life; the
reduction of human embryos to nothing more than a resource and the
coarsening of our moral sensibilities that would come with it; the
prospect of a law that would mandate the destruction of nascent
human life; and the prospect of other (greater) harms down the road,
most notably the production of cloned children, research on later-stage
fetuses, or genetic engineering of future generations we must
take pause and resist. In trying to discern where a wise and prudent
boundary must be drawn to protect those beings who are humanly
inviolable, to prevent the dangers that most tempt us, and to protect
the moral fabric of society we hold that the boundary must
be drawn by prohibiting the production and use of cloned embryos.
To cross this boundary or to set it further down the road
that is, "with limits" is to invite (and perhaps ensure) that
some (or all) of the dehumanizing possibilities described above
will come to pass.
C. What We Owe to the Suffering
The final question to be considered is what we owe to the suffering.
Like our colleagues who endorse cloning-for-biomedical-research,
we believe it would be less than human to turn a blind eye to those
who suffer and need relief, or to stand silent in the face (especially)
of suffering and premature death. In saying "no" to cloning-for-biomedical-research,
we are not closing the door on medical progress not in principle
and not in practice. We are simply acknowledging that, for very
strong moral reasons, progress must come by means that do not involve
the production, use, and destruction of cloned embryos and that
do not reduce nascent human life to a resource for our exploitation.
This does mean, of course, that advances in basic research and progress
in the cure of disease, though not halted, might be slowed (though,
as described above, this is far from certain on scientific grounds).
It is possible that some might suffer in the future because research
proceeded more slowly. We cannot suppose that the moral life comes
without cost. And honesty compels us not to offer guarantees where
our human limits and the unpredictable nature of the future
ensure that no such assurances are possible.
There may be occasions in life when the only means available for
achieving a desired end is a means that it would be wrong to employ.
This is especially true in circumstances such as those considered
here; for to give our initial approval to cloning-for-biomedical-research
is to set foot on a path whose deepest implications can scarcely
be calculated. People sometimes imagine that human beings are responsible
for all the harms they could prevent but do not; yet, this cannot
be true. When we refuse to achieve a good outcome by doing what
is wrong, and thereby perhaps accept some suffering that might have
been avoided, we are not guilty of causing that suffering. To say
otherwise would mean that sufficiently evil men could always hold
us morally hostage. In order to obligate us to do an evil deed,
they need only credibly threaten to do great harm unless we comply.
Were we actually responsible for all the harm we might have prevented
but did not, they would have us in their moral power. If our duty
to prevent harm and suffering were always overriding, if it always
held moral trump, we could not live nobly and justly.
We are not deaf to the voices of those who desperately want biomedical
research to proceed. Indeed, we can feel the force of that desire
ourselves, for all of us and those we love most are
or could one day be patients desperate for a cure. But we are not
only patients or potential patients. We are human beings and citizens,
and we know that relief of suffering, though a great good, is not
the greatest good. As highly as we value health and longer life,
we know that life itself loses its value if we care only for how
long we live, and not also for how we live.
Suppose, then, that we refrain from such research and that future
sufferers say to us: "You might have helped us by approving cloning
for research, but you declined to do so." What could we say to them?
Something like the following: "Yes, perhaps so. But we could have
done so only by destroying, in the present, the sort of world in
which both we and you want to live a world in which, as best
we can, we respect human life and human individuals, the weak and
the strong. To have done it would have meant stepping across boundaries
that are essential to our humanity. And, although we very much want
to leave to our children a world in which suffering can be more
effectively relieved, that is not all we want to leave them. We
want to bequeath to them a world that honors moral limits, a world
in which the good of some human lives is not entirely subordinated
to the good of others, a world in which we seek to respect, as best
we can, the time each human being has and the place each fills."
This understanding of what commitment to our shared humanity requires
is not alien to the efforts of scientific researchers to make progress
in the cure of disease and relief of suffering. Theirs is, after
all, a moral mission, which serves us all and which we all support.
But if history teaches anything, it is the danger of assuming that,
because our motives are praiseworthy and our hope is to heal, our
actions cannot possibly violate or diminish human well-being. Indeed,
we may be least likely to see the dangers when we are most confident
of the goodness of our cause.
Scientists already accept important moral boundaries in research
on human subjects, and they do not regard such boundaries as unwarranted
restrictions on the freedom of scientific research. More generally,
the scientific enterprise is a moral one not only because of the
goals scientists seek but also because of the limits they honor.
Indeed, it is precisely the acceptance of limits that stimulates
creative advance, that forces scientists to conceive of new and
morally acceptable ways of conducting research. Surely, therefore,
before society takes a step that cannot be undone, it should ponder
soberly the moral implications of accepting cloning, even for research.
To approve cloning-for-biomedical-research, to drink from that
cup, is an inviting prospect indeed, but there is a spider in the
cup. When we consider what we owe to the embryo, to our society,
and to the suffering, we can see it more clearly and can, perhaps,
acquire the wisdom and even the courage not to put this cup to our
lips.
* * *
V. Conclusion
In this chapter, Council Members have presented as best we can
the moral cases for and against cloning-for-biomedical-research,
seen in the contexts of efforts to heal the sick; present and projected
developments in reproductive, developmental, and genetic biotechnology;
and the moral concerns for nascent life and the moral well-being
of American society. Our different moral out-looks and judgments
have been preserved and, we hope, clarified. We are now ready to
move from ethics to public policy, in search of the best course
of action regarding human cloning.
ENDNOTES
- Osler, W. "Chauvinism in Medicine" Aequanimitas, with Other
Addresses to Medical Students, Nurses and Practitioners of Medicine
Philadelphia: Blakiston, 1943, p. 267. Back
to Text
- For more information about the scientific and medical case for
cloning-for-biomedical-research, see the following two reports:
(1) National Research Council/Institute of Medicine (NRC/IOM),
Stem Cells and the Future of Regenerative Medicine, Washington
DC, National Academy Press, 2001. (2) National Academy of Sciences
(NAS), Scientific and Medical Aspects of Human Reproductive
Cloning, Washington, DC, National Academy Press, 2002. Back
to Text
- Reyes, M., et al. "Origin of endothelial progenitors in human
postnatal bone marrow" Journal of Clinical Investigation,
109: 337-346, 2002. Back
to Text
- Jiang, Y. et al. "Pluripotency of mesenchymal stem cells derived
from adult marrow" Nature, 418: 41-49, 2002. Back
to Text
- Rideout III, W.M. et al. "Correction of a genetic defect by
nuclear transplantation and combined cell and gene therapy" Cell,
109: 17-27, 2002. Back
to Text
- Wilson, J.Q. "On Abortion" Commentary, 97(1): 21ff,
1994. Back
to Text
- Lanza, R.P., et al. "Generation of histocompatible tissues using
nuclear transplantation" Nature Biotechnology, 20: 689-696,
2002. Back
to Text
- Brian Appleyard calls attention to this passage in his book,
Brave New Worlds: Staying Human in the Genetic Future
(New York: Viking, 1998). Back
to Text
- Cited in Kass, L. "The Meaning of Life-in the Laboratory" The
Public Interest, No. 146, pp. 45-46, Winter 2002. Back
to Text
- Jonas, H. "Philosophical Reflections on Experimenting With Human
Subjects" in Readings on Ethical and Social Issues in Biomedicine,
ed. Richard W. Wertz (Prentice-Hall, 1973), p. 32. Back
to Text
- National Bioethics Advisory Commission, Ethical Issues in
Human Stem Cell Research, volume I, p. 53. Bethesda, MD:
Government Printing Office, 1999. Back
to Text
- See endnote 7, above. Back
to Text
- Leggett, K., and A. Regalado. "China Stem Cell Research Surges
as Western Nations Ponder Ethics" Wall Street Journal,
March 6, 2002, p. A1. Back
to Text
_____________________
- Once such cells were produced in one laboratory, they could
be stored at low temperatures and supplied to other laboratories
for study. And so, for at least this particular area of cloning-for-biomedical-research,
it might not be necessary to perform the cloning experiment more
than a few times for each disease, making it possible that the
number of cloned embryos required will be limited. Back
to Text
- See Chapter
Four, in the section on stem cells and regenerative medicine.
Back
to Text
- In the first case, human individuality would be present from
the start, in the second case, it would not, a morally significant
distinction to some people. Back
to Text
- See, for example, "The Ethics of Stem Cell Research," by Gene
Outka, a paper presented and discussed at the Council's April
2002 meeting. Outka extends the principle "that nothing more be
lost" to justify use of excess IVF embryos in research, but argues
that this principle cannot be used to justify creating cloned
(or IVF) embryos explicitly for research (available online at
www.bioethics.gov). A slightly revised version has been published
in the Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal 12(2), 175-213,
2002. Back
to Text
- To increase the chances of keeping people from a serious transgression
(the law), a prohibition is imposed (the fence) on activities
that might lead or tempt one to commit it. For example, if the
goal is to keep people from engaging in commerce on the Sabbath,
one makes it unlawful for them to handle money on the Sabbath.
Back
to Text
- This means of reducing demand for human oocytes would imply
increased SCNT of human nuclei into animal eggs, a practice that
may bring additional moral questions. It was unanimously opposed
by the National Institutes of Health Human Embryo Research Panel
in its 1994 report (p. 82). Back
to Text
- We are especially impressed by the promise of the research of
Dr. Catherine Verfaillie and her group, showing the stability
and multipotency of cells derived from bone marrow of animals
and human adults. Should this work prove successful, it might
serve all of the purposes said to require cells from cloned embryos.
See presentation by Dr. Verfaillie at the April 25, 2002, meeting
of the Council (transcript on the Council's website, www.bioethics.gov)
and the papers cited in endnotes 3 and 4 to this chapter. Back
to Text
- That the embryo in question is produced by cloning and not by
the fertilization of an egg should not, in our view, lead us to
treat it differently. The cloned embryo is different in its origins,
but not in its possible destiny, from a normal embryo. Were it
brought to term it too would indisputably be a member of the human
species. We caution against defining the cloned embryo into a
"non-embryo"-especially when science provides no warrant for doing
so. Back
to Text
- Thus, for example, the 1994 report of the National Institutes
of Health Human Embryo Research Panel, even while endorsing embryo
research under certain circumstances, spoke (p. xi) of "respect
for the special character of the preimplantation human embryo"
and affirmed (p. x) that "the preimplantation human embryo warrants
serious moral consideration as a developing form of human life"
(though not, the report added, "the same moral status as infants
and children"). Another report, Ethical Issues in Human Stem
Cell Research, released in 1999 by the National Bioethics
Advisory Commission, while declining to claim that the embryo
should receive "the same level of respect accorded persons" (p.
50), spoke of and seemed to endorse the "ethical intuition" that
"the act of creating an embryo for reproduction is respectful
in a way that is commensurate with the moral status of embryos,
while the act of creating an embryo for research is not" (p. 56).
Back
to Text
Chapter Seven
Public Policy Options
The connection between moral assessment and public policy, here
as elsewhere, is hardly straightforward. The relation of morality
to law is notoriously complex, especially in free societies such
as our own in which citizens may live their lives according to their
own moral views. At the same time, however, practices deemed seriously
wrong and harmful are outlawed, from incest and sexual abuse to
slavery and racial discrimination. In addition, law functions not
only to encourage or discourage conduct but also as a moral teacher.
It expresses the social norms of the community, whether by fostering
public education and medical research or by discouraging dishonest
business practices and teenage pregnancy. Whether and how the law
should address any given morally charged topic is often a debatable
matter, requiring careful study and prudent judgment. Not everything
that is morally defensible should be encouraged by public policy;
not everything that is morally troubling should be legally proscribed.
These general remarks apply also to the case at hand. The moral
assessments of the previous two chapters do not carry self-evident
policy recommendations. Even a thoroughly developed moral position
on either or both of the uses of human cloning still leaves open
the question of what public policy would be appropriate, prudent,
and effective. One can be morally opposed to cloning-to-produce-children,
yet also oppose making it illegal, say, because of hesitation to
increase the police power of the state in matters of reproduction.
Or one can have no personal moral objection to cloning-for-biomedical-research,
but still find practical reasons to favor a moratorium on such activity,
say, because one wants to develop regulatory institutions before
allowing the research to proceed. Moral principle and judgment,
though necessary, are not sufficient for deliberating about what
to do about human cloning. Prudence is also required.
In this chapter, we consider a broad range of public policy options.
We assess and compare these options in the hope of seeing our way
clear, in the eighth and final chapter of this report, to offer
recommendations that comport, not only with our ethical judgments,
but also with our sense as citizens of what is prudent, practical,
and appropriate for this country at this time.
The policy debate about human cloning is a particularly vivid example
of the tension between competing public goods, between the goods
served by biomedical science and technology and other moral and
social goods important to community life. The desire to ban human
cloning, whether for producing children or for biomedical research,
arises primarily from moral and social objections made in the name
of human dignity, individuality, and respect for life. The opposition
to a comprehensive ban on human cloning arises primarily from a
belief that cloning research may lead to new remedies for human
diseases and disabilities, backed also by appeals to the principle
of freedom for scientific inquiry and technological innovation.
Assumptions about the relative merits of these competing goods,
as well as about the broader relation between science and society,
lie just beneath the surface of this debate. Wittingly or not, these
assumptions inform how people think about the various policy options
proposed for dealing with human cloning. A brief examination of
the more general question of the relation between science and society
might clarify the principles that should guide our approach to a
national policy on human cloning.
I. Science and Society
Since its birth in the seventeenth century, modern science
and especially modern medicine has been guided by a desire
to improve and elevate the human condition. Unlike ancient science,
which sought speculative knowledge of what things are purely
as an end in itself satisfying to the knower, modern science from
the start sought effective knowledge of how things work,
in the service of what Francis Bacon called "the conquest of nature
for the relief of man's estate." Since then, scientists have been
increasingly motivated not only by a deep desire to know,
but also by a desire to do: that is, to provide resources,
know-how, and relief in humanity's pursuit of health, happiness,
and comfort. Biomedical scientists especially have pursued a dual
goal: to increase our knowledge and understanding of living nature
and to help the sick and the suffering.
In exchange for the promise of great human benefits, the practice
of science entered into an unprecedented relation to the larger
society. Scientists gradually acquired a privileged standing in
modern societies, first with protections against persecution and
censorship, later with public recognition and financial support.
But it deserves to be noted that, insofar as the public respect
for science rests on its moral intention and its ability to deliver
the goods that society wants, scientists tacitly subject themselves
to public scrutiny and moral judgment of their work, both as to
ends and to means. The tacit social contract between scientists
and society freedom and support for scientists, benefits for
all humanity is double-sided: on the one hand, the opportunity
for scientists to be public benefactors and recognized as such;
on the other hand, the need, in cases where values conflict, for
scientists to defend what they do in terms of the community's judgments
about the relation of scientific activity to other moral and social
goods.
As we have noted in the previous chapters, in the twentieth century,
biomedical science made tremendous advances, resulting in both greater
knowledge of how the human body works and greater ability to affect
its workings. The results have been so dramatic, and so beneficial,
that in the United States today virtually no one questions the benefits
of the modern scientific endeavor, especially in medicine. This
consensus about benefits has expressed itself as consistently strong
public support for public funding of basic research, as well as
strong support for the freedom of scientists to set their own research
agendas, limited only by their curiosity, their imaginations, and
our commonly agreed-upon moral and ethical norms. The tacit "contract"
or relationship between science and society recognizes and celebrates
the great benefits of freedom for all involved.
But for all these great benefits and good purposes, there are also
times when the activities of scientists or the products of scientific
work can imperil society and its members. For one thing, the work
of scientific research is by its nature experimental. Scientific
inquiry involves action, not only observation or theory. For this
reason, freedom of inquiry does not adequately describe
the freedom that scientific work requires and is generally granted.
It may be more accurate to say that scientists desire and often
receive great freedom of action. Yet because scientists
learn by doing, some of what scientists do can be dangerous or inappropriate.
And because some of their actions may infringe on the rights, security,
or dignity of individuals, or on the principles and interests of
society as a whole, scientific freedom of action cannot be absolute.
In addition, many of the technological products of scientific research
can be used to do harm as well as good. Just as society has moved
in the past to restrict access to dangerous nuclear and biological
agents, as well as to restrict public access to information about
these things, so too will society be confronted with moral challenges
by the new biomedical technologies. Technologies that disclose our
genetic abnormalities or that alter the human genome, neurotropic
drugs that can enhance (or destroy) memory or libido, computer implants
in human brains these and many other technological possibilities
now on the horizon may raise profound moral and social challenges
to privacy, freedom, equality, dignity, and human self-understanding.
As citizens we may indeed we must decide whether and
where to limit potentially harmful research or technology even as
we continue to desire and uphold free intellectual inquiry and technological
innovation.
American society has done this in the past. The various codes of
conduct for human experimentation, discussed at several points in
this report, demonstrate some of the ways in which the polity has
established important moral boundaries that biomedical researchers
must respect. In addition, rules and restrictions governing the
pharmaceutical industry, the practice of medicine, the sale of organs
for transplantation, the handling of biohazards, the development
of biological weapons, and numerous other areas of scientific and
technological work show that even given our desire for scientific
advance and our belief in the inherent value of freedom, the pursuit
of research and technology has not been allowed to trump all other
concerns.
Thus we conclude that in the realm of genetics and reproduction,
as in many others, boundaries and regulations may be needed: lines
may need to be drawn that none may cross, guidelines may need to
be established that all must follow. Because the wisdom needed to
decide how scientific knowledge and technology should be used is
not something that science can provide by itself, these boundaries
and regulations must be set by the whole community, democratically,
through its representative institutions, and not only by those who
are experts in the scientific work involved. Our analysis in Chapters
Five and Six of the serious moral and social questions raised by
human cloning has persuaded us that human cloning in both
its forms is an appropriate area for public policy.
II. Public Policy Options: General Considerations
A. The Scope of Policy
Having decided that human cloning is an activity fit for public
policy decision, we still face many questions. Does it warrant legislative
proscription, governmental regulation, professional oversight or
self-regulation, or merely civil tort liability for bad results?
And how broadly or narrowly should we delimit the domain in which
human cloning is to be considered? Although the ethical analysis
in this report has often concentrated on human cloning considered
on its own, when considering public policy it is especially important
to recall the larger contexts in which human cloning belongs. As
we emphasized in Chapters One and Two, human cloning (in both its
possible uses) would be but a special area of a larger domain of
biotechnology, made possible by present and projected techniques
of embryo research, assisted reproduction, genetic screening, and
genetic engineering all of which are coming to be grouped
under the field of "reprogenetics." As we contemplate possible policy
options regarding human cloning, it behooves us to consider what
cloning's place within this broader context might mean for public
policy.
Many other countries have in fact taken up cloning in this broader
context. In Germany, for example, this broader approach has taken
the form of a series of legal proscriptions and restrictions, centered
on the Embryo Protection Act of 1990. The act treats all embryo
research together and prohibits all interventions not undertaken
for the well-being of the embryo (including the creation of embryos
specifically for research). The German system also includes specific
rules for IVF procedures, and in general treats all interventions
involving the human embryo under one rubric. Human cloning, for
whatever purposes, is legislatively prohibited.
In the United Kingdom, too, policy on these subjects takes as its
organizing principle the human embryo itself, though the approach
here is regulative rather than proscriptive. The British system
is centered around a regulatory body the Human Fertilization
and Embryology Authority (HFEA), created in 1990 charged with
monitoring and regulating essentially all of what has come to be
called reprogenetics, including human cloning, both for producing
children and for biomedical research. The HFEA regulates infertility
treatment and clinical work; storage of gametes and embryos; and
all embryo research, whether publicly or privately funded. It licenses
these various activities, monitors compliance, sets standards of
practice, establishes limits and requirements on the use of embryos
for various purposes, and maintains a detailed information registry
about both assisted reproduction and embryo research. Human cloning
is treated within this broader regulatory scheme: cloning-to-produce-children
is not permitted; cloning-for-biomedical-research is allowed, but
only with cloned embryos no older than fourteen days.
Canada is completing the process of establishing a national system,
combining elements of legal proscription and governmental regulation,
to govern all technological activities used to help people have
children as well as the use of embryos in research. Some activities
would be permitted and regulated, others would be prohibited by
law. The chosen point of departure is not the human embryo, but
rather the goods of human health and dignity: to protect the health
and safety of Canadians; to prevent commercial exploitation of reproduction;
and to protect human individuality and diversity and the integrity
of the human genome. A single broad regulatory body, the Assisted
Human Reproduction Agency of Canada, would issue and renew licenses
for assisted reproduction facilities, collect and analyze health
information, set policies, and monitor compliance. Among the prohibited
activities are all human cloning, whether to produce children or
for biomedical research. Human embryos no longer needed for infertility
may be used for stem cell research (with consent of the progenitors).
But producing in vitro embryos for research purposes is prohibited,
except for efforts to improve assisted reproduction procedures.1
Several other countries have approached this area of biotechnology
with a similar broad outlook. The United States to date has not;
indeed we lack any national monitoring, oversight, or regulatory
system in this area. It may therefore be appropriate, in connection
with thinking about specific policies for human cloning in the United
States, to initiate discussions of a national policy for these related
arenas. Doing so might allow us to regard the question of embryo
research in its full scope, and to consider it together with the
closely related issues that arise when the techniques of assisted
reproduction come together with those of genetic diagnosis and potential
genetic engineering. In putting forward its recommendations in the
next chapter, the Council will take into account this broader context
of related biotechnologies.
Yet, much as it would be desirable to consider public policy regarding
human cloning in its larger context, it is for us also necessary
to consider it on its own. Owing to the immediate concern over the
prospect of cloning-to-produce-children, legislative proposals and
public debate have largely treated the subject of human cloning
in isolation though for reasons we have noted, it has overlapped
with the controversy about embryonic stem cell research. Accordingly,
the policy options presented below are drawn for the most part from
the ongoing public and legislative debate about human cloning, and
therefore direct themselves to legislative alternatives regarding
cloning in particular.
B. A Legislative Complication
There is a complication that bedevils prospects for legislation
regarding human cloning. Given that human cloning may be used for
two very different purposes to produce children and for biomedical
research one might think that these two different uses could
be treated independently, just as we have done (for the most part)
in the ethical analyses in Chapters Five and Six. The ethical issues
of cloning-to-produce-children and cloning-for-biomedical-research
differ considerably, and, as our own discussions have indicated,
one's moral assessment of the second can be independent of one's
moral assessment of the first. Some people who oppose cloning-to-produce-children
may favor cloning-for-biomedical-research; some people who oppose
producing embryos solely for research may object less forcefully
to cloning-to-produce-children (should it ever become safe to attempt
it). And people who oppose both uses may differ as to which they
think is the worse. Given these variations, it would seem sensible
to disaggregate the two forms of cloning and develop independent
public policies for each.
But this is easier said than done. The reason is simple: both forms
begin in the same way with the act of cloning (by somatic cell nuclear
transfer [SCNT]) that produces a cloned human embryo. It is therefore
difficult perhaps impossible to craft a public policy
regarding one use of cloned human embryos that does not, at least
tacitly but usually explicitly, also affect the other. A thoroughgoing
attempt to prevent cloning-to-produce-children by banning the first
step would also prevent cloning-for-biomedical-research. An attempt
to promote cloning-for-biomedical-research might well have consequences
for cloning-to-produce-children (for example, by improving the technique
or by increasing the likelihood of attempts to initiate a pregnancy).
An attempt to prevent cloning-to-produce-children at the step of
transfer of a cloned embryo to initiate a pregnancy would tacitly
approve the initial creation of cloned embryos for other purposes.
Moreover, by imposing penalties on implantation while sanctioning
creation, a policy that banned only transfer to a uterus would in
effect require, by law, that cloned human embryos be destroyed.
Even if one thinks only of the task of statutory drafting, the
difficulty persists. For if one wants to make a particular action
illegal, one must specify precisely the act to be proscribed. It
turns out to be very difficult to specify precisely and unambiguously
the forbidden act of human cloning without touching both uses at
once. "It shall be unlawful to attempt to clone a human being" is
simple enough to say, but vexing to specify. The meaning of the
term "human being" is contested: does it mean only a child or adult,
or is an embryo too a human being, albeit in its primordial stage?
The definition of "to clone" must specify either the initial act
of somatic cell nuclear transfer or the birth of a cloned child.
"Attempting to clone" will mean either somatic cell nuclear
transfer itself or the transfer of the resulting cloned embryo to
a woman's uterus.
There is, of course, one possible policy approach that could disentangle
the two uses of human cloning, but it would require dealing with
cloning-for-biomedical-research in a different context. Since cloning-for-biomedical-research
is one form of embryo research another is research that uses
embryos produced by IVF one could have a broad policy on all
embryo research, which would then necessarily apply to research
with cloned embryos. Several states have separate laws
that cover research on all human embryos, cloned or not. In these
cases, a law to deal with the special practice of cloning-to-produce-children
could then be added without difficulty. And, as we have indicated,
in the United Kingdom and several other countries, there is a broad
regulatory system for handling all activities involving human embryos
both for research and for initiating pregnancies into
which further regulations regarding cloned embryos may
easily be fit. But the legislative debates in Congress, both in
1998 and in 2001-2002, have not squarely addressed independent treatment
of embryo research in general and cloning-for-biomedical-research
in particular. That fact shapes our examination of specific public
policy options.
III. Public Policy Options: Specific Alternatives
What sort of policy regarding human cloning would be most
appropriate in this country at this time? In approaching the various
alternatives, we operate on the following premises.
First, given the seriousness of the subject, we favor a policy
that makes an explicit and considered decision about whether to
proceed. Should our society come to have no rules or guidelines
regarding human cloning, it should do so deliberately, not by default.
Second, we need to decide whose decision and responsibility
this should be. And while we may differ among ourselves on the answer
to this question, we agree that whichever persons, institutions,
or agencies of government have authority for the decision and any
subsequent oversight, the responsible parties should be answerable
to and held accountable by the people and their representatives.
This is not an arena where secrecy or lack of accountability should
be tolerated.
Third, whether one opts for permission with or without regulation
or for legislative proscription, permanent or temporary, we believe
that the following two balancing principles should be followed:
(1) Because of the gravity of the issues at stake, whoever bears
the power of decision needs to be persuaded that we should now
proceed with human cloning, in either or both of its forms. (2)
At the same time, we should not stand in the way of proceeding simply
out of some vague fear of possible future harms of unknown magnitude;
we should interfere only if the harms are deemed serious, important
to the common good, and likely to occur.
A. Federal or State Jurisdiction?
We begin, as we should in America, by examining human cloning in
the context of our constitutional system and, in particular, of
our special form of federalism. In short, we must consider which
level of government has jurisdiction. Human cloning is not obviously
a federal concern, nor is it plainly outside the jurisdiction of
the states; thus it might be presumed to be a matter for regulation
by the states alone. Certainly a number of states have moved to
legislate in this area. As of this writing, twenty-two state legislatures
have considered bills on cloning, and six of them have passed laws
on the subject. Of these, five directly or indirectly prohibit both
forms of human cloning, while one prohibits only cloning-to-produce-children.i
It is possible to argue that human cloning is one of those many
issues, essentially local in nature, that call more or less exclusively
for the exercise of local self-government, which in the American
system means primarily government by the states. And yet, a number
of factors point to the need to consider a federal policy as well.
For one thing, as we hope the foregoing chapters have made clear,
human cloning-to-produce-children has nationwide implications, with
potentially profound effects on individuals, families, and all of
society. This view is reflected in the efforts in Congress to legislate
on the subject, first in 1998 and again in 2001 and 2002. President
Clinton made clear, in his executive order on human cloning,2
that he regards it as a federal issue; and President Bush has done
likewise in several public statements.3
For another thing, the federal government plays an extensive role
in funding and regulating scientific research. Insofar as there
has been a role for government in the oversight of scientific work
in America, it has generally been filled by the federal government,
for reasons of scale and efficacy and also to some extent of historical
accident. So long as this remains the case, questions relating to
the funding and regulation of human cloning will, in practice, be
addressed mostly or even solely at the federal level.
Moreover, it can be assumed that, if they remain legally permissible,
both forms of human cloning would tend to enter into interstate
commerce, thus bringing them within the purview of Congress, at
least as far as its power to regulate interstate commerce allows.
Historically, when several or most of the states have proscribed
some activity they regard as injurious to public health, safety,
or morals (such as prostitution or the use of narcotic drugs), the
federal government has tended to enact laws supportive of the states',
or most of the states', moral proscriptions, either by restricting
interstate commerce (as in the Mann Act relating to prostitution)
or even by directly prohibiting the activity itself (as in the Federal
Controlled Substances Act). Since the states have begun to act on
human cloning, it has become valid therefore to ask whether federal
legislation is also needed.
Finally, human cloning has become a subject of international law.
A number of nations have moved to prohibit one or both forms of
human cloning, and the United Nations is currently debating whether
to promulgate an international convention to ban cloning-to-produce-children.
Since only the federal government can make treaties or conduct foreign
policy for the whole nation, it seems likely that at some point
the United and not merely the separate States will be
under pressure to legislate on this subject.
For some or all of these reasons, we think it reasonable to conclude
that human cloning, of either variety, is a fit subject for debate
and action at the federal level.ii
B. Seven Basic Policy Options
With respect to each form of human cloning, cloning-to-produce-children
and cloning-for-biomedical-research, there are two basic alternatives:
permit or prohibit. For each of these alternatives, there are again
two further possibilities: permit with or without regulation; prohibit
indefinitely ("ban") or for a limited time ("moratorium"). (The
alternative "permit with regulation" might or might not make permission
contingent upon getting the regulatory system in place beforehand.)
Among the numerous permutations and possibilities, we now take up
seven basic policy options that have been publicly discussed and
that appear to us worthy of consideration:
- Policy Option 1: Professional self-regulation with
no legislative action ("self-regulation").
- Policy Option 2: A ban on cloning-to-produce-children,
with neither endorsement nor restriction of cloning-for-biomedical-research
("ban plus silence").
- Policy Option 3: A ban on cloning-to-produce-children,
with regulation of the use of cloned embryos for biomedical research
("ban plus regulation").
- Policy Option 4: Governmental regulation, perhaps by
a new federal agency, with no legislative prohibitions ("regulation
of both").
- Policy Option 5: A ban on all human cloning, whether
to produce children or for biomedical research ("ban on both").
- Policy Option 6: A ban on cloning-to-produce-children,
with a moratorium, or temporary ban, on cloning-for-biomedical-research
("ban plus moratorium").
- Policy Option 7: A moratorium, or temporary ban, on
all human cloning, whether to produce children or for biomedical
research ("moratorium on both").
In considering each of these options, we bear in mind four basic
questions: (1) How would the policy be enforced and by whom? (2)
On what moral opinions, and on what views of the role of government,
is it based? (3) What are the arguments in favor? (4) What are the
possible objections? To avoid needless repetition, where two options
are very similar we refrain from repeating the same arguments at
great length, and instead focus on the major new points worthy of
note.
* * *
Policy Option 1: Professional self-regulation with no legislative
action ("self-regulation").
This option would enact no new legal restraints on human cloning,
and rely instead on self-regulation and private decision making.
Passing no law on the subject would maintain the legal status quo;
it would leave in place the existing moratorium on federal funding
for either form of human cloning, while also leaving private parties
free to use private funds to conduct either form of human cloning,
as they see fit, consistent with state law.
This approach would let physicians and patients decide privately
whether to engage in cloning-to-produce-children 3
It would rely upon the people actually engaged in cloning-for-biomedical-research
to establish a mechanism for self-regulation and to prevent abuses.
And it could utilize tort liability to deter tragedies and mishaps,
by holding people legally responsible for harms inflicted upon a
cloned child or his or her mother.
This approach assumes that neither form of human cloning poses
moral or practical dangers sufficient to require public action.
It assumes that the harms of cloning-to-produce-children are not
so grave as to merit a legal restriction, and it sees no harm, or
at least negligible harm, in cloning-for-biomedical-research. It
also assumes that government's role in regulating scientific research
and reproductive medicine should be minimal; that federal legislation
may cause more harms than it prevents; that self-regulation provides
sufficient safeguards against the worst abuses of cloning practices;
that the subject is so complex that the people best qualified to
regulate it are the experts in the field themselves; or that any
more restrictive policy is unlikely to succeed and likely to drive
scientific talent overseas to more permissive jurisdictions.
This hands-off approach would seem to ignore the widespread public
and congressional support for a ban on cloning-to-produce-children,
as evidenced in the July 31, 2001, vote in the House of Representatives,
where nearly every member voted for some kind of federal ban on
at least one form of human cloning. Of this option, it may be asked:
Is cloning-to-produce-children so morally unproblematic that we
could safely leave people free to try it? Would tort liability really
be sufficient to deter abuses? And can we afford a laissez-faire
policy on what is surely only the first of a series of powerful
new genetic technologies? For those who answer "no" to any of these
questions, it will be necessary to seek another option.
Policy Option 2: A ban on cloning-to-produce-children,
with neither endorsement nor restriction of cloning-for-biomedical-research
("ban plus silence").
A second option would be to prohibit cloning-to-produce-children
but remain silent on cloning-for-biomedical-research. Such a policy
would prohibit the implantation rather than the creation of cloned
human embryos. By remaining silent on the question of creating cloned
human embryos, this approach would not establish an oversight mechanism
or other means of keeping track of cloned embryos or otherwise preventing
implantation before the act itself is undertaken. It would therefore
probably not require a new enforcement agency; enforcement of the
ban would presumably fall to the Department of Justice.
This approach assumes that cloning-to-produce-children is sufficiently
unacceptable as to merit legal prohibition, but minimizes or sets
aside the disputed question of cloning-for-biomedical-research.
It seeks to balance the responsibility for establishing public control
over potential misuses of technology with public tolerance for competing
worldviews and interests. It permits potentially valuable medical
and scientific research to go forward. It preserves the current
federal embryo research policy, which (1) permits all embryo
research to proceed unimpeded with private funds, (2) permits research
on certain embryonic stem cell lines to proceed under federal guidance
with public funds, and (3) leaves open, for continued debate, the
question of whether there should be public funding for embryo and
embryonic stem cell research.
Against this option, it can be argued that it is not possible for
the government to be neutral on the question of cloning-for-biomedical-research.
It is difficult, if not impossible, to write a statute banning the
act of implanting cloned embryos without tacitly sanctioning the
creation of the cloned embryos in the first place. Thus, a ban on
cloning-to-produce-children not accompanied by a prohibition on
cloning-for-biomedical-research would put the government in the
position of allowing the creation of a class of (cloned) human embryos
and then effectively mandating their destruction (or at least their
perpetual preservation in cold storage), a class of (cloned) human
embryos that it would be a felony to try to keep alive to birth.
Also such a partial ban could arguably make cloning-to-produce-children
more likely to occur. After all, without a regulatory system in
place to keep track of and govern the use of cloned human embryos,
the ban on implantation would be difficult to monitor and enforce.
The commercial production of embryos for research would be protected
by industrial secrecy. The transfer of cloned embryos to begin a
pregnancy would be virtually undetectable and protected by doctor-patient
confidentiality. Those charged with monitoring and enforcing the
ban on cloning-to-produce-children would not know who is doing what
with cloned human embryos. Moreover, actually enforcing the ban
in the event of a violation would be nearly impossible. Once a clonal
pregnancy has begun, there would be no real remedy except a forced
abortion, an untenable option.
Policy Option 3: A ban on cloning-to-produce-children,
with regulation of the use of cloned embryos for biomedical research
("ban plus regulation").
This option would be similar to Option 2 ("ban plus silence"),
but in place of silence would require the establishment of a system
of oversight and regulation of cloning-for-biomedical-research.
These functions would be carried out by a regulatory agency (new
or existing) authorized to do some or all of the following things:
- Establish what may and may not be done with cloned human embryos
once they are created, including a prohibition on implantation of
cloned human embryos into human, animal, or artificial wombs.
- License and conduct prior review of all research involving cloned
embryos.
- Establish guidelines for the protection of all human subjects
participating in the research, including donors of eggs and nuclei.
- Register and track each individual cloned human embryo.
- Establish the number of days beyond which a cloned human embryo
may not be grown in vitro, and enforce this requirement.
- Monitor and regulate financial transactions regarding cloned embryos
and human oocytes used in cloning-for-biomedical-research.
- Monitor corporate, academic, and industrial cloning-for-biomedical-research,
check for compliance, and enforce sanctions against violations of
regulations.
To be effective, such a regulatory structure would have to be
applied to both federally funded and privately funded research.
Its first purpose would be to facilitate the ban on cloning-to-produce-children,
by keeping close track of all research using cloned human embryos.
Its second aim would be to enforce certain general standards for
the handling and use of cloned human embryos, to ensure that they
are not created for frivolous purposes, used irresponsibly, or
treated in ways that go beyond what American society deems morally
acceptable.
This option assumes that neutrality on the question of cloning-for-biomedical-research
is neither possible nor desirable. Instead, it assumes that a
system is needed to regulate and limit the use of cloned embryos
both in the interest of preventing cloning-to-produce-children,
and in the interest of establishing a clear ethical framework
for undertaking cloning-for-biomedical-research and allowing that
research to flourish. At the same time, such a system would establish
clear rules and limits to prevent abuses for example, experimentation
on later-stage embryos and fetuses or attempts to produce cloned
children.
This new task could be assigned to an existing regulatory agency
(or combination of agencies), such as the Food and Drug Administration
or the National Institutes of Health, or, alternatively, it could
be carried out by a new regulatory agency devised specifically
for the purpose.
Establishment of a regulatory structure may be aided by the study
of models in other countries, such as the United Kingdom's Human
Fertilization and Embryology Authority (HFEA) or the Assisted
Human Reproduction Agency being brought into existence in Canada
taking into account, of course, the important differences
between their political, economic, and health-care systems and
our own.
Regulation, for these proponents, would limit the uses of cloned
embryos to especially promising and worthy biomedical research
and would set boundaries beyond which such embryos may not be
grown or exploited. For some proponents of this option, such oversight
and regulation would be aimed primarily at preventing the use
of cloned embryos to produce children. For others, regulation
is called for to ensure that cloned human embryos be treated not
simply as a natural resource but with appropriate measures of
respect owed them as humanembryos.
Against this option can be raised some of the same objections
that were raised against Option 2 ("ban plus silence"), namely,
that it puts the government in the new position of requiring the
destruction of nascent human life, and that it could, by allowing
the production of cloned human embryos, make cloning-to-produce-children
more likely. It might also be argued against this option that
setting up a workable regulatory structure is either impossible
or impossible to do very quickly. After all, the IVF and assisted-reproduction
industry is today largely unregulated in any way that could be
called coordinated, comprehensive, or systematic. The federal
government has no experience in regulating or keeping track of
the number and fate of embryos produced in IVF clinics.4
And the biotechnology industry has shown little enthusiasm for
outside regulation. Establishing an effective regulatory regime
could take several years of trial and error, during which time
cloned embryos might be mishandled or implanted in an effort to
produce children. There are also the dangers that regulatory bodies
often prove ineffective and unaccountable and that they are vulnerable
to capture by special interests that have a large stake, economic
or other, in their regulatory decisions but little incentive to
respect the permanent and aggregate interests of the nation. Establishing
the regulatory body overseeing human cloning-for-biomedical-research
within the National Institutes of Health, for example, would not
be reassuring to those who worry that the fate of the embryo will
always be subordinated to the imperative for research. In this
view, regulation is not enough.
Policy Option 4: Governmental regulation, perhaps by
a new federal agency, with no legislative prohibitions ("regulation
of both").
This option is similar to the regulatory half of Option 3 ("ban
plus regulation"), but the regulatory agency would have authority
to set policy and guidelines also regarding cloning-to-produce-children.
In addition to the functions listed in the description of Option
3, the regulatory body would determine if and when human cloning
techniques were sufficiently safe to warrant attempts to produce
children by human cloning. The entity might also function as a
licensing agency, setting down clear guidelines delineating acceptable
and unacceptable purposes for such a practice (for example, it
might choose to permit cloning to "replace" a deceased child but
not to "replicate" a famous athlete).
The major argument for this option is flexibility: as the science
and technology of human cloning proceeds in nonhuman animals,
and as the public's views develop in response to new information
and new debates, the nation will not be locked into a legislatively
defined position that might later appear to have been misguided.
Either a congressional ban or the refusal to enact a ban may prove
to be a decision that will later look undesirable and yet difficult
to undo.
Against this option are many of the same objections raised against
the regulatory part of Option 3. Also, it may be argued that,
given our society's strong moral opposition to cloning-to-produce-children,
any decision to permit such a practice, even in exceptional cases,
should not be left to a regulatory body; it should rather require
a decision by people directly accountable to the voters. This
option fails that test.
Policy Option 5: A ban on all human cloning, whether
to produce children or for biomedical research ("ban on both").
This option would ban the initial act of human cloning
the production of cloned human embryos regardless of the
intended purpose. It would thus prohibit both forms of human cloning.
Specifically, this approach would proscribe the act of producing
cloned human embryos by means of SCNT. Although enforcing the
ban would be the responsibility of law enforcement agencies
as would enforcing a ban on cloning-to-produce-children-the "policing
of laboratories" would hardly be necessary. Financial and criminal
penalties, along with the inability to publish, patent, or profit
from (the now illegal) work involving cloned human embryos, would
by themselves eliminate nearly all incentive to clone. The ban
would deter by subjecting to prosecution and social stigma any
researchers or institutions whose efforts to create cloned human
embryos came to public attention.
As we have seen in previous chapters, some proponents of this
option argue that the creation, use, and ultimate destruction
of cloned human embryos solely for research is morally unacceptable,
either in itself or because of its moral consequences. Others
hold that a ban only on the transferring of cloned embryos to
a woman's uterus, even with additional regulations, would fail
to prevent the cloning of a child, and that human cloning must
be comprehensively stopped before it starts. Also, any regulatory
arrangements that allowed cloning-for-biomedical-research within
legally established limits would put the federal government
in the novel and morally troubling position of mandating the destruction
of nascent life.
In favor of this approach it can be argued that a "ban on both"
would steer scientists toward less morally troubling (and, in
the view of some, more medically promising) forms of biomedical
research. Indeed, some argue that pursuing cloning-for-biomedical-research
might actually hurt those patients whom it claims to help, by
diverting valuable resources away from more promising areas of
research or more urgent health-care needs. By taking this option,
some proponents argue, America would send a strong signal of moral
leadership to the rest of the world, where the human cloning question
is also currently being debated.
Against this option it is frequently and vigorously argued that
prohibiting cloning-for-biomedical-research would cut off a promising
avenue of medical research. It is also argued that forbidding
such research here may simply drive American talent overseas and
thus diminish American scientific preeminence and economic strength.
Policy Option 6: A ban on cloning-to-produce-children,
with a moratorium, or temporary ban, on cloning-for-biomedical-research
("ban plus moratorium").
This option would impose a permanent legal prohibition on cloning-to-produce-children,
by banning the creation and subsequent transfer of cloned embryos
into a woman's uterus. At the same time, it would also prohibit
the creation of cloned human embryos for any reason, but would
require a mandatory review of that latter prohibition after a
certain period of time (for example, five years). This option
would lock in a permanent ban on the activity virtually everyone
opposes (cloning-to-produce-children), while calling for continued
and enlarged debate on a question about which people currently
differ (cloning-for-biomedical-research).
The main benefits of a moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research
are that it would (1) allow time for research in related fields
to proceed and perhaps clarify the potentially unique benefits
of cloning-for-biomedical-research or discover superior alternatives
that would make cloning-for-biomedical-research unnecessary; (2)
allow time for a regulatory structure whether narrow or
broad in scope to be developed, if deemed desirable; and
(3) allow time for further debate and deliberation about the moral
questions, to determine if the prohibition on cloning-for-biomedical-research
should be renewed, made permanent, or abandoned after the moratorium
expires. Rightly understood, a moratorium should not be seen as
an attempt to stall, but as an opportunity to figure out the wisest
way to proceed. And for those interested in exploring and establishing
regulatory arrangements, a moratorium, as a de jure halt,
would provide prospective researchers with an incentive (otherwise
lacking) to recommend moral and legal guidelines before the moratorium
would expire and be up for possible renewal.
This option separates cloning-to-produce-children from cloning-for-biomedical-research.
It therefore would enable policymakers to take up the question
of cloning-for-biomedical-research in the larger context of the
embryo-research question, rather than in the narrower context
of human cloning.
This option captures much of the current public debate, in which
there is general agreement on the need to prohibit cloning for
producing children, but a great deal of uncertainty over the proper
approach to cloning-for-biomedical-research.
The arguments against this option are the same as those leveled
against Option 5 ("ban on both"), namely, that prohibiting cloning-for-biomedical-research,
even for a limited time, would cut off a promising avenue of medical
research and simply drive American talent overseas. Others may
object that the two uses of human cloning might hereafter be delinked,
a prospect that troubles some for both practical and moral reasons
(laid out in the discussion of the next option).
Policy Option 7: A moratorium, or temporary ban, on all
human cloning, whether to produce children or for biomedical research
("moratorium on both").
The final option is a temporary form of Option 5 ("ban on both"),
with a mandatory review of the policy after a certain period of
time (for example, five years).
The main benefits of this option are the same as those listed
above for Option 6 ("ban plus moratorium"). But this option has
what some consider the additional virtue of keeping the two uses
of cloning linked in the policy arena. This has, they say, two
major benefits.
First, on practical grounds, the policy on cloning-for-biomedical-research
will bear heavily on the feasibility and efficacy of any ban on
cloning-to-produce-children, and therefore there is an advantage
in ensuring that the two are considered together. Because the
availability of cloned embryos would make enforcement of the ban
on cloning-to-produce-children more complicated and demanding,
a ban on cloning-to-produce-children should never be de-coupled
from an identical ban on cloning-for-biomedical-research.
Second, on moral grounds, some argue that permitting
the creation of cloned human embryos for research crosses an important
line, and that one use of cloned embryos should not be separated
fully from the other in public consideration. They hold that human
cloning is a single thing, and therefore should be taken up whole.
They are concerned that, at the end of the moratorium outlined
in Option 6, the situation would be transformed into Option 2
("ban plus silence") or Option 3 ("ban plus regulation"), with
all the deficiencies that they think these permissive options
would hold. For this reason, these opponents argue, it is more
appropriate for both forms to be considered together at the end
of the moratorium period, even if the eventual resulting policy
does not treat them equally.
Once again, the arguments against this option are the same as
those leveled against Option 5 ("ban on both") or Option 6 ("ban
plus moratorium") that it would cut off, at least temporarily,
a promising avenue of medical research and drive American talent
overseas. In addition, some may object that linking the two uses
of cloning misrepresents the state of the public discussion on
the subject and places cloning-for-biomedical-research in the
wrong context causing it to be considered always as a form
of cloning, rather than as a form of embryo research.
Finally, some do not want to forgo the present opportunity to
enact a permanent ban on cloning-to-produce-children; failure
to do so now, they argue, would seem to imply that cloning-to-produce-children
may one day be perfectly acceptable.
* * *
Having sketched out what we consider to be the most plausible
options, we now proceed to offer our own policy recommendations
and our reasons for them.
ENDNOTES
- Presentation made by Dr. Patricia Baird, chair, Royal Commission
on New Reproductive Technologies, at the June 2002 meeting of
the President's Council. Transcript available at the Council's
web site, www.bioethics.gov. Back
to Text
- Clinton, W.J., "Memorandum on the Prohibition on Federal Funding
for Cloning of Human Beings, March 4, 1997" In Weekly Compilation
of Presidential Documents (Volume 33, Number 10), p. 281.
Washington, DC: Government Printing Office, 1997. Back
to Text
- Bush, G.W., "Remarks on Human Cloning Legislation, April 10,
2002" In Weekly Compilation of Presidential Documents
(Volume 38, Number 15), pp. 608-610. Washington, DC: Government
Printing Office, 2002. Back
to Text
_____________________
- As of June 2002, three states (Iowa, Michigan, and Virginia)
ban both cloning-to-produce-children and cloning-for-biomedical-research.
Two states (Louisiana and Rhode Island) ban cloning-to-produce-children,
but also have embryo-research laws that appear to prohibit cloning-for-biomedical-research.
One state (California) has banned cloning-to-produce-children
until December 31, 2002, but has no embryo-research law and
thus effectively permits cloning-for-biomedical-research. Back
to Text
- We prescind from trying to determine at length whether federal
legislation limiting human cloning would infringe on what some
believe is a fundamental constitutional right to attempt to
procreate. Nor will we try to offer our own legal opinion about
whether the Food and Drug Administration has existing authority
that would enable it to regulate either or both forms of human
cloning. These questions we are content to leave to others.
Instead we proceed here on the assumption that, whatever the
precise state of the law, Congress may (and we would argue,
should) take the lead in determining federal cloning policy.
Back
to Text
- The Food and Drug Administration (FDA) has stated that attempts
to clone humans would come under its jurisdiction. But this
assertion of regulatory authority has never been tested, and
might well be disputed if it were invoked in practice. The FDA
has never attempted to regulate the human uses of IVF embryos.
Back
to Text
- The FDA has never attempted to regulate the practice of IVF,
intracytoplasmic sperm injection, preimplantation genetic diagnosis,
or embryo research conducted with IVF-produced embryos. Back
to Text
Chapter Eight
Policy Recommendations
The Council's formation of its policy recommendations is shaped
by the following considerations:
First, our recognition of both the scientific and technological
and the human and ethical contexts of human cloning, considered
in Chapters One through Four.
Second, our awareness that human cloning is but a small
part of a large and growing field of biomedical science and technology
based on the convergence of developmental biology and genetics;
and our awareness that this field offers relief for human disease
and suffering while impinging also upon human procreation and
family life, regard for nascent human life, and the relations
between science and society.
Third, our ethical assessments of cloning-to-produce-children
and cloning-for-biomedical-research, as presented in Chapters
Five and Six.
Fourth, our ethical and prudential assessment of the
strengths and weaknesses, benefits and harms, of the various policy
options, as presented in Chapter
Seven, including a serious effort to judge in the face
of unavoidable ignorance about what the future may bring
what will likely be gained and what will likely be lost should
we pursue one path rather than another.
Fifth, our assessment of recent congressional efforts
to develop national legislation on human cloning, and the reasons
for their failures to date.
Sixth, our respect for the strongly held moral views
of those with whom we do not agree, both on the Council and in
the larger society.
Seventh, our desire to seek a wise and prudent course
of action that does justice to our deepest moral concerns while
preserving our nation's thriving biomedical science and technology.
I. The Council's Points of Departure in Formulating Policy Recommendations
(a) The Council regards the country's public policy decision
about human cloning as a matter of great moment. It is important
not only for its effect on the prospects of human cloning but
also for what it will say about our democratic society's ability
to govern the course of technological innovation and use in the
name of things we as a nation hold dear.
(b) The Council is unanimous in opposing cloning-to-produce-children.
We hold that the likely harms and injustices to prospective cloned
offspring and the women involved, as well as to their families
and the broader society, are sufficiently great and sufficiently
likely as to justify governmental action to prevent cloning-to-produce-children.
(c) Two general approaches have thus far been proposed by those
seeking to prevent cloning-to-produce-children. The first would
stop the process at the first step by banning the creation of
any cloned embryos. The second would stop the process at the initiation
of a pregnancy by banning the transfer of a cloned embryo into
a woman's uterus (or other gestational environment). If the question
of cloning-to-produce-children were considered in isolation, the
first and stricter ban would be most prudent: if it were illegal
to produce cloned embryos, they would be less likely to be created
and hence less likely to be available for attempts at pregnancy.
But such a comprehensive ban would preclude cloning-for-biomedical-research,
research favored by most scientists and patient advocacy groups,
but about which the public is deeply divided.
(d) Regarding the ethics of cloning-for-biomedical-research,
the Council is of many minds. Among Members who approve
the practice all of whom strongly endorse the worthiness
and importance of the research and its enormous potential for
medical therapies a few approve it unconditionally and with
enthusiasm, but more approve it with moral concern. Among the
latter are a few Members who, though approving it in principle,
are reluctant at this time to approve it in practice, for one
or more of the following prudential reasons: the current lack
of sufficient scientific evidence to sustain claims of the unique
value of cloned embryos for the desired researches; the
absence of proper regulatory institutions and mechanisms to enforce
regulations, held by these Members to be a prerequisite
for allowing the research to go forward; and an unwillingness
to alienate large numbers of our fellow citizens who oppose this
research on moral grounds.
Among Members who disapprove of cloning-for-biomedical-research,
most oppose it permanently because they think it is immoral to
create human embryos for purposes that are foreign to the embryos'
own well-being and that necessarily require their destruction.
Others oppose such cloning permanently because they hold that
society (and not only the embryos) will suffer irreversible moral
harm by crossing the boundary that allows nascent human life routinely
to be treated as a natural resource. Some Members oppose permitting
the practice because they fear that it will greatly increase the
likelihood that cloning-to-produce-children will occur or because
they think that a law banning only the transfer of a cloned embryo
into a woman's uterus would be unenforceable. Some Members oppose
the practice also because they think that the scientific case
for proceeding has not yet met the burden of showing why this
research is necessary and of sufficient importance to
justify crossing the moral barrier of creating nascent human life
for the purpose of experimentation.
(e) Were we to indicate where we stand on the ethical and prudential
assessments of the two forms of human cloning, each considered
independently, we would line up as follows:
|
Permit Now
(with Regulation)/u> |
Moratorium |
Ban |
To produce children |
0 |
0 |
17 |
For biomedical research |
7i |
3 |
7 |
Where we stand on the public policy options in
which both cloning-to-produce-children and cloning-for-biomedical-research
are necessarily considered together we shall indicate
below, in our recommendations.
(f) The Council notes that research on stem cells, both embryonic
and adult, is still in its very early stages. Work with both embryonic
and non-embryonic stem cells has led to some very promising results,2
and it is impossible to predict which avenues of research will
prove most successful in providing basic knowledge of disease
processes and tools for regenerative medicine. It is likely that
different diseases or research problems will require different
approaches. The Council also notes that the possible benefits
of cloning-for-biomedical-research are, at the present time, uncertain
and undemonstrated. There is little evidence from animal experimentation
to indicate, one way or the other, whether work with embryonic
stem cells derived from cloned embryos offers unique
benefits not otherwise available. Only further research can answer
these questions. These uncertainties about the future should cut
in two directions. They should temper claims of medical miracles
just around the corner, placing a high demand for cautious accumulation
of evidence. They should also temper assertions that biomedical
researchers can pursue their goals without using human embryos
because other approaches that are morally nonproblematic will
surely prove successful.
(g) The Council notes, with special emphasis, that proposals
to engage in cloning-for-biomedical-research necessarily endorse
the creation of (cloned) human embryos solely for the purpose
of such research. Public policy that specifically promoted
this research would thus explicitly and officially approve
crossing a moral boundary.3
(h) The Council also notes that, at the present time, human embryo
research proceeds unregulated in commercial biotechnology companies
and with local oversight in university based laboratories
(under the governance of institutional review boards [IRBs], whose
oversight is generally stringent). In addition, federally funded
research on human embryonic stem cell lines is now proceeding,
under guidelines established by the National Institutes of Health
pursuant to President Bush's decision of August 9, 2001. Any legislative
action on human cloning, including cloning-for-biomedical-research,
would not directly affect this other valuable research, including
all research on embryonic stem cells derived from IVF embryos.
In addition, a ban on cloning-for-biomedical-research would leave
undisturbed the freedom that scientists (in the private sector)
now have to create embryos solely for research by means of IVF,
a practice that lacks official sanction and that has drawn public
criticism but that is nonetheless legal (except in those few states
that have banned this practice).
(i) Finally, in viewing congressional efforts in 1998 and in
2001-2002 to enact a legislative ban on human cloning, the Council
notes the failure to enact a ban on cloning-to-produce-children-a
ban that nearly everyone supports because of irreconcilable
differences between the supporters of cloning-for-biomedical-research
and the opponents of any research that destroys (cloned) human
embryos. Failure to prohibit cloning-to-produce-children, especially
after protracted debate on the issue, amounts tacitly to public
willingness to allow this practice to remain legal. We are accordingly
interested in seeking a policy proposal that would, among other
things, overcome this impasse.
Below are the two alternative proposals to which Council Members
have given their support.
* * *
II. First Proposal
Ban on Cloning-to-Produce-Children, Moratorium on Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research
(Policy Option 6 of Chapter
Seven).
Call for a federal review of current and projected practices
of human embryo research, preimplantation genetic diagnosis, genetic
modification of human embryos and gametes, and related matters,
with a view to recommending and shaping ethically sound policies
for the entire field.
We recommend a congressionally enacted ban on all attempts at
cloning-to-produce-children and a four-year national moratorium
(a temporary ban) on human cloning-for-biomedical-research.4
These measures would apply everywhere in the United States and
would govern the conduct of all researchers, physicians, institutions,
or companies, whether or not they accept public funding. We also
recommend that, during this moratorium, the federal government
undertake a thoroughgoing review of present and projected practices
of human embryo research, preimplantation genetic diagnosis, genetic
modification of human embryos and gametes, and related matters,
with a view to proposing, before the moratorium expires, an ethically
acceptable public policy to govern these scientifically and medically
promising but morally challenging activities. Several reasons
converge to make this our recommended course of action at the
present time. Members of the Council who support this recommendation
do so for different reasons; some individual Members do not endorse
all the concurring arguments given below.
A. Strengths of the Proposal
1. Bans Cloning-to-Produce-Children
The strong ethical verdict against cloning-to-produce-children,
unanimous in this Council (and in Congress) and widely supported
by the American people, is hereby translated into clear and strong
legal proscription. The nation's moral conviction is expressed
with force of law through the people's representatives. To be
sure, such a ban (like any proscription) could be violated, but
it could not be violated with impunity. By reflecting the pervasive
moral judgment of the community, this ban would also serve as
a source of moral instruction and a sign that we can exercise
some control over the direction and use of biotechnology. Moreover,
were we at this time to settle for a mere moratorium on cloning-to-produce-children,
we might lose what may be our society's best chance to get a permanent
ban on this practice before it occurs and to declare our opposition
to the idea of designing and manufacturing our children. We would
lose this precious opportunity to demonstrate that we are able
to practice democratic self-rule regarding biotechnology and that
we can establish firm guidelines for the moral practice of science
and technology.
2. Provides a Highly Effective Means of Preventing Cloning-to-Produce-Children
The proposal's ban on all efforts to produce cloned children
is a primary goal. The moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research
(while desired by many for its own sake) would also provide an
additional safeguard against cloning-to-produce-children during
the next four years, beyond what would be available in a proposal
that banned only the implantation of cloned embryos but left cloning-for-biomedical-research
unregulated. By stopping all human cloning for four years, this
proposal would prevent the creation of cloned embryos, thus decreasing
the chances that anyone will be able to attempt to produce a cloned
child. The moratorium would also permit time to explore other
effective safeguards against this possibility that might be put
in place should the moratorium not be reenacted after four years.
3. Calls for and Provides Time for Further Democratic Deliberation
A true national discourse on cloning-for-biomedical-research
has not yet taken place. Certainly it has begun. But no consensus
has been reached, no clear majority has appeared, and only in
rare cases have the various parties to the debate acknowledged
(as we have attempted to do in this report) that their opponents
are also defending important and shared values. The matters at
stake are too significant to be settled now either by proceeding
with the research with minimal delay or by banning the research
outright when the nation is so divided and when the implications
of proceeding or not proceeding are as yet unclear. Under these
circumstances, the proper attitude is modesty, caution, and moderation,
expressed in a temporary ban to be revisited when time and democratic
argumentation have clarified the matter. By allowing the debate
and deliberation to continue, a moratorium would offer the following
specific benefits:
(a) Seeking consensus on crossing a major moral boundary.
To decide to create nascent human life expressly for the purpose
of experimentation and use is to cross a significant moral boundary.
It goes beyond permitting the use of extra embryos, created for
reproductive purposes, that are stored in IVF clinics and otherwise
destined for destruction. Yet the meaning and moral propriety
of crossing such a boundary are today hotly contested. Many people
believe that even the earliest stages of a new human life should
be protected against such use and destruction and would oppose
such a practice at any time. Many others favor permitting the
practice, but only under conditions of strict governmental regulation
that would guard against abuses and reflect measured respect for
the embryonic life that is being sacrificed. Our society needs
more time to explore the full moral significance of taking such
a step, to debate the moral and practical issues involved, and
to seek a national consensus about all research
on early human embryonic (and fetal) life (not just that formed
through cloning techniques).
(b) Gaining needed scientific evidence. The moratorium
on all human cloning will allow time for scientists to produce
hard evidence from cloning research in animals and animal disease
models evidence not available today. Such evidence, if available,
would support their present claims regarding the value of cloning-for-biomedical-research,
both for understanding normal and disease processes and for finding
new treatments. The moratorium will also provide time to see whether
cloning research will be indispensable for these goals or whether
there are equally fruitful but morally nonproblematic alternatives
to cloning, (such as, for example, work with adult stem cells
or multipotent adult progenitor cells or work that would solve
the transplant rejection problem for tissues derived from ordinary
embryonic stem cell lines).
(c) Promoting fuller and focused public debate, leading to
a better-informed decision. For people who believe that the
human embryo must not be violated, and who would therefore advocate
a permanent ban on cloning-for-biomedical-research, this moratorium
offers a partial step in what they deem to be the right direction,
and an opportunity to make further progress through moral persuasion
and political action. By preventing cloning-for-biomedical-research
for a while, this proposal takes seriously their warnings of possible
harms from allowing such research. But it also calls on them to
make those warnings more concrete and convincing, by arguing their
case in the proper context of embryo research in general and not
just that of cloning. Meanwhile, those who now do (or later might)
support cloning-for-biomedical-research would also find benefits
in this moratorium. It would allow them the opportunity to make
their full case and win over new supporters, to prepare the ground
properly (using new scientific evidence) for agreement on the
merits of research when the time to decide comes, and to devise
safeguards against likely abuse and misuse. The public decision
made after the moratorium expires would be better informed and
more fully considered as a result of such debate.
(d) Preserving a decent respect for the deep moral concerns
of our fellow citizens. A large number of Americans, perhaps
even a majority, hold that it is deeply immoral to create what
they regard as new human life for the purposes of experimental
research that involves the destruction of that life. We should
be very reluctant to ride roughshod over these views and to practice
contempt for our fellow citizens, especially for the sake of promised
benefits that are at this point highly uncertain and speculative,
and especially when the necessity of this approach to
the treatment of disease has not been demonstrated and when the
public debate has been so brief. A moratorium will enable us to
respect and assess these moral concerns while we look to science
to provide alternatives that do not require crossing this moral
boundary. Should the community decide, after the ongoing deliberation
made possible by the moratorium, to cross it, no group would have
grounds to complain that its views had been treated with contempt.
Also, we could have in the meantime established new boundaries
and devised effective regulations that could give genuine assurance
that additional and more problematic practices would be forestalled
or avoided altogether.
4. Provides Time and Incentive to Develop Adequate Regulation
Regarding Human Cloning
Because of the widespread concern to prevent cloning-to-produce-children,
those who support cloning-for-biomedical-research bear the burden
of devising and instituting adequate oversight and regulatory
mechanisms that would effectively reduce the risk that embryos
cloned for research might be used in efforts to produce cloned
children. In addition, regulatory guidelines and mechanisms, devised
and installed in advance, are called for regarding cloning-for-biomedical-research
itself. Because everyone has a stake in how nascent human life
is treated, serious efforts are necessary to protect the public
interest. Cloning-for-biomedical-research, if and when it
is to be allowed, must be preceded by the formulation of proper
rules and the institution of effective safeguards. Devising
effective regulatory instruments takes time, and a moratorium
could afford regulation proponents that time. Equally important,
in the absence of a moratorium, few proponents of the research
would have much incentive to help institute an effective regulatory
system. And a governmental policy simply to withhold federal
funding pending the development of a regulatory regimen would
have no effect on the conduct of this research in the private
sector. The following matters, at a minimum, would need to be
considered by any serious program of regulation:
(a) Comprehensive scope. Regulations that would cover
all cloning research, whether done with public or private funds,
whether done in universities, private research institutes, assisted
reproduction clinics, or biotech companies.
(b) Protections for egg donors. Regulations governing
the safety and consent of the oocyte donors, with safeguards against
improper inducements and exploitation of poor or otherwise vulnerable
women.
(c) Transparency and accountability. Regulations permitting
full public knowledge and scrutiny of what is being done with
cloned embryos produced for research purposes.5
(d) Equal access to benefits. Guidelines to promote
equal access to the medical benefits that flow from such research.
The very process of proposing such regulations would clarify
the moral and prudential judgments involved in deciding whether
and how to proceed with this research, as well as how cloning-for-biomedical
research relates to other areas of embryological, reproductive,
and genetic experimentation.
5. Calls for and Provides Time for a Comprehensive Review of
the Entire Domain of Related Biotechnologies
A moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research would enable
us to consider this activity in the larger context of research
and technology in the areas of developmental biology and genetics.
The practices of human embryo research and preimplantation genetic
diagnosis are largely unregulated by the federal government, or
regulated in a haphazard, uncoordinated way. These practices,
along with those of assisted reproduction, are largely unstudied:
we lack comprehensive knowledge about what is being done, with
what success, at what risk, under what ethical guidelines, respecting
which moral boundaries, subject to what oversight and regulation,
and with what sanctions for misconduct or abuse. If we are to
have wise public policy regarding these scientifically and medically
promising but morally challenging activities, we need careful
study and sustained public moral discourse on this general subject,
and not only on specific narrowly defined pieces of the field.
To achieve this goal, the moratorium here proposed should be accompanied
by a concerted review of the entire field, with the aim of establishing
permanent institutions to advise and shape federal policy in this
arena.
The President's Council on Bioethics stands ready to undertake
the preliminary steps of such a process and to provide advice
on further steps. As part of our ongoing inquiry, we intend to
continue to study various models of oversight and regulation of
biomedical research and technology, both professional and governmental,
that are used in the United States and abroad. As the necessary
efforts will likely lead beyond the authority, scope, and perhaps
also the duration of this advisory Council,6
we shall be especially interested in recommendations for devising
a more permanent national agency or institution, with broad oversight,
advisory, and decision-making authority,7
that could emerge before the expiration of the four-year moratorium
here proposed. Such a body could provide much-needed understanding
and national guidance on these vitally important subjects. Progress
toward creating such a body would ratify and perpetuate the deliberative
goals of the moratorium.
6. Provides Time to Garner Long-Term Respect and Support for
Biomedical Research and to Reaffirm the Social Contract between
Science and Society
A moratorium, rather than a lasting ban, signals a high regard
for the value of biomedical research and an enduring concern for
patients and families whose suffering such research may help alleviate.
By providing time to consider whether and how regulations might
govern research in this morally troubling area, the moratorium
invites the scientific, medical, and industrial communities into
the activities of devising boundaries that they themselves would
willingly respect. Such responsible behavior of biomedical researchers
would go a long way to protect them against a public backlash
should some less responsible scientists or technologists engage
in practices repugnant to community standards or should some of
their experiments result in great harm to some human subjects.
It would reaffirm the principle that science can progress while
upholding the community's moral norms. It would reassure researchers
that any public moral restrictions on their activities will be
rare, strictly limited, and carefully drawn. It would reassure
the community that there is to be no slippery slope toward significant
interference with the progress of beneficial biomedical research,
the treatment of human diseases, or the moral uses of biomedical
technologies. Friction between scientists and the wider community,
aggravated by precipitate decision, would be reduced. The community's
moral support for science and biomedical technology would be reaffirmed,
and, as a result, the long-term interests of patients, families,
and the entire society could be better served.
B. Some Specifics for the Legislation
Drafting the legislation that would give effect to this proposal
lies beyond the scope and competence of the Council. Yet the following
considerations would seem to be indispensable for a well-drafted
and effective statute.
1. Broad Coverage
The ban and moratorium should cover everyone, corporations as
well as individuals, private as well as public institutions.
2. Narrowly Drafted
The statute should be very narrowly drafted, making sure that
only the human cloning actions in question are proscribed, and
indicating explicitly other research and assisted-reproduction
practices that will not be in any way affected by the ban or moratorium.
3. Temporary
Regarding the moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research,
in the event that Congress takes no further action after four
years, the moratorium should lapse.
C. Conclusion
The proposal we recommend is, admittedly, a compromise, requiring
some give on both sides of the national debate if it is to be
enacted. But it is by no means merely a compromise. On the contrary,
it is perfectly warranted by the state of public opinion and justified
by the supreme value in our democracy of informed and deliberate
decision in matters of great moment. If enacted, it would establish
a permanent ban on cloning-to-produce-children, a practice that
the nation overwhelmingly opposes. And it would not prematurely
settle the equally important question of cloning-for-biomedical-research.
As already noted, this proposal accurately reflects the state
of the public discussion of human cloning. There is broad agreement
that cloning-to-produce-children should be banned, but there is
deep disagreement and uncertainty regarding whether and how to
proceed with cloning-for-biomedical-research. Such uncertainty
calls for more discussion, more data, and more time things
a moratorium would provide. In proposing the combination of a
ban on cloning-to-produce-children and a moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research,
we do not imply that we hold one form of cloning to be worse than
the other, but rather that the state of the public debate is such
that a clearly-agreed-upon course of action presents itself in
the one case, but more time and deliberation are called for in
the other. Even some of us who see merit in proceeding with cloning-for-biomedical-research
worry that cloning-for-biomedical-research may turn out to be
morally worse than cloning-to-produce-children, at least in magnitude,
especially should it lead to a routinized practice of embryo cultivation
and the growth of nascent human life for body parts. But given
the present state of the public discussion and the dearth of scientific
evidence, the Council has not reached consensus on how to formulate
a permanent policy on this matter at this moment, and the American
people are apparently divided on the subject.
The proposal we have offered is not just an acknowledgement of
the current lack of consensus. It is intended to advance the discussion
toward an informed decision by forcing both sides to argue for
their positions clearly and openly. A moratorium means that neither
side would be free to cling to the status quo and avoid presenting
its full case for public discussion.
On the one hand, the moratorium would permit and require the
research community to provide the public with more information
about the desirability and necessity of the research, and to indicate
how it can go forward within proper limits and respectful of communal
norms. It will also provide time and incentive for researchers
to seek out and invest in alternative technological approaches
that are morally nonproblematic. It may well be that when Congress
revisits the issue after the moratorium expires, the facts on
the ground may show no unique or compelling need for cloning-for-biomedical-research,
and morally nonproblematic alternatives may have been discovered.
Yet the ban on cloning-to-produce-children would remain in place
regardless of what happens on the research front.
On the other hand, the moratorium would permit and require the
community concerned about defending the inviolability of embryonic
human life to continue the moral argument in the hope of persuading
the broader society to desist. That argument, we point out, has
to be about embryo research in general, and not just about cloned
embryos in particular. With cloning-to-produce-children prohibited
and hence off the table, the debate could focus honestly and fully
on this central question.
We acknowledge the concerns raised by opponents of this proposal,
who worry that even a four-year moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research
cuts off urgently needed investigation, and that prominent scientists
may be tempted to leave the United States for countries without
such restrictions on cloning research. These are understandable
worries, but we believe they are misplaced and are not sufficient
to force an immediate decision on this subject.
First, the promise of this research is for now purely speculative,
and no significant evidence from animal research has presented
itself that might demonstrate that this (to many people) morally
disquieting or objectionable practice is in fact necessary
for the goals that researchers aim to serve, or that adult stem
cells cannot provide equally good models for studying inherited
diseases, or that other routes are not more effective in addressing
the transplant rejection problem.
Second, there is more to this matter than scientific and medical
progress. We ask proponents to recognize the moral hazards that
such research would be unleashing. Treating nascent human life
as a natural resource (or even, more respectfully, as a human
resource to which we ought to feel indebted) is morally troubling,
and there is a clear and present danger that it could lead us
down a path where our reverence for life may be imperiled. We
would therefore ask proponents of this research and the public-at-large
to keep these moral concerns in mind as we try to develop a sound
public policy for the whole area of embryo research. We think
that the moratorium provides needed time to do this right.
Finally, while it is possible that a few scientists will leave
the country if a moratorium is enacted, the vast majority will
not. We have examples at the state and national levels (for instance,
Michigan and Germany) where highly restrictive laws banning all
human cloning have been enacted yet where the biotechnology industry
is thriving. We have confidence that this robust field will continue
to grow, including the area of stem cell research from sources
other than cloned embryos (Indeed, several other countries, including
France, Italy, Norway, South Korea, and Canada, permit work on
embryonic stem cells but do not allow cloning-for-biomedical-research).
Moreover, succumbing to the threat that some researchers might
leave would not be a worthy way of making such a crucial moral
decision. A scientist, like any other citizen, may choose to leave
the United States for many different reasons. But there is no
reason to assume that good scientists will not be able to work
with and within the moral boundaries of the communities of which
they are members and whose blessings and support they enjoy.
We believe that a permanent ban on cloning-to-produce-children
coupled with a four-year moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research
would be the best way for our society to express its firm position
on the former, and to engage in a properly informed and open democratic
deliberation on the latter. Moreover, combined with a systematic
review at the federal level of the general field of embryo, reproductive,
and genetic research and technology, this proposal would enable
our society to think more comprehensively about how we should
deal not just with human cloning but also with other vitally important
areas of biotechnology. Ethical principles and boundaries need
to be established; regulatory mechanisms need to be considered
and devised; and ways must be found to give guidance to biomedical
researchers and technological innovators so that beneficial research
may proceed while upholding the moral and social norms of the
community. The decision before us is of great moment and importance.
Creating cloned embryos for any purpose requires crossing a major
moral boundary, with grave risks and likely harms, and once we
cross it there will be no turning back. Our society should take
the time to do it right and to make a judgment that is well-informed
and morally sound, respectful of strongly held views, and representative
of the priorities and principles of the American people. We believe
this proposal offers the best means of achieving these goals.
* * *
III. Second Proposal
Ban on Cloning-to-Produce-Children, with Regulation of the
Use of Cloned Embryos for Biomedical Research (Policy Option 3 of
Chapter Seven).
We recommend a congressionally enacted ban on all attempts
at cloning-to-produce-children while preserving the freedom of
cloning-for-biomedical-research. We recommend the establishment
of a system of oversight and regulation that would permit cloning-for-biomedical-research
to proceed promptly, but only under carefully prescribed limits.
These measures would apply everywhere in the United States and
would govern the conduct of all researchers, physicians, institutions,
or companies, whether or not they accept public funding. In addition,
we recommend that the federal government undertake a thoroughgoing
review of present and projected practices of human embryo research.
Several reasons converge to make this our recommended course of
action at the present time. Members of the Council who support
this recommendation do so for different reasons; some individual
Members do not endorse all the concurring arguments given below.
A. Strengths of the Proposal 1. Bans Cloning-to-Produce-Children
The strong ethical verdict against cloning-to-produce-children,
unanimous in this Council (and in Congress) and widely supported
by the American people, is hereby translated into clear and strong
legal proscription. The nation's moral conviction is expressed
with force of law through the people's representatives. To be
sure, such a ban (like any proscription) could be violated, but
it could not be violated with impunity. By reflecting the pervasive
moral judgment of the community, this ban would also serve as
a source of moral instruction and a sign that we can exercise
some control over the direction and use of biotechnology. Moreover,
were we at this time to settle for a mere moratorium on cloning-to-produce-children,
we might lose what may be our society's best chance to get a permanent
ban on this practice before it occurs and to declare our opposition
to the idea of designing and manufacturing our children. We would
lose this precious opportunity to demonstrate that we are able
to practice democratic self-rule regarding biotechnology and that
we can establish firm guidelines for the moral practice of science
and technology.8
2. Provides an Effective Means of Preventing Cloning-to-Produce-Children
Statutory prohibition on the transfer of a cloned human embryo
to a woman's uterus, backed by heavy penalties, would provide
a sufficient deterrent for anyone contemplating cloning-to-produce-children.
Cloned embryos created for research could, it is true, possibly
get into the hands of those who would attempt to use them to produce
cloned children. But the regulatory mechanisms and guidelines
governing cloning-for-biomedical-research, provided for by this
proposal (see below), will greatly minimize the likelihood of
such an occurrence. And anyone who attempted to clone a child
could not claim the credit for any successes without incurring
prosecution. Even if slightly less foolproof than a ban that also
blocked the creation of cloned embryos, this is a sufficiently
effective means for preventing cloning-to-produce-children.
3. Approves Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research and Permits It to
Proceed without Substantial Delay
Here is the major benefit to be obtained from this proposal (benefits
foreclosed by the First Proposal). This proposal would provide
clear congressional endorsement of the importance of proceeding
with cloning-for-biomedical-research. This potentially very valuable
research, promising for all the reasons enumerated in Chapter
Six, Part III ("The Moral Case for Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research")
could now go forward without substantial delay using human
cloned embryos and the stem cells and tissues derived therefrom.
Uncertainty about the potential of this research can only be overcome
by doing the research. It will be critically important to compare
directly the advantages and disadvantages of adult stem cells,
embryonic stem cells from IVF blastocysts, and embryonic stem
cells from cloned blastocysts side by side in the same laboratory.
Regardless of how much time we allow, no amount of experimentation
with animal models could provide the essential and urgently needed
understanding of human diseases. Moreover, the special
and possibly unique benefits of stem cell research using cloned
embryos (see Chapter
Six, Part III) cannot be obtained using embryos produced by
in vitro fertilization. The possible benefits to potentially millions
of patients are so great that we think they should be pursued
as soon as possible (under proper guidelines and regulations;
see next point). While not disturbing the current policy on embryo
research (which permits federal funding for research only on certain
designated stem cell lines), this proposal explicitly eschews
federal legal bans on new approaches to the revolutionary possibilities
of regenerative medicine.
4. Establishes Necessary Protections against Possible Misuses
and Abuses, Thus Paying the Respect Owed to Embryos Sacrificed in
the Research
Unlike those human cloning bills, recently considered by Congress,
that would permit cloning-for-biomedical-research, this proposal
takes seriously the special respect owed to nascent human life
as well as the moral hazards involved in this research, and it
proposes concrete steps to prevent or minimize them. While such
regulation will not satisfy those who believe that all such research
is morally wrong, it will give concrete expression to our view
that human embryos are never merely a natural resource,
and that the special respect owed to them as human resources
must be reflected in limits on what we may do with them. In addition,
such regulation may succeed in assuaging everyone's worst fears
about where this research might lead.9
Because of our concern to prevent cloning-to-produce-children,
we call for adequate oversight and regulatory mechanisms to effectively
reduce the risk that embryos cloned for research might be used
in efforts to produce cloned children. In addition, we welcome
regulatory guidelines and mechanisms, devised in advance, regarding
cloning-for-biomedical-research itself. We agree that everyone
has a stake in how nascent human life is treated, and that therefore
serious efforts are necessary to protect the public interest.
And although we want now to approve cloning-for-bio-medical-research,
we agree that it shall not go forward in the absence of appropriate
regulations and effective mechanisms for enforcing them.
Although this is not the place to draft legislation, the regulatory
mechanisms we favor would be based on the following principles:
(a) Prevent cloned embryos from being used to initiate pregnancies.
To do this, regulations must register, inventory, and track
the fate of individual cloned embryos; prohibit the shipping or
sale of cloned embryos (but not stem cells or other tissues or
products derived from these embryos).
(b) Provide enforceable ethical guidelines for the use of
cloned embryos for research. To do this, regulations must
license and conduct prior review of all research involving cloned
human embryos; set a definite time limit and developmental stage
beyond which a cloned human embryo may not be grown, either in
vitro or in vivo (we suggest fourteen days, or the formation of
the primitive streak); prohibit the transfer of a cloned human
embryo into the womb (or other gestational environment) of a human
being or an animal (or into an artificial equivalent of the same)
for research purposes; and provide strong penalties to deter unlicensed
or impermissible research.
(c) Protect the adult participants in this research.
To do this, regulations must establish clear regulations for the
protection of any human egg donors; set rules for financial compensation
for egg donation; and establish other relevant measures designed
to protect against the exploitation of women.
(d) Promote equal access to the medical benefits that flow
from this research. To do this, guidelines must be developed
that will keep down costs of medical therapies made available
through this research, which would have been explicitly sanctioned
by the community to serve the health needs of all.
5. Who Should Regulate This?
Whether done by an existing agency or a new one devised for this
purpose, the regulatory authority should include scientists, physicians,
and representatives of the biotechnology and pharmaceutical industries,
but also lawyers, ethicists, humanists, clergy, and members of
the public. In its composition and in its activities, every effort
should be made to avoid even the appearance of conflict of interest,
to prevent capture by special interests, and to ensure that the
public's moral concerns are fully addressed in the devising of
the regulations. A special Cloning Research Review Board, appointed
by the President, might be one way to ensure high visibility and
accountability.
6. Calls for a Comprehensive Review of the Entire Domain of
Embryo Research
The ethical and policy issues regarding cloning-for-biomedical-research
deserve to be considered in the context of all human embryo research.
Regulatory mechanisms for cloning-for-biomedical research should
be part of a larger regulatory program governing all research
involving human embryos. To achieve this goal, we recommend that
the federal government undertake a thorough-going review of present
and projected practices of human embryo research, with the aim
of establishing appropriate institutions to advise and shape federal
policy in this arena.
B. Some Specifics for the Legislation
Drafting the legislation that would give effect to this proposal
lies beyond the scope and competence of the Council. Yet the following
considerations would seem to be indispensable for a well-drafted
and effective statute.
1. Broad Coverage
The ban on cloning-to-produce-children, as well as the regulations
devised for cloning-for-bio-medical-research, should cover everyone,
corporations as well as individuals, private as well as public
institutions.
2. Narrowly Drafted
The statute should be very narrowly drafted, making sure that
only the human cloning actions in question are proscribed and
indicating explicitly other research and assisted-reproduction
practices that will not be in any way affected by the ban or regulations.
C. Conclusion
This recommendation is above all grounded in the importance of
not needlessly foreclosing or delaying a promising avenue of medical
research. Permitting cloning-for-biomedical-research now, while
governing it through a prudent and sensible regulatory regime,
is the most appropriate way to allow this important research to
proceed while ensuring that abuses are prevented. Combined with
a firm ban on the transfer of cloned embryos into a woman's uterus,
as we have recommended, such a policy would provide the balance
of freedom and protection, medical progress and respect for moral
standards, always sought in a free society. Most important, it
would leave open and endorse an important new avenue of research
that might help alleviate the suffering of millions of our fellow
citizens.
We respect and recognize the concerns of many in the public and
in this Council regarding cloning-for-biomedical-research, especially
about the need for further deliberation and the necessary safeguards
to prevent cloning-to-produce-children. But we do not believe
that our proposal forecloses continued deliberation. On the contrary,
the public process of designing a system to regulate cloning-for-biomedical-research
is likely to generate public discussion about the difficult ethical
issues posed by embryo research in general.
First, the ban we propose on cloning-to-produce-children would
be a strong deterrent against a practice that the nation overwhelmingly
opposes. By stopping, with the force of law, the transfer of cloned
embryos into a uterus, this ban would effectively prevent the
cloning of children. Like any law, the ban we propose could be
violated, but so too could a more comprehensive ban on all cloning
of embryos. Moreover, we believe that the sort of regulatory mechanisms
we have proposed here would provide sufficient protection against
the implantation of cloned embryos. Research scientists and fertility
specialists are not out to break the law or violate the moral
norms of their communities. They can in general be relied upon
to abide by the ban we have proposed, and those who violate it
can be penalized.
Second, we believe that the regulatory system we have proposed
would address those concerns specific to cloning-for-biomedical-research
itself. We do not discount these concerns. The moral seriousness
of working with nascent human life and the larger public concern
about where this research may lead make it imperative, even as
a matter of enlightened self-interest, for the research community
to welcome and participate in the regulation of this research.
Because the issues at stake are not just those of safety and efficacy,
but moral and social ones as well, the participation of other
citizens in these decisions is entirely appropriate. Cooperation
with the broader community in this matter of public moral concern
can only advance the relations between science and technology
and the broader society.
Third, we do not believe that cloning-for-biomedical-research
is the place to settle the more general question of research on
human embryos. That is why we have proposed that the federal government
review in a systematic way the general field of embryo research,
with an eye to devising a possible set of general policies or
institutions. In the meantime, it seems inappropriate to halt
promising embryo research in one arena (cloned embryos) while
it proceeds essentially unregulated in others. A sensible system
of regulation will allow this important research to continue safely,
while the nation considers a possible general policy on all embryo
research.
Last, in answer to the specific concern that our proposal may
put the government in the position of mandating the destruction
of human embryos, we point out that those who would be producing
the cloned embryos for research would have absolutely no intention
of keeping them alive beyond the limits needed for the research.
Hence there would be no occasion when governmental interference
might be called for to compel unwilling researchers to destroy
the cloned embryos. Strictly speaking, it would be the researchers,
not government officials, who would be responsible for the destruction
of the embryos; the government would not be requiring anything
that was not already implicit in the research activity itself.
True, the government, by enacting this legislation, would be accepting
the use of cloned embryos for research, but it would be doing
so fully mindful of the moral cost, for very good reason and under
strict guidelines.
We therefore believe that the legitimate concerns about human
cloning expressed throughout this report are sufficiently addressed
by a ban on cloning-to-produce-children and the regulation of
cloning-for-biomedical-research. And we believe that the nation
should affirm and support the responsible effort to find treatments
and cures that might help ameliorate or thwart diseases and disabilities
that shorten life, limit activity (often severely), and cause
great suffering for the afflicted and their families. Finding
a way to support such valuable research while preserving moral
standards is the challenge that confronts the federal government
and the American public in the matter of cloning. We believe our
approach offers the best means of achieving that goal.
* * *
IV. Recommendation
After extensive deliberation, Members of the Council have coalesced
around the two policy proposals, as follows:
The following ten Members of the Council form a majority in support
of the First Proposal: Rebecca S. Dresser, Francis Fukuyama, Robert
P. George, Mary Ann Glendon, Alfonso Gómez-Lobo, William B. Hurlbut,
Leon R. Kass, Charles Krauthammer, Paul McHugh, Gilbert C. Meilaender.
The following seven Members of the Council form a minority in
support of the Second Proposal: Elizabeth H. Blackburn, Daniel
W. Foster, Michael S. Gazzaniga, William F. May, Janet D. Rowley,
Michael J. Sandel, James Q. Wilson.
_____________________
- This group includes some Members who would make the permission
to proceed contingent upon the prior institution of
strict regulations and a mechanism for enforcing them, and some
Members who would allow the regulations to be developed as the
research proceeds. Back
to Text
- The embryonic stem cells in these studies were obtained from
non-cloned human embryos, produced by IVF. Back
to Text
- The National Bioethics Advisory Commission recommended that
federal agencies not fund research involving the derivation
or use of human embryonic stem cells from embryos made solely
for research purposes or using SCNT. (NBAC, Ethical
Issues in Human Stem Cell Research, Vol. I, 1999, Recommendations
3 and 4, pp. 71-72.) Back
to Text
- Operationally, the legislation could address separately the
two uses of cloning and define the prohibited acts as fol-lows.
Cloning I: the creation of a cloned human embryo by somatic
cell nuclear transfer. Cloning II: the creation of a cloned
human embryo, produced by somatic cell nuclear transfer, followed
by transfer into a woman's (or animal's) uterus or into an artificial
womb. It could then declare that: (1) Cloning I shall be unlawful
for four years from the date of the enactment of this legislation.
(2) Cloning II is hereby declared unlawful. Back
to Text
- Careful consideration should be given to the following matters:
licensing requirements to engage in such research; accurate
inventory and reporting of the numbers, uses, and fates of all
cloned embryos; decisions about whether to permit the buying
and selling of cloned human embryos; rules governing commerce
or traffic in cloned human em-bryos, should it be allowed; patent
law questions regarding cloned human embryos, blastocysts, and
later stages of cloned human organisms; age and stage of embryonic
development beyond which it would be impermissible to main-tain
and experiment upon cloned embryos; rules regarding the permissibility
of growing cloned human embryos in animal hosts or artificial
substitutes for a human or animal uterus; regulations concerning
cloned human-animal chi-meras (for example, human nuclei placed
in animal oocytes); guidelines specifying the kinds of experiments
that may be performed on the cloned embryos; guidelines regarding
production levels and storage of cloned embryos; and, finally,
effective institutional mechanisms-designed to prevent easy
capture by cloning researchers or biotech com-panies-for monitoring
cloning activities, enforcing the rules, and penalizing violators.
Back
to Text
- The President's Council on Bioethics is currently chartered
through November 2003. Back
to Text
- In thinking about this process we think it will be helpful
to consult the work of the Canadian Royal Commission on New
Reproductive Technologies. The process by which that Commission
arrived at its final conclusions, and its manner of presenting
those conclusions (carefully taking into account voluminous
public testimony and dissenting opinions) strike us as providing
an excellent model worthy of study and, to the extent appropriate,
emulation. The scope, principles, structure, and functions of
the proposed Assisted Human Reproduction Agency of Canada seem
to us worthy of special attention. Back
to Text
- On this point and some others to follow, this policy proposal
is identical to the First Proposal. To indicate this fact, the
earlier argument will sometimes be repeated in this Second Proposal
verbatim. We do so for symmetry and balance, and to allow each
proposal to be read as a self-contained unit, without relying
on the other. Back
to Text
- See Position Number One of "The Moral Case for Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research"
in Chapter Six
and the dis-cussion of Policy Option 3 in Chapter
Seven for the details of the moral hazards and how specific
regulations can deal with them. Back
to Text
Glossary of Terms
Asexual reproduction
Reproduction not initiated by the union of oocyte and sperm. Reproduction
in which all (or virtually all) the genetic material of an offspring
comes from a single progenitor.
Blastocyst
Name used for an organism at the blastocyst stage of development.
Blastocyst stage
An early stage in the development of embryos, when (in mammals)
the embryo is a spherical body comprising an inner cell mass that
will become the fetus surrounded by an outer ring of cells that
will become part of the placenta.
Cloned embryo
An embryo arising from the somatic cell nuclear transfer process
as contrasted with an embryo arising from the union of an egg
and sperm.
Cloning
- Cloning-to-produce-children-Production of a cloned
human embryo, formed for the (proximate) purpose of initiating
a pregnancy, with the (ultimate) goal of producing a child who
will be genetically virtually identical to a currently existing
or previously existing individual.
- Cloning-for-biomedical-research-Production of a cloned
human embryo, formed for the (proximate) purpose of using it
in research or for extracting its stem cells, with the (ultimate)
goals of gaining scientific knowledge of normal and abnormal
development and of developing cures for human diseases.
- Gene (molecular) cloning-Isolation and characterization
of DNA segments coding for proteins (genes) using carrier pieces
of DNA called vectors.
- Human cloning-The asexual reproduction of a new human
organism that is, at all stages of development, genetically
virtually identical to a currently existing, or previously existing,
human being.
Chromosomes
Structures inside the nucleus of a cell, made up of long pieces
of DNA coated with specialized cell proteins, that are duplicated
at each cell division. Chromosomes thus transmit the genes of
the organism from one generation to the next.
Cytoplasmic
Located inside the cell but not in the nucleus.
Diploid
Refers to the chromosome number in a cell, distinct for each species
(forty-six in human beings).
Diploid human cell
A cell having forty-six chromosomes.
Embryo
- The developing organism from the time of fertilization until
significant differentiation has occurred, when the organism
becomes known as a fetus.
- An organism in the early stages of development.
Enucleated egg
An egg cell whose nucleus has been removed or destroyed.
Epigenetic modification
The process of turning genes on and off during cell differentiation.
It may be accomplished by changes in (a) DNA methylation, (b)
the assembly of histone proteins into nucleosomes, and (c) remodeling
of chromosome-associated proteins such as linker histones.
Epigenetic reprogramming
The process of removing epigenetic modifications of chromosomal
DNA, so that genes whose expression was turned off during embryonic
development and cell differentiation become active again. In cloning,
epigenetic reprogramming of the donor cell chromosomal DNA is
used to reactivate the complex program of gene expression and
repression required for embryonic development.
Eugenics
An attempt to alter (with the aim of improving) the genetic constitution
of future generations.
Gamete
A reproductive cell (egg or sperm).
Haploid human cell
A cell such as an egg or sperm that contains only twenty-three
chromosomes.
Infertility
The inability to conceive a child through sexual intercourse.
In vitro fertilization (IVF)
The union of an egg and sperm, where the event takes place outside
the body and in an artificial environment (the literal meaning
of "in vitro" is "in glass"; for example, in a test tube).
Mitochondria
Small energy-producing organelles inside of cells. Mitochondria
give rise to other mitochondria by copying their small piece of
mitochondrial DNA and passing one copy of the DNA along to each
of the two resulting mitochondria.
Moral status
The standing of a being or entity in relation to other moral agents
or individuals. To have moral status is to be an entity toward
which human beings, as moral agents, have or can have moral obligations.
Multipotent cell
A cell that can produce several different types of differentiated
cells.
Nucleus
An organelle, present in almost all types of cells, which contains
the chromosomes.
Nuclear transfer
Transferring the nucleus with its chromosomal DNA from one (donor)
cell to another (recipient) cell. In cloning, the recipient is
a human egg cell and the donor cell can be any one of a number
of different adult tissue cells.
Oocyte
Egg.
Organism
Any living individual animal considered as a whole.
Parthenogenesis
A form of nonsexual reproduction in which eggs are subjected to
electrical shock or chemical treatment in order to initiate cell
division and embryonic development.
Pluripotent
A cell that can give rise to many different types of differentiated
cells.
Somatic cell (human)
A diploid cell containing forty-six chromosomes obtained or derived
from a living or deceased human body at any stage of development.
Somatic cell nuclear transfer (SCNT)
Transfer of the nucleus from a donor somatic cell into an enucleated
egg to produce a cloned embryo.
Stem cells
Stem cells are undifferentiated multipotent precursor cells that
are capable both of perpetuating themselves as stem cells and
of undergoing differentiation into one or more specialized types
of cells.
Totipotent
A cell with an unlimited developmental potential, such as the
zygote and the cells of the very early embryo, each of which is
capable of giving rise to (1) a complete adult organism and all
of its tissues and organs, as well as (2) the fetal portion of
the placenta.
Zygote
The diploid cell that results from the fertilization of an egg
cell by a sperm cell.
Bibliography
Appleyard, B. Brave New Worlds: Staying Human in the Genetic
Future. New York: Viking, 1998.
Bahn, S., et al. "Neuronal target genes of the neuron-restrictive
silencer factor in neurospheres derived from fetuses with Down's
syndrome: A gene expression study." The Lancet, 359:
310-315, 2002.
Baird, P., chair, Royal Commission on New Reproductive Technologies.
Presentation at the June 2002 meeting of the President's Council
on Bioethics, Washington, D.C. Transcript available on the Council's
web site at www.bioethics.gov.
Belmont Report. The National Commission for the Protection of
Human Subjects of Biomedical and Behavioral Research. The
Belmont Report: Ethical Principles and Guidelines for the Protection
of Human Subjects of Research. Bethesda, MD: Government Printing
Office, 1978.
Briggs, R., and T.J. King. "Transplantation of living nuclei
from blastula cells into enucleated frog's eggs." Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences (USA), 38: 455-463, 1952.
Brown, D. "Human Clone's Birth Predicted; Delivery Outside U.S.
May Come By 2003, Researcher Says." The Washington Post,
16 May 2002, A8.
Bush, G.W. "Remarks on Human Cloning Legislation." Weekly
Compilation of Presidential Documents, 38, no. 15: 608-610,
10 April 2002.
Chesne, P., et al. "Cloned rabbits produced by nuclear transfer
from adult somatic cells." Nature Biotechnology, 20:
366-369, 2002.
Cibelli, J.B., et al. "Somatic cell nuclear transfer in humans:
Pronuclear and early embryonic development." e-biomed: The
Journal of Regenerative Medicine, 2: 25-31, 2001.
Cibelli, J.B., et al. "The health profile of cloned animals."
Nature Biotechnology, 20:13-14, 2002a.
Cibelli, J.B., et al. "Parthenogenetic stem cells in nonhuman
primates." Science, 295: 819, 2002b.
Clinton, W.J. "Memorandum on the Prohibition on Federal Funding
for Cloning of Human Beings." Weekly Compilation of Presidential
Documents, 33, no. 10: 281, 4 March 1997.
Code of Federal Regulations (CFR) Title 45, Part 46.111(a)(2).
Fletcher, J. The Ethics of Genetic Control: Ending Reproductive
Roulette. New York: Anchor Books, 1974.
Fukuyama, F. Our Posthuman Future: Consequences of the Biotechnology
Revolution. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2002.
Gaylin, W. "The Frankenstein Myth Becomes a Reality-We Have the
Awful Knowledge to Make Exact Copies of Human Beings." New
York Times Magazine, 5 March 1972.
Gurdon, J.B. "The developmental capacity of nuclei taken from
intestinal epithelium cells of feeding tadpoles." Journal
of Embryology and Experimental Morphology, 10: 622-640, 1962.
Hagell, P., and P. Brundin. "Cell survival and clinical outcome
following intrastriatal transplantation in Parkinson's disease."
Journal of Neuropathology and Experimental Neurology,
60: 741-752, 2001.
Hall, C.T. "UCSF Admits Human Clone Research; Work to Duplicate
Embryos for Medical Purposes on Hold." San Francisco Chronicle,
25 May 2002, A1.
Hansen, M., et al. "The Risk of Major Birth Defects after Intracytoplasmic
Sperm Injection and In Vitro Fertilization." New England Journal
of Medicine, 346: 725-730, 2002.
Helsinki Declaration. 18th World Medical Association General
Assembly. Ethical Principles for Medical Research Involving
Human Subjects. Helsinki, 1964 (amended 1975, 1983, 1989,
1996, 2000).
Hemingway, E. The Old Man and the Sea. New York: Simon
& Schuster, 1996.
Hill, J.R. "Placental defects in nuclear transfer (cloned) animals."
Paper presented at Workshop: Scientific and Medical Aspects
of Human Cloning, National Academy of Sciences, Washington,
D.C., 7 August 2001.
Hill J.R., et al. "Clinical and pathologic features of cloned
transgenic calves and fetuses (13 case studies)." Theriogenology,
8: 1451-1465, 1999.
Huxley, A. Brave New World. New York: Harper Perennial,
1998.
Jaenisch, R., and I. Wilmut. "Don't clone humans!" Science,
291: 5513, 2001.
Jiang, Y., et al. "Pluripotency of mesenchymal stem cells derived
from adult marrow." Nature, 418: 41-49, 2002.
Jonas, H. "Philosophical Reflections on Experimenting With Human
Subjects." In Readings on Ethical and Social Issues in Biomedicine,
edited by Richard W. Wertz. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall,
1973.
Kass, L. "Making Babies-The New Biology and the 'Old' Morality."
The Public Interest, No. 26: 18-56, Winter 1972.
Kass, L. "The Wisdom of Repugnance." The New Republic,
2 June 1997, 17-26.
Kass, L. "Preventing a Brave New World: Why We Should Ban Human
Cloning Now." The New Republic, 21 May 2001, 30-39.
Kass, L. "The Meaning of Life-in the Laboratory." The Public
Interest, No. 146: 45-46, Winter 2002.
Kim, J.-H., et al. "Dopamine neurons derived from embryonic stem
cells function in an animal model of Parkinson's disease." Nature,
418: 50-56, 2002.
Kluger, J. "Here Kitty Kitty!" Time, 159(8), 25 February
2002 (issued online February 17, 2002).
Kolata, G. Clone: The Road to Dolly and the Path Ahead. New York:
Morrow and Company, 1998.
Kolata, G. "In Cloning, Failure Far Exceeds Success." New
York Times, 11 December 2001, D1.
Kristol, W., and E. Cohen. The Future Is Now. Lanham,
MD: Rowman and Littlefield, 2002.
Lanza, R.P., et al. "Human therapeutic cloning." Nature Medicine,
5: 975-977, 1999.
Lanza, R.P., et al. "Cloned cattle can be healthy and normal."
Science, 294: 1893-1894, 2001.
Lanza, R.P., et al. "Generation of histocompatible tissues using
nuclear transplantation." Nature Biotechnology, 2: 689-696,
2002.
Lederberg, J. "Experimental Genetics and Human Evolution." The
American Naturalist, 100: 519-536, September-October 1966.
Leggett, K., and A. Regalado. "China Stem Cell Research Surges
as Western Nations Ponder Ethics." Wall Street Journal,
6 March 2002, A1.
Macklin, R. Testimony before the National Bioethics Advisory
Commission, March 14, 1997. Transcript available at www.georgetown.edu/research/nrcbl/nbac/.
National Academy of Sciences (NAS). Scientific and Medical
Aspects of Human Reproductive Cloning. Washington, D.C.:
National Academy Press, 2002.
National Bioethics Advisory Commission (NBAC). Cloning Human
Beings. Bethesda, MD: Government Printing Office, 1997.
National Bioethics Advisory Commission (NBAC). Ethical Issues
in Human Stem Cell Research. Bethesda, MD: Government Printing
Office, 1999.
National Institutes of Health (NIH). Ad Hoc Group of Consultants
to the Advisory Committee to the Director (Human Embryo Research
Panel). Report. Bethesda, MD: Government Printing Office,
1994.
National Research Council/Institute of Medicine (NRC/IOM). Stem
Cells and the Future of Regenerative Medicine. Washington,
D.C.: National Academy Press, 2001.
Nuremberg Report. Trials of War Criminals before the Nuremberg
Military Tribunals under Control Council Law No. 10. Vol.
2, pp. 181-182. Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Office,
1949.
Nussbaum, M., and C.R. Sunstein. Clones and Clones: Facts
and Fantasies about Human Cloning. New York: Norton, 1998.
Ogonuki, N., et al. "Early death of mice cloned from somatic
cells." Nature Genetics, 30: 253-254, 2002.
Osler, W. "Chauvinism in Medicine." In Aequanimitas, with
Other Addresses to Medical Students, Nurses and Practitioners
of Medicine. Philadelphia: Blakiston, 1943.
Outka, G. "The Ethics of Human Stem Cell Research." Paper presented
at the April 2002 meeting of the President's Council on Bioethics,
posted at the Council's web site at www.bioethics.gov. A slightly
revised version of this article appears in the Kennedy Institute
of Ethics Journal, 12, No. 2: 175-213, 2002.
President's Commission for the Study of Ethical Problems in Medicine
and Biomedical and Behavioral Research. Splicing Life: A Report
on the Social and Ethical Issues of Genetic Engineering with Human
Beings. Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Office, 1982.
Ramsey, P. Fabricated Man: The Ethics of Genetic Control.
New Haven: Yale University Press, 1970.
Regalado, A. "Only Nine Lives for Kitty? Not if She Is Cloned."
Wall Street Journal, 14 February 2002, B1.
Reyes, M., et al. "Origin of endothelial progenitors in human
postnatal bone marrow." Journal of Clinical Investigation,
109: 337-346, 2002.
Rideout III, W.M., et al. "Nuclear cloning and epigenetic reprogramming
of the genome." Science, 293: 1093-1098, 2001.
Rideout III, W.M., et al. "Correction of a genetic defect by
nuclear transplantation and combined cell and gene therapy." Cell,
109: 17-27, 2002.
Rimington, M., E. Simons, and K. Ahuja. "Counseling patients
undergoing ovarian stimulation about the risks of ovarian hyper-stimulation
syndrome," Human Reproduction, 14: 2921-2922, 1999.
Robertson, J.A. "A Ban on Cloning and Cloning Research Is Unjustified."
Testimony before the National Bioethics Advisory Commission, 14
March 1997.
Rorvik, D. In His Image: The Cloning of a Man. New York:
J.B. Lippincott, 1978.
Rougier, N., and Z. Werb. "Minireview: Parthenogenesis in mammals."
Molecular Reproduction and Development, 59: 468-474,
2001.
Saad, L. "Cloning Humans Is a Turn-Off to Most Americans." Gallup
Poll Analyses, 16 May 2002.
Shamblott, M.J., et al. "Derivation of pluripotent stem cells
from cultured human primordial germ cells." Proceedings of
the National Academy of Science (USA), 95: 13726-13731, 1998.
Shin, T., et al. "A cat cloned by nuclear transplantation." Nature,
415: 859, 2002.
Spemann, H. Embryonic Development and Induction. New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1938.
Stent, G. "Molecular biology and metaphysics" Nature,
248: 779-781, 1974.
Supreme Court of the United States. Eisenstadt v. Baird,
405 U.S. 438, 1972.
Thomson, J.A., et al. "Embryonic stem cell lines derived from
human blastocysts." Science, 282: 1145-1147, 1998.
Tribe, L. "On Not Banning Cloning for the Wrong Reasons." In
M. Nussbaum and C.R. Sunstein, Clones and Clones: Facts and
Fantasies about Human Cloning. New York: Norton, 1998.
Vogelstein, B., et al. "Please don't call it cloning!" Science,
295: 1237, 2002.
Wakayama, T., et al. "Cloning of mice to six generations." Nature,
407: 318-319, 2000.
Wakeley, K., and E. Grendys. "Reproductive technologies and risk
of ovarian cancer." Current Opinion in Obstetrics and Gynecology,
12: 43-47, 2000.
Watson, J. "Moving Toward the Clonal Man." The Atlantic Monthly,
May 1971.
Watson, J. Testimony before the Committee on Science and Astronautics,
U. S. House of Representatives, Ninety-Second Congress, January
26, 27, and 28, 1971.
Weiss, R. "Human Cloning Bid Stirs Experts' Anger; Problems in
Animal Cases Noted." The Washington Post, 11 April 2001,
A1.
Weiss, R. "Stem Cell Transplant Works in Calif. Case, Parkinson's
Traits Largely Disappear." The Washington Post, 9 April
2002, A8.
Wilmut, I. "Application of animal cloning data to human cloning."
Paper presented at Workshop: Scientific and Medical Aspects
of Human Cloning, National Academy of Sciences, Washington,
D.C., 7 August 2001.
Wilmut, I. et al. "Viable offspring derived from fetal and adult
mammalian cells." Nature, 385: 810-813, 1997.
Wilson, J.Q. "On Abortion." Commentary, 97, No. 1: 21ff,
1994.
Appendix
Personal Statements
The eight chapters, plus Bibliography
and Glossary
of Terms, constitute the official body of this report. Though it
contains expressed differences of opinion, especially in Chapters
Six and Eight,
it stands as the work of the entire Council. In the interest of
contributing further to public discussion of the issues, and of
enabling individual Members of the Council to speak in their own
voice on one or another aspect of this report, we offer in this
Appendix personal statements from those Members who have elected
to submit them:
Elizabeth
H. Blackburn, Ph.D., D.Sc.
Rebecca
S. Dresser, J.D., M.S.
Daniel
W. Foster, M.D.
Michael
S. Gazzaniga, Ph.D.
Robert
P. George, D.Phil., J.D. (joined by Alfonso Gómez-Lobo,
Ph.D.).
William
B. Hurlbut, M.D.
Charles
Krauthammer, M.D.
Paul McHugh,
M.D.
William F.
May, Ph.D.
Gilbert
C. Meilaender, Ph.D.
Janet
D. Rowley, M.D., D.Sc.
Michael
J. Sandel, D.Phil.
James
Q. Wilson, Ph.D.
* * *
Statement of Professor Blackburn
Why a Moratorium on Cloning-for-Biomedical- Research Is Not
the Way to Proceed
There are several reasons why a moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research
(SCNT) is not a logical or productive direction in which to proceed.
The goal of a moratorium is to wait until something happens,
then make a decision. For a moratorium on SCNT (cloning-for-biomedical-research),
waiting would have several consequences that I do not believe
reflect the spirit of much of the Council's opinion.
First, during any such proposed moratorium, patients will continue
to have currently incurable diseases for which there is
now no hope of alleviation and many will continue to die
of them. Second, a moratorium is used to gain more information.
It may sound tempting to impose a moratorium to get more information,
since, despite very promising results, it is true, at this early
stage of the research, that we still know only a little. But that
information can only be gained by performing the same research
that the moratorium proposes to halt.
It has been proposed that other kinds of research will provide
such answers. One cannot find out the answers about oranges by
doing all the research on apples. Some kinds of research on apples
will be useful, because it will provide information about generalities
that apply to fruit in general. But diseases are very specific,
and humans are very specific. They share overarching features
with other animals, but the very nature of disease is to be particular.
Thus, diabetes research does not apply to Parkinson's research.
Furthermore, it has been proposed that the needed information
can be gained from research in animal models. However, it is of
crucial importance to be aware that human diseases are different,
in certain specific ways, from their counterpart models in animals.
This is the case just as the course of development in a mouse
has overarching similarities to, yet at the same time startling
and highly specific differences from, the course of development
of a human. Hence, animal models, while invaluable up to a point,
cannot provide the needed information for understanding and treating
a human disease.
Currently, there are excess in vitro fertilization embryos, and
it has been proposed that biomedical research on these, if allowed
by their parents and those responsible for them, would be adequate
for obtaining the types of information that could be gained from
research that involves SCNT. But first, these excess embryos represent
only a limited set of genetic backgrounds. They do not represent
the wide diversity of genetic and ethnic groups that will be needed
if the fruits of this research are to be available to all. Second,
the limited set of available excess IVF embryos would not, of
course, represent the very genotypes of perhaps greatest interest:
those representing the diseases that are the rightful subject
of research involving SCNT. A final point concerns why these embryos
are in excess. It is not only to attempt to ensure success of
IVF, but also, in current IVF practice, these excess embryos are
more often the ones that were judged by the IVF clinic professionals
as appearing less likely to develop well which is why they
were not chosen for implantation in the first place. If they have
a higher chance of abnormality, this is not the group of embryos
that is ideal for obtaining the best, most relevant information
about development and disease.
SCNT-derived stem cells could provide other crucial information,
in a way impossible for excess in-vitro-fertilized-embryo-derived
stem cells. Researchers could address, in a clear and experimentally
controlled way, a key unknown issue about the therapeutic value
of stem cell use for regenerative medicine: the immune rejection
issue. There are excellent in vitro investigations that could
cast a lot of much needed light on this area, and could be done
only with cells derived from the same genetic background
i.e., using stem cells from SCNT. Again, this cannot be done with
animal models alone, which have been the only source of information
on this topic to date, because we know that animal models are
not complete models for many particular biological questions in
humans.
In sum, reliance on excess IVF embryos would severely hobble
efforts to gain the information that is needed to be able to judge
the promise of cloning-for-biomedical-research. Further, the use
of IVF embryos in no way facilitates the most immediately promising
areas of SCNT research, which involve not tissue transplantation
but rather the development of laboratory tissue that has been
grown from somatic cells with known genetic mutations that are
needed for study and for testing of new pharmaceutical interventions.
Hence, a moratorium, imposed in order to wait for more information
that will give us a better informed set of facts from which to
proceed, is logically flawed.
The President's Council on Bioethics currently is proposing two
possible policy recommendations. Both would ban cloning-to-produce-children.
One proposal is to proceed with cloning-for-biomedical-research
(SCNT) with appropriate regulations; the other is to put it under
a four-year moratorium. I support the former proposal.
Some have called for a moratorium pending development of elaborate
regulatory innovations, such as the creation of a new government
body to oversee all this research. Unfortunately, such regulations
might well never emerge, allowing opponents of research to accomplish
by administrative delay what they have been unable to accomplish
through legislation, that is, a de facto ban on SCNT research.
Furthermore, these proposals ignore the extensive regulation already
in place.
Based on the Council's public deliberations, over half of the
Council do not have ethical problems with cloning-for-biomedical-research
based simply on the status of the embryo. The proposal of a moratorium
on SCNT, and not its outright ban, by the President's Council
on Bioethics certainly implies that the Council deems this research
to be important for medical science. A moratorium can only be
counterproductive to the good that can come out of this research.
Rather, the thoughtful application of current regulations to all
SCNT research and consideration of independent efforts to regulate
the market in human gametes will allow this research to proceed
with its risks minimized and its benefits maximized for all.
ELIZABETH H. BLACKBURN
* * *
Statement of Professor Dresser
Below are my reasons for agreeing with the First Proposal.
I. Cloning to Have a Child
The ethical question presented today is not, "if cloning to
have a child were safe, should it then be permitted?" Instead,
the question is whether societies should allow scientists and
physicians to conduct research aimed at producing babies through
cloning. Posing the question this way highlights the research
ethics issues raised by this form of cloning.
A central ethical issue is whether studies of cloning to have
a child would present a balance of risks (to women, fetuses, children,
and society) and expected benefits (to the child, prospective
parents, and society) that justifies proceeding with human trials.
The National Academy of Sciences (NAS) report Scientific and
Medical Aspects of Human Reproductive Cloning observes that
high numbers of human eggs would be required for this research.
Women serving as research subjects would be exposed to the risks
presented by fertility drugs and egg retrieval procedures. Women
would also be exposed to risks associated with gestating a cloned
fetus. As the NAS report notes, animals pregnant with cloned fetuses
have had miscarriages and other health complications. If prenatal
tests revealed problems in the fetus, women would face decisions
about pregnancy termination. At least initially, human studies
would expose children to the risk of disability and premature
death. Parents and society could face burdens associated with
caring for disabled children. Even if further cloning work in
other species leads to better outcomes, good outcomes would not
be assured in humans.
Added to these risks are the broader ethical concerns raised
by cloning to have a child, such as psychological harm and objectification
of children. Admittedly, many children today are born into environments
that expose them to serious physical, social, and psychic harms.
Prenatal and preimplantation screening allow parents to exercise
deliberate control over children=s genetic makeup. Confused and
difficult family relations can arise in "natural" family settings
and as a result of currently practiced assisted reproduction methods.
Certain social practices may allow and encourage parents to regard
children as projects or products.
What is different about cloning is the array of risks and worries
it presents, together with the relatively little that would be
gained by developing the procedure. Although there are a few cases
in which cloning to have a child might be morally acceptable,
there are not enough of those cases to justify exposing research
subjects and others to the harms that could accompany human testing.
Research on cloning to have children would also consume resources
that might otherwise be devoted to more worthwhile projects. The
limited resources available to support biomedical research should
go to studies relevant to serious human health problems. Responsible
companies and scientists ought to devote their efforts to research
on important health problems, rather than on cloning to have children.
II. Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research
Several U.S. court opinions and advisory panel reports assign
an intermediate moral status to the human embryo. According to
these statements, embryos should be treated with special respect
not the respect we give to fully developed humans, but more
respect than we give to items of property. One difficulty with
the intermediate status position is that there is little clarity
or agreement on what it means to treat human embryos with special
respect.
Special respect might mean that embryos ought not be created
purely for use as a research tool or a therapy to help others.
Creating embryos for these purposes would represent a significant
step beyond allowing the research use of donated IVF embryos that
would otherwise be destroyed. Creating embryos for research would
require women to provide eggs for research use. It is possible
that payment would be necessary to attract a sufficient number
of egg providers (this would depend on the number of eggs
needed and the number of women willing to donate for altruistic
reasons). In this context, women would be helping to produce a
research tool, rather than helping infertile people to have children.
Some people believe that creation of cloned and other embryos
for research would be consistent with the special respect view.
In 1994, a majority of the National Institutes of Health Human
Embryo Research Panel said that creating embryos for research
"for the most serious and compelling reasons" would be permissible.
Former President Clinton disagreed with this judgment, however.
And because panel Members themselves were concerned about the
risks associated with egg donation, they recommended that eggs
for research embryos be obtained solely from women already undergoing
IVF for infertility treatment, women undergoing gynecological
surgery for other reasons, and deceased women based on their previous
consent or the consent of their next-of-kin. The deliberations
in 1994 concerned acceptable conditions for government funding
of human embryo research, but I do not think the participants
meant to suggest that privately funded research should be evaluated
according to wholly different moral considerations.
Because there are legitimate moral concerns raised by the practice
of creating human embryos for research, I believe it would be
premature to endorse cloning-for-biomedical-research. To approve
cloning is to approve the creation of embryos as research tools.
Past advisory groups and others have expressed sufficient reservations
about this step to warrant more extensive national deliberation
about whether it is justified at all and, if so, under what conditions.
I find it hard to reconcile the special respect view with a policy
that allows embryos to be created purely as a research tool. I
also recognize that some individuals assign a higher moral status
to the early embryo. I do not want to endorse a practice that
many people believe is wrong in the absence of compelling reasons
to do so. At the same time, I can imagine studies that would offer
sufficient benefit to patients to justify the creation of embryos
for research through cloning or other methods.
For me, an important consideration is whether there are or will
be in the near future alternative methods of investigating the
relevant scientific questions. With regard to potential stem cell
therapies, the question is whether cloning will be necessary to
avoid the immune rejection problem. The NAS report Stem Cells
and the Future of Regenerative Medicine repeatedly states
that additional research in many areas is needed to determine
whether embryonic stem cells can provide effective therapies to
patients. A period of research focused on stem cells from donated
embryos remaining after infertility treatment and on the immune
rejection problem in animals could help to clarify whether it
is necessary to move to research on stem cells from cloned human
embryos. As for other types of research that might be conducted
with stem cells from cloned human embryos, I believe scientists
need to explain in more detail the significance of the research
questions and the reasons why they cannot be investigated using
alternative methods.
The appropriate oversight system is another matter meriting further
analysis. In my view, proposals to create research embryos should
be evaluated by a group that includes scientific experts, members
of other professions, and ordinary citizens. The review group
should include individuals with different positions on the moral
status of early embryos. Approval should occur only after a rigorous
and thorough analysis of individual proposals. The review group
should require strong evidence that a proposal will generate information
both relevant to a serious human health problem and not available
through alternative research approaches.
I also believe that the temptation will be strong to extend the
time limits for permissible human embryo and fetal research. Events
in the past demonstrate that the desire to advance knowledge can
lead to immoral research practices. Because there is likely to
be pressure to allow destructive research on developing humans
past the point at which stem cells can be retrieved, our nation
should establish a strong moral and policy basis for drawing the
line at a particular point in development.
In sum, I believe that a four-year moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research
is justified for a variety of reasons. A moratorium gives scientists
time to gather data and develop a stronger account of why it is
necessary to obtain stem cells from cloned embryos. A moratorium
allows Members of this Council and others to consider embryo cloning
in its broader ethical and policy context and to deliberate about
appropriate oversight structures for cloning and related practices.
I hope that the moratorium also gives members of the public an
opportunity to learn more about the actual state of stem cell
research. This is truly a promising area, but it is far from certain
that all or even some of its projected therapeutic benefits will
materialize.
Finally, I hope that future public and policy discussions will
confront the challenge of providing patients with access to any
stem cell therapies that may be developed. Millions of patients
in the United States lack access to established health care that
could improve and extend their lives. People in developing countries
lack access to the most basic medical assistance. Because helping
patients is the ethical justification for conducting stem cell
and other forms of biomedical research, improved access to existing
and future therapies must be part of the national discussion.
Rebecca S. Dresser
* * *
Statement of Dr. Foster
For Proposal Two
I begin by saying that the deliberations of the Council have
been from the beginning serious, open and collegial. Although
strong differences exist amongst some members, these have been
expressed in scholarly and dignified fashion, without anger or
personal attacks.
I support Proposal 2. The core issues in the discussion have
been two. The first is "the nature of the embryo" argument. Some
supporting Proposal 1 feel strongly that from the moment of conception,
or the moment of cloning, the germ of potential life is so powerful
as to render the nascent embryo deserving of protection equal
to that of a full human. Others believe that respect for the embryo,
though it is not yet fully human, requires a moratorium to see
if alternatives might render cloning unnecessary. There is no
doubt that a five or six day embryo is potentially human, but
it cannot become a human by itself as would occur in normal human
conception. The one or two hundred cell organism, the blastocyst,
is neither viable nor feeling; there are no organs and there is
no brain. There is nothing it can do without external help and
implantation. From the standpoint of science it is potentially
human but biologically pre-human. The evidence for this conclusion
seems unarguable to me.
Proponents of Proposal 1, although they may agree with the biological
facts, focus on "what might be" for the embryo. If implanted,
some of the blastocysts from any source might become fully human,
a child. However, in natural conception many embryos, perhaps
half or more, are deleted in the first trimester. I calculated,
using the World Health Organization 2001 estimate of about 360,000
births in the world each day, and assuming 50 percent implantation
possibility, that more than 130 million embryos are lost naturally
each year. Thus what any embryo might become is far from certain.
Obviously the philosophical/moral argument of absolute or near
absolute sanctity of any embryo cannot be answered by the scientific/biological
argument. But I hold to the latter.
The "slippery slope" argument has been extensively discussed
and fundamentally devolves to the fear or belief that lessons
learned in cloning for research and therapy would make cloning-to-produce-children
easier or more likely to occur. That is a legitimate fear, hence
the desire by all of us for a ban on cloning-to-produce-children
and the demand for regulation of all cloning.
I believe that biomedical science is a powerful good in the universe.
The achievements in the prevention and cure of human disease and
suffering over the past half century have been remarkable. What
we know about nature grows daily. Stem cell research has great
potential to take us further. Is it certain that dramatic health
benefits will follow? Of course not. Science is a discipline of
uncertainty. That is why in my view we should begin the research.
I believe we have to compare the stem cells side by side: adult
stem cells versus IVF stem cells versus cloned stem cells. Then
we will know whether the potential is real and what the advantages
or disadvantages of each cell type might be. Supporters of Proposal
1 also believe that research is necessary and argue that the moratorium
will allow research on adult and IVF stem cells. But it eliminates
a critical element, the direct comparison by controlled experiments
for all three types of potentially therapeutic cells.
I said above that science is a discipline of uncertainty that
requires experiments to answer questions of truth. It is also
a discipline of hope. I believe that Proposal 2 is a very good
thing for all those who suffer from disease. It is a decision
for hope. It is for this reason that I support it.
Daniel W. Foster
* * *
Statement of Dr. Gazzaniga
Oscar Wilde's lament, "A man who moralizes is usually a hypocrite,"
is a fairly rough statement. While I don't fully subscribe to
it, I do believe that it cuts to the heart of much of the problematic
nature of moralization: the divide that can exist between reasoning
as reflected in actions in the face of a collection of facts and
reasoning grounded on little more than a cultural belief system.
Of course, we are all free to have our views on everything from
baseball to embryos. This is a large part of what makes this country
great. But moralizers often go much further. Frequently, they
want you to conform to their views, an agenda that I find entirely
disturbing, and particularly troubling, when cast in the large,
as a basis for social and even scientific policy.
My personal view on these matters is driven by forty years of
scientific study on how the brain enables mind, which gives me
a particular professional perspective on how our species forms
and maintains its belief systems. This, for better or worse, is
the lens through which I see these deliberations.
I disagree with most of the moral reasoning argued in this report.
For me it is full of unsubstantiated psychological speculations
on the nature of sexual life and theories of moral agency. In
what follows, I state my position on the issue of both cloning-to-produce-children
and cloning-for-biomedical-research in the form of a short essay.
I try to capture my own passion for what is at stake.
Let Science Roll Forward
It was a bright and wintry January day when President Bush convened
his advisory panel on bioethics in the Roosevelt Room of the White
House. I was excited to be there and our charge was, and is, to
see, explicate, and finally advise him how to respond to the flood
of ethical complexities unearthed by the torrent of new biomedical
technology. The President implored us to engage in that age-old
technique of intellectual dueling that is debate. I was confident
that a sensible and sensitive policy might evolve from what was
sure to be a cacophony of voices of scientists and philosophers,
representing a spectrum of opinions, beliefs, and intellectual
backgrounds.
It was thus a surprise to me to hear the President's April speech
on cloning. His opinions appeared fully formed, even though our
panel had yet to finalize a report and still awaited a vote on
the singularly crucial point of so-called cloning-for-biomedical-research.
While it is true that the President's position is one held by
some of the Members of the panel, it is not unanimous, and the
panel's charge, the public nature of our panel's debate, and our
national political process leave me wanting to make public my
own personal view at this time.
Most people are aware that we no longer see cloning in a simple
one-process-fits-all framework. At the very least there are two
flavors. Cloning-to-produce-children is that process by which
a new human being might be grown from the genetic material of
a single individual. At this point in our history, no one supports
cloning-to-produce-children. It is, by consensus, dangerous, probably
not even attainable for years, and simply an odd concept. Even
if cloning-to-produce-children did succeed in the future, the
idea of informing one's spouse, "Let's go with my genes, not yours,"
is bizarre and socially a nonstarter.
In juxtaposition to cloning-to-produce-children is cloning-for-biomedical-research.
This is another matter entirely. Cloning-for-biomedical-research
is carried out with a completely different set of intentions from
cloning-to-produce children. Cloning-for-biomedical-research is
a bit of a misnomer, but it is the term the panel wants to use
instead of "therapeutic cloning," for it is meant to cover not
only cloning for therapeutics (for such diseases as diabetes,
Parkinson's disease, and so on) but also that cloning now deemed
necessary for understanding all genetic disorders. This is cloning
for the sole purpose of enabling various types of lifesaving biomedical
research. Perhaps the Council should have called it "lifesaving
cloning."
Intentions aside, it is worth recalling the mechanics of cloning-for-biomedical-research.
Scientists prefer to call this somatic cell nuclear transfer for
a simple reason. That is all it is. Any cell from an adult can
be placed in an egg whose own nucleus has been removed and given
a jolt of electricity. This all takes place in a lab dish, and
the hope is that this transfer will allow the adult cell to be
reprogrammed so that it will form a clump of approximately 150
cells called a blastocyst. That clump of cells will then be harvested
for the stem cells the clump contains, and medical science will
move forward.
The general public gets confused around this point in a discussion.
The confusions come from a conflation of ideas, beliefs, and facts.
At the core seems to be the idea, asserted by some religious groups
and some ethicists, that this moment of transfer of cellular material
is an initiation of life, and so is the moment when a moral equivalency
is established between a developing group of cells and a human
being. They believe this is true for a normally sexually produced
embryo and now so too for this new activated cell. This is the
point of view that led to the President's view that both cloning-to-produce-children
and cloning-for-biomedical-research should be outlawed. But in
light of modern biological knowledge, is the view that life and
moral agency start at the same time reasonable and true? Some
think not.
First, consider embryos. We now know that as many as 50 to 80
percent of all fertilized eggs spontaneously abort. Those fertilized
eggs are simply expelled from the body. It is hard to believe
that under any religious belief system people would grieve and/or
hold funerals for these natural events. Yet, if these unfortunate
zygotes are considered human beings, then logically they should.
Second, the process of a single zygote splitting to make identical
twins can occur at least until fourteen days after fertilization.
Thus, how could we possibly identify a person with a single fertilized
egg? Additionally, even divided embryos can recombine back into
one. The happy result would be a person who has emerged from two
distinct fertilized eggs but is otherwise just like you and me.
The "person = zygote" theory would have to say that he is two
people! Finally, with respect to activated cells, there is no
real claim when it all starts because it is not known in any detail.
Because the fertilization process is now understood, it serves
as the modern scientific basis for the British position, which
does not grant moral status to an embryo until after fourteen
days, the time when all the twinning issues cease and the point
where it must be implanted into the uterus if development is to
continue. Thus, in Britain, embryo research goes on up to the
blastocyst stage only and now, most recently, attempts at cloning
to the blastocyst stage will be permitted.
The laboratory-devised blastocyst to be used for cloning-for-biomedical-research,
the biological clump of cells at issue here, is the size of the
dot on this "i." It has no nervous system and is therefore not
sentient in any way and has no trajectory to becoming a human
unless it is re-implanted into a women's uterus. And yet it likely
carries the gold for the cure of millions of people. My brother
is a general surgeon. He has saved hundreds of lives because he
was able to transplant hearts and livers and kidneys and lungs
to others from clinically brain-dead patients. The next of kin
gave their loved one's tissue to help others, a practice which
is condoned by all of society, including Catholics. It seems only
right that those adults not needing leftover IVF embryos or eggs,
neither of which have a brain at all, should have the same right
to will them for use in biomedical research. The no-brained blastocyst
that can develop from these tissue gifts, from both IVF and biomedical
cloning technologies, is ready to help the suffering of brain
alive children and adults.
The President asked us to debate on our opening day. He said,
"That's what I want. You haven't heard a debate until you have
heard Colin Powell and Don Rumsfeld go at it." He lets these two
trusted aides have it out, and I think he made a courageous and
wise decision to send in the troops to have at the terrorists
who would destroy innocent women and children. Disease does the
same. I only hope he hears the debate, and then I hope he decides
to send in the stem cells to root out disease. In the spirit of
these times, I too say, "Let's roll."
Michael S. Gazzaniga
* * *
Statement of Professor George
(Joined by Dr. Gómez-Lobo)
The subject matter of the present report is human cloning, the
production of a human embryo by means of somatic cell nuclear
transfer (SCNT) or similar technologies. Just as fertilization,
if successful, generates a human embryo, cloning produces the
same result by combining what is normally combined and activated
in fertilization, that is, the full genetic code plus the ovular
cytoplasm. Fertilization produces a new and complete, though immature,
human organism. The same is true of successful cloning. Cloned
embryos therefore ought to be treated as having the same moral
status as other human embryos.
A human embryo is a whole living member of the species homo sapiens
in the earliest stage of his or her natural development. Unless
denied a suitable environment, an embryonic human being will by
directing its own integral organic functioning develop himself
or herself to the next more mature developmental stage, i.e.,
the fetal stage. The embryonic, fetal, infant, child, and adolescent
stages are stages in the development of a determinate and enduring
entity a human being who comes into existence as a
single cell organism and develops, if all goes well, into adulthood
many years later.i
Human embryos possess the epigenetic primordia for self-directed
growth into adulthood, with their determinateness and identity
fully intact. The adult human being that is now you or me is the
same human being who, at an earlier stage of his or her life,
was an adolescent, and before that a child, an infant, a fetus,
and an embryo. Even in the embryonic stage, you and I were undeniably
whole, living members of the species homo sapiens. We were then,
as we are now, distinct and complete (though in the beginning
we were, of course, immature) human organisms; we were not mere
parts of other organisms.
Consider the case of ordinary sexual reproduction. Plainly, the
gametes whose union brings into existence the embryo are not whole
or distinct organisms. They are functionally (and not merely genetically)
identifiable as parts of the male or female (potential)
parents. Each has only half the genetic material needed to guide
the development of an immature human being toward full maturity.
They are destined either to combine with an oocyte or spermatozoon
to generate a new and distinct organism, or simply die. Even when
fertilization occurs, they do not survive; rather, their genetic
material enters into the composition of a new organism.
But none of this is true of the human embryo, from the zygote
and blastula stages onward. The combining of the chromosomes of
the spermatozoon and of the oocyte generates what every authority
in human embryology identifies as a new and distinct organism.
Whether produced by fertilization or by SCNT or some other cloning
technique, the human embryo possesses all of the genetic material
needed to inform and organize its growth. Unless deprived of a
suitable environment or prevented by accident or disease, the
embryo is actively developing itself to full maturity. The direction
of its growth is not extrinsically determined, but is
in accord with the genetic information within it.ii
The human embryo is, then, a whole
(though immature) and distinct human organism a human being.
If the embryo were not a complete organism, then what could it
be? Unlike the spermatozoa and the oocytes, it is not a part of
the mother or of the father. Nor is it a disordered growth such
as a hydatidiform mole or teratoma. (Such entities lack the internal
resources to actively develop themselves to the next more mature
stage of the life of a human being.) Perhaps someone will say
that the early embryo is an intermediate form, something that
regularly emerges into a whole (though immature) human organism
but is not one yet. But what could cause the emergence of the
whole human organism, and cause it with regularity? It is clear
that from the zygote stage forward, the major development of this
organism is controlled and directed from within, that
is, by the organism itself. So, after the embryo comes into being,
no event or series of events occur that could be construed as
the production of a new organism; that is, nothing extrinsic to
the developing organism itself acts on it to produce a new character
or new direction in development.
But does this mean that the human embryo is a human being deserving
of full moral respect such that it may not legitimately be used
as a mere means to benefit others?
To deny that embryonic human beings deserve full respect, one
must suppose that not every whole living human being is deserving
of full respect. To do that, one must hold that those human beings
who deserve full respect deserve it not in virtue of the kind
of entity they are, but, rather, in virtue of some acquired
characteristic that some human beings (or human beings at some
stages) have and others do not, and which some human beings have
in greater degree than others.iii
We submit that this position is untenable. It is clear that one
need not be actually conscious, reasoning, deliberating,
making choices, etc., in order to be a human being who deserves
full moral respect, for it is clear that people who are asleep
or in reversible comas deserve such respect. So, if one denied
that human beings are intrinsically valuable in virtue of what
they are, but required an additional attribute, the additional
attribute would have to be a capacity of some sort, and, obviously
a capacity for certain mental functions. Of course, human beings
in the embryonic, fetal, and early infant stages lack immediately
exercisable capacities for mental functions characteristically
carried out (though intermittently) by most (not all consider
cases of severely retarded children and adults and comatose persons)
human beings at later stages of maturity. Still, they possess
in radical (= root) form these very capacities. Precisely by virtue
of the kind of entity they are, they are from the beginning
actively developing themselves to the stages at which these capacities
will (if all goes well) be immediately exercisable. In this critical
respect, they are quite unlike cats and dogs even adult
members of those species. As humans, they are members of a natural
kind the human species whose embryonic, fetal, and
infant members, if not prevented by some extrinsic cause, develop
in due course and by intrinsic self-direction the immediately
exercisable capacity for characteristically human mental functions.
Each new human being comes into existence possessing the internal
resources to develop immediately exercisable characteristically
human mental capacities and only the adverse effects on
them of other causes will prevent their full development.
In this sense, even human beings in the embryonic, fetal, and
infant stages have the basic natural capacity for characteristically
human mental functions.
We can, therefore, distinguish two senses of the "capacity" (or
what is sometimes referred to as the "potentiality") for mental
functions: an immediately exercisable one, and a basic natural
capacity, which develops over time. On what basis can one require
for the recognition of full moral respect the first sort of capacity,
which is an attribute that human beings acquire (if at all) only
in the course of development (and may lose before dying), and
that some will have in greater degree than others, and not the
second, which is possessed by human beings as such? We can think
of no good reason or nonarbitrary justification.
By contrast, there are good reasons to hold that the second type
of capacity is the ground for full moral respect.
First, someone entertaining the view that one deserves full moral
respect only if one has immediately exercisable capacities for
mental functions should realize that the developing human being
does not reach a level of maturity at which he or she performs
a type of mental act that other animals do not perform even
animals such as dogs and cats until at least several months
after birth. A six-week-old baby lacks the immediately exercisable
capacity to perform characteristically human mental functions.
So, if full moral respect were due only to those who possess immediately
exercisable capacities for characteristically human mental functions,
it would follow that six-week-old infants do not deserve full
moral respect. If one further takes the position that beings (including
human beings) deserving less than full moral respect may legitimately
be dismembered for the sake of research to benefit those who are
thought to deserve full moral respect, then one is logically committed
to the view that, subject to parental approval, the body parts
of human infants, as well as those of human embryos and fetuses,
should be fair game for scientific experimentation.
Second, the difference between these two types of capacity is
merely a difference between stages along a continuum. The proximate,
or immediately exercisable, capacity for mental functions is only
the development of an underlying potentiality that the human being
possesses simply by virtue of the kind of entity it is. The capacities
for reasoning, deliberating, and making choices are gradually
developed, or brought toward maturation, through gestation, childhood,
adolescence, and so on. But the difference between a being that
deserves full moral respect and a being that does not (and can
therefore legitimately be dismembered as a means of benefiting
others) cannot consist only in the fact that, while both have
some feature, one has more of it than the other. A mere quantitative
difference (having more or less of the same feature, such as the
development of a basic natural capacity) cannot by itself be a
justificatory basis for treating different entities in radically
different ways. Between the ovum and the approaching thousands
of sperm, on the one hand, and the embryonic human being, on the
other hand, there is a clear difference in kind. But
between the embryonic human being and that same human being at
any later stage of its maturation, there is only a difference
in degree.
Third, being a whole human organism (whether immature or not)
is an either/or matter a thing either is or is not a whole
human being. But the acquired qualities that could be proposed
as criteria for personhood come in varying and continuous degrees:
there is an infinite number of degrees of the relevant developed
abilities or dispositions, such as for self-consciousness, intelligence,
or rationality. So, if human beings were worthy of full moral
respect only because of such qualities, and not in virtue of the
kind of being they are, then, since such qualities come in varying
degrees, no account could be given of why basic rights are not
possessed by human beings in varying degrees. The proposition
that all human beings are created equal would be relegated to
the status of a superstition. For example, if developed self-consciousness
bestowed rights, then, since some people are more self-conscious
than others (that is, have developed that capacity to a greater
extent than others), some people would be greater in dignity than
others, and the rights of the superiors would trump those of the
inferiors where the interests of the superiors could be advanced
at the cost of the inferiors. This conclusion would follow no
matter which of the acquired qualities generally proposed as qualifying
some human beings (or human beings at some stages) for full respect
were selected. Clearly, developed self-consciousness, or desires,
or so on, are arbitrarily selected degrees of development of capacities
that all human beings possess in (at least) radical form from
the coming into being of the organism until his or her death.
So, it cannot be the case that some human beings and
not others are intrinsically valuable, by virtue of a certain
degree of development. Rather, human beings are intrinsically
valuable in virtue of what (i.e., the kind of being) they
are; and all human beings not just some, and
certainly not just those who have advanced sufficiently along
the developmental path as to be able to exercise their capacities
for characteristically human mental functions are intrinsically
valuable.
Since human beings are intrinsically valuable and deserving of
full moral respect in virtue of what they are, it follows that
they are intrinsically valuable from the point at which they come
into being. Even in the embryonic stage of our lives, each of
us was a human being and, as such, worthy of concern and protection.
Embryonic human beings, whether brought into existence by union
of gametes, SCNT, or other cloning technologies, should be accorded
the status of inviolability recognized for human beings in other
developmental stages.
Three arguments have been repeatedly advanced in the course of
our Council's deliberations in an effort to cast doubt on the
proposition that human embryos deserve to be accorded such status.
(1) Some have claimed that the phenomenon of monozygotic twinning
shows that the embryo in the first several days of its gestation
is not a human individual. The suggestion is that as long as twinning
can occur, what exists is not yet a unitary human being but only
a mass of cells each cell is totipotent and allegedly independent
of the others.
It is true that if a cell or group of cells is detached from
the whole at an early stage of embryonic development, then
what is detached can sometimes become a distinct organism and
has the potential to develop to maturity as distinct from the
embryo from which it was detached (this is the meaning of "totipotent").
But this does nothing to show that before detachment the cells
within the human embryo constituted only an incidental mass. Consider
the parallel case of division of a flatworm. Parts of a flatworm
have the potential to become a whole flatworm when isolated from
the present whole of which they are part. Yet no one would suggest
that prior to the division of a flatworm to produce two whole
flatworms the original flatworm was not a unitary individual.
Likewise, at the early stages of human embryonic development,
before specialization by the cells has progressed very far, the
cells or groups of cells can become whole organisms if they are
divided and have an appropriate environment after the division.
But that fact does not in the least indicate that prior to such
an extrinsic division the embryo is other than a unitary, self-integrating,
actively developing human organism. It certainly does not show
that the embryo is a mere clump of cells.
In the first two weeks, the cells of the developing embryonic
human being already manifest a degree of specialization or differentiation.
From the very beginning, even at the two-cell stage, the cells
differ in the cytoplasm received from the original ovum. Also
they are differentiated by their position within the embryo. In
mammals, even in the unfertilized ovum, there is already an "animal"
pole (from which the nervous system and eyes develop)iv
and a "vegetal" pole (from which the future "lower" organs and
the gut develop). After the initial cleavage, the cell coming
from the "animal" pole is probably the primordium of the nervous
system and the other senses, and the cell coming from the "vegetal"
pole is probably the primordium of the digestive system. Moreover,
the relative position of a cell from the very beginning (that
is, from the first cleavage) has an impact on its functioning.
Monozygotic twinning usually occurs at the blastocyst stage, in
which there clearly is a differentiation of the inner cell mass
and the trophoblast that surrounds it (from which the placenta
develops).v
The orientation and timing of the cleavages are species specific,
and are therefore genetically determined, that is, determined
from within. Even at the two-cell stage, the embryo begins synthesizing
a glycoprotein called "E-cadherin" or "uvomorulin," which will
be instrumental in the compaction process at the eight-cell stage,
the process in which the blastomeres (individual cells of the
embryo at the blastocyst stage) join tightly together, flattening
and developing an inside-outside polarity.vi
And there is still more evidence, but
the point is that from the zygote stage forward, the embryo, as
well as maintaining homeostasis, is internally integrating various
processes to direct them in an overall growth pattern toward maturity.vii
But the clearest evidence that the embryo in the first two weeks
is not a mere mass of cells but is a unitary organism is this:
if the individual cells within the embryo before twinning
were each independent of the others, there would be no reason
why each would not regularly develop on its own. Instead, these
allegedly independent, noncommunicating cells regularly function
together to develop into a single, more mature member of the human
species. This fact shows that interaction is taking place
between the cells from the very beginning (even within the zona
pellucida, before implantation), restraining them from individually
developing as whole organisms and directing each of them to function
as a relevant part of a single, whole organism continuous with
the zygote. Thus, prior to an extrinsic division of the cells
of the embryo, these cells together do constitute a single organism.
So, the fact of twinning does not show that the embryo is a mere
incidental mass of cells. Rather, the evidence clearly indicates
that the human embryo, from the zygote stage forward, is a unitary,
human organism.
(2) The second argument we wish to address suggests that since
people frequently do not grieve, or do not grieve intensely, for
the loss of an embryo early in pregnancy, as they do for the loss
of a fetus late in pregnancy or of a newborn, we are warranted
in concluding that the early embryo is not a human being worthy
of full moral respect.
The absence of grieving is sometimes a result of ignorance about
the facts of embryogenesis and intrauterine human development.
If people are told (as they still are in some places) that there
simply is no human being until "quickening" a view which
is preposterous in light of the embryological facts then
they are likely not to grieve (or not to grieve intensely) at
an early miscarriage. But people who are better informed, and
women in particular, very often do grieve even when a
miscarriage occurs early in pregnancy.
Granted, some people informed about many of the embryological
facts are nevertheless indifferent to early miscarriages; but
this is often due to a reductionist view according to which embryonic
human beings are misdescribed as mere "clumps of cells," "masses
of tissue," etc. The emotional attitude one has toward
early miscarriages is typically and for the most part an effect
of what one thinks rightly or wrongly about the humanity
of the embryo. Hence it is circular reasoning to use the indifference
of people who deny (wrongly, in our view) that human beings in
the embryonic stage deserve full moral respect as an argument
for not according such respect.
Moreover, the fact that people typically grieve less in the case
of a miscarriage than they do in the case of an infant's death
is partly explained by the simple facts that they do not actually
see the baby, hold her in their arms, talk to her, and so on.
The process of emotional bonding is typically completed after
the child is born sometimes, and in some cultures, months
after the child is born. However, a child's right not to be killed
plainly does not depend on whether her parents or anyone else
has formed an emotional bond with her. Every year perhaps
every day people die for whom others do not grieve. This
does not mean that they lacked the status of human beings who
were worthy of full moral respect.
It is simply a mistake to conclude from the fact that people
do not grieve, or grieve less, at early miscarriage that the embryo
has in herself less dignity or worth than older human beings.
(3) We now turn to the third argument. Some people, apparently,
are moved to believe that embryonic human beings are not worthy
of full moral respect because a high percentage of embryos formed
in natural pregnancies fail to implant or spontaneously abort.
Again, we submit that the inference is fallacious.
It is worth noting first, as the standard embryology texts point
out, that many of these unsuccessful pregnancies are really due
to incomplete fertilizations. So, in many cases, what is lost
is not actually a human embryo. To be a complete human organism
(a human being), the entity must have the epigenetic primordia
for a functioning brain and nervous system, though a chromosomal
defect might only prevent development to maximum functioning (in
which case it would be a human being, though handicapped). If
fertilization is not complete, then what is developing is not
an organism with the active capacity to develop itself to the
mature (even if handicapped) state of a human.
Second, the argument here rests upon a variant of the naturalistic
fallacy. It supposes that what happens in "nature," i.e., with
predictable frequency without the intervention of human agency,
must be morally acceptable when deliberately caused. Since embryonic
death in early miscarriages happens with predictable frequency
without the intervention of human agency, the argument goes, we
are warranted in concluding that the deliberate destruction of
human beings in the embryonic stage is morally acceptable.
The unsoundness of such reasoning can easily be brought into
focus by considering the fact that historically, and in some places
even today, the infant mortality rate has been very high.
If the reasoning under review here were sound, it would show that
human infants in such circumstances could not be full human beings
possessing a basic right not to be killed for the benefit of others.
But that of course is surely wrong. The argument is a non
sequitur.
In conclusion, we submit that law and public policy should proceed
on the basis of full moral respect for human beings irrespective
of age, size, stage of development, or condition of dependency.
Justice requires no less. In the context of the debate over cloning,
it requires, in our opinion, a ban on the production of embryos,
whether by SCNT or other processes, for research that harms them
or results in their destruction. Embryonic human beings, no less
than human beings at other developmental stages, should be treated
as subjects of moral respect and human rights, not as objects
that may be damaged or destroyed for the benefit of others. We
also hold that cloning-to-produce-children ought to be legally
prohibited. In our view, such cloning, even if it could be done
without the risk of defects or deformities, treats the child-to-be
as a product of manufacture, and is therefore inconsistent with
a due respect for the dignity of human beings. Still, it is our
considered judgment that cloning-for-biomedical-research, inasmuch
as it involves the deliberate destruction of embryos, is morally
worse than cloning-to-produce-children. Thus we urge that any
ban on cloning-to-produce-children be a prohibition on the practice
of cloning itself, and not on the implantation of embryos. Public
policy should protect embryonic human beings and certainly not
mandate or encourage their destruction. An effective ban on cloning-to-produce-children
would be a ban on all cloning.viii
Although an optimal policy would permanently ban all cloning,
we join in this Council's call for a permanent ban on cloning-to-produce-children
combined with a four-year ban (or "moratorium") on cloning-for-biomedical-research
for the reasons set forth by Gilbert Meilaender in his personal
statement. It is our particular hope that a four-year period will
provide time for a careful and thorough public debate about the
moral status of the human embryo. This is a debate we welcome.
* * *
ROBERT P. GEORGE
ALFONSO GÓMEZ-LOBO
____________________
- A human embryo (like a human being in the fetal, infant, child,
or adolescent stage) is not properly classified as a "prehuman"
organism with the mere potential to become a human being. No
human embryologist or textbook in human embryology known to
us presents, accepts, or remotely contemplates such a view.
The testimony of all leading embryology textbooks is that a
human embryo is already and not merely potentially
a human being. His or her potential, assuming a sufficient measure
of good health and a suitable environment, is to develop by
an internally directed process of growth through the further
stages of maturity on the continuum that is his or her life.Back
to Text
- The timing of the first two cleavages seems to be controlled
by the maternal RNA within the embryo rather than by its new
DNA (see Ronan O'Rahilly and Fabiola Mueller, Human Embryology
and Teratology (New York: John Wiley & Sons, 1992), 23).
Still, these cleavages do not occur if the embryo's nucleus
is not present, and so the nuclear genes also control these
early changes. Back
to Text
- A possible alternative, though one finding little support
in current discussions, would be to argue that what I am, or
you are, is not a human organism at all, but rather a nonbodily
consciousness or spirit merely inhabiting or somehow "associated
with" a body. The problem with this argument is that it is clear
that we are bodily entities-organisms, albeit of a particular
type, namely, organisms of a rational nature. A living thing
that performs bodily actions is an organism, a bodily entity.
But it is immediately obvious in the case of the human individual
that it is the same subject that perceives, walks,
and talks (which are bodily actions), and that understands,
deliberates, and makes choices what everyone, including
anyone who denies he is an organism, refers to as "I." It must
be the same entity that perceives these words on a page, for
example, and understands them. Thus, what each of us refers
to as "I" is identically the physical organism that is the subject
both of bodily actions, such as perceiving and walking, and
of mental activities, such as understanding and choosing. Therefore,
you and I are physical organisms, rather than consciousnesses
that merely inhabit or are "associated with" physical organisms.
And so, plainly, we came to be when the physical organism
we are came to be; we once were embryos, then fetuses,
then infants, and so on. Back
to Text
- Werner A. Muller, Developmental Biology (New York:
Springer Verlag, 1997), 12 f. Scott Gilbert, Developmental
Biology 5th edition (Sunderland, Mass.: Sinnauer Associates,
1997); O'Rahilly and Mueller, Human Embryology and Teratology,
23-24. Back
to Text
- O'Rahilly and Fabiola Mueller, Human Embryology and Teratology,
30-31. Back
to Text
- Ibid. 23-24; Keith Moore, and T.V.N. Persaud, Before We
Are Born: Essentials of Embryology and Birth Defects (Philadelphia:
W.B. Saunders, 1998), 41; William J. Larson, Human Embryology
3rd edition (New York: Churchill Livingstone, 2001), 18-21.
Back
to Text
- Gilbert, Developmental Biology, 12 f; 167 f. Also see
O'Rahilly and Mueller, Human Embryology and Teratology
23-24. Back
to Text
- A ban on implantation of an existing embryo or class of embryos
would be subject to constitutional as well as moral objections.
Such a ban would certainly be challenged, and the challenge
would likely come from a powerful coalition of "pro-life" and
"pro-choice" forces. A prohibition of the production of embryos
by cloning would have a far better likelihood of withstanding
constitutional challenge than would a ban on implantation. Back
to Text
* * *
Statement of Dr.Hurlbut
In joining with fellow Members of the Council in support of a
moratorium on cloning for biomedical research, I consider this
recommendation not an admission of ambivalence on matters of policy,
but a recognition of the difficulty of the moral issues involved
and an affirmation of the need for further discussion and deliberation.
Throughout our proceedings it has become increasingly apparent
that without clear and distinct moral principles, grounded in
scientific evidence and reasoned moral argument, no policy can
be effectively formulated or enforced. Most specifically, the
proposed limitation of fourteen days for research on human embryos
and the prohibition against implantation appear to be arbitrarily
set and therefore vulnerable to transgression through the persuasive
promise of further scientific benefit. Clearly, a more thorough
and thoughtful consideration of the moral status of the human
embryo is warranted. It is in the spirit of this continuing discussion
that I offer the personal perspectives that follow.
Introduction
In pondering the ethics of cloning-for-biomedical-research it
is apparent that as our science is changing, so is the nature
of our moral dilemmas. Each advance forces us to think more deeply
about what it means to be human. As the scientific focus on genomics
moves on to proteomics and now to the early stages of the study
of developmental biology, we are confronted with the challenge
of understanding the moral meaning of human life in its dynamics
of change, as both potential and process.
A reasonable anticipation of the likely course of science suggests
that concerns about cloning are just the beginning of a series
of difficult ethical issues relating to embryo experimentation
and medical intervention in developing life. In addition, advances
in developmental biology will open more deeply the dilemmas related
to human-animal hybridization, extra-corporeal gestation, and
genetic and cellular enhancement. Driven by the vast range of
research applications and opportunities for clinical interventions
in disease and disability (especially the open ended possibilities
promised by regenerative medicine) this technology will be powerfully
propelled into the forefront of medical science.
Given the complex course of science and the drive to its development,
any moral assessment of cloning-for-biomedical-research (CBR)
must describe the central human goods it seeks to preserve, the
range and boundaries of these values, and the broad implications
for science and society implied by them. Such an assessment should
serve the dual purpose of helping to define the moral dangers
while clearing the course for the fullest and most open future
for scientific investigation and application.
Moral Principles
Although there are already numerous promising approaches for
research on human development even without cloning-for-biomedical-research
(CBR), I believe this technology could provide valuable tools
for scientific inquiry and medical advance. In my judgment, the
moral imperative to foster an increase of knowledge and new modes
of therapeutic intervention weighs heavily in the equation of
consideration. Nonetheless, I believe that, as they stand, current
proposals for CBR will breach fundamental moral goods, erode social
cohesion and ultimately constrain the promise of advances in developmental
biology and their medical applications. However, there may be
morally acceptable ways of employing CBR that could both preserve
our commitment to fundamental moral principles and strengthen
our appreciation of the significance of developing life, while
also opening avenues of advance less limiting and more promising
than the current scientific proposals.
The principle of human life as the fundamental good serves as
the cornerstone of law for our civilization. In no circumstance
is the intentional destruction of the life of an innocent individual
deemed morally acceptable. Even where a right to abortion is given,
for example, it is based on a woman's right not to be encumbered,
a right of privacy, not a right to directly kill the fetus.i
This valuing of human life is indeed the moral starting point
for both advocates and opponents of CBR. This principle of the
inviolability of human life is the reciprocal respect that we
naturally grant as we recognize in the other a being of moral
equivalence to ourselves. Although different cultures and different
eras have affirmed this recognition in varied ways, I will argue
that it is reasonable in light of our current scientific knowledge
that we extend this principle to human life in its earliest developmental
stages.
Life as Process
When looked at through the lens of science, it is evident that
human existence cannot be defined atemporally, but must be recognized
in the full procession of continuity and change that is essential
for its development. From conception, our unique genetic endowment
organizes and guides the expression of our particular nature in
its species and individual character. Fertilization initiates
the most complex chemical reaction in the known universe: a self-directing,
purposeful integration of organismal development. In both character
and conduct the zygote and subsequent embryonic stages differ
from any other cells or tissues of the body; they contain within
themselves the organizing principle of the full human organism.
This is not an abstract or hypothetical potential in the sense
of mere possibility, but rather a potency, an engaged and effective
potential-in-process, an activated dynamic of development in the
direction of human fullness of being. For this reason a zygote
(or a clonote) differs fundamentally from an unfertilized egg,
a sperm cell, or later somatic cells; it possesses an inherent
organismal unity and potency that such other cells lack. Unlike
an assembly of parts in which a manufactured product is in no
sense "present" until there is a completed construction, a living
being has a continuous unfolding existence that is inseparable
from its emerging form. The form is itself a dynamic process rather
than a static structure. In biology, the whole (as the unified
organismal principle of growth) precedes and produces the parts.
It is this implicit whole, with its inherent potency, that endows
the embryo with its human character and therefore its inviolable
moral status. To interfere in its development is to transgress
upon a life in process. ii
The argument is sometimes made that
potential should not be part of the moral equation because of the
low probability of successful development of the early embryo.iii
This, however, is itself an argument based on potential, in this
case the lack of potential to develop normally.iv
The fact that life in its early stages is extremely fragile and
often fails is not an argument to lessen the moral standing of the
embryo. Vulnerability does not render a life less valuable. Accrued
Moral Status
The major alternative to the view that an embryo has an inherent
moral status is the assertion that moral status is an accrued
or accumulated quality related to some dimension of form or function.
Several arguments have been put forward for this position.
1. Gastrulation
One such accrual argument is based on the idea that before gastrulation
(designated as the fourteenth day) the embryo is an inchoate clump
of cells with no actuated drive in the direction of distinct development.v
It is argued that the undifferentiated quality of the blastocyst
justifies its disaggregation for the procurement of stem cells,
while the evident organization at gastrulation reveals an organismal
integrity that endows inviolable moral status to all subsequent
stages of embryological development. Scientific evidence, however,
supports the argument that from conception there is an unbroken
continuity in the differentiation and organization of the emerging
individual life. The anterior-posterior axis appears to be already
established within the zygote, early cell divisions (at least
after the eight-cell stage) exhibit differential gene expressionvi
and unequal cytoplasmic concentrations of cell constituents suggest
distinct cellular fates. This implies that the changes at gastrulation
do not represent a discontinuity of ontological significance,
but merely the visibly evident culmination of more subtle developmental
processes (at the cellular level) driving in the direction of
organismal maturity.
2. Twinning
Another argument for accrued moral status is that as long as
an embryo is capable of giving rise to a twin it cannot be considered
to have the moral standing of an individual. There is the obvious
objection that as one locus of moral status becomes two it does
not diminish but increases the moral moment. But perhaps more
substantially, this argument actually supports the notion that
crucial dimensions of individuation (and their disruption that
results in twinning) are already at work in the blastocyst, the
stage at which most twinning occurs. Monozygotic twinning (a mere
0.4 percent of births) does not appear to be either an intrinsic
drive or a random process within embryogenesis. Rather, it is
a disruption of normal development by a mechanical or biochemical
disturbance of fragile cell relationships that provokes a compensatory
repair, but with the restitution of integrity within two distinct
trajectories of embryological development.vii
In considering the implications of twinning for individuation,
one might ask the question from the opposite perspective. What
keeps each of these totipotent cells from becoming a full embryo?
Clearly, crucial relational dynamics of position and intercellular
communication are already at work establishing the unified pattern
of the emerging individual. From this perspective twinning is
not evidence of the absence of an individual, but of an extraordinary
power of compensatory repair that reflects more fully the potency
of the individual drive to fullness of form.
3. Implantation
Some have argued that the implantation of the embryo within the
uterine lining of the mother constitutes a moment of altered moral
status. Implantation, however, is actually a process that extends
from around the sixth or seventh day to about the eleventh or
twelfth day when the uteroplacental circulation is established.
This complex circulatory exchange extends the earlier relationship
between mother and embryo in which physiological conditions, including
the diffusion of essential nutrients, sustained the life and nourished
the growth of the developing embryo. Although these early conditions
can be artificially simulated as in IVF, the delicate balance
of essential factors and their effect on development (as seen
in Large Offspring Syndrome)viii
is evidence of the crucial contribution of the mother even in
the first week of embryogenesis. Changes in the intricate interrelations
between mother and infant cannot be viewed as an alteration of
moral status, but as part of the ongoing epigenetic process all
along the continuum of natural development that begins with conception
and continues into infancy. This continuity implies no meaningful
moral marker at implantation.ix
4. Function
Arguments for a change in moral status based on function are
at once the most difficult to refute and to defend. The first
and most obvious problem is that the essential functions (even
their minimal criteria and age of onset) are diverse and arbitrarily
assigned. Generally they relate to the onset of sentience, awareness
of pain, or some apparently unique human cognitive capability
such as consciousness.x
But if human moral worth is based on actual manifest functions,
then does more of a particular function give an individual life
a higher moral value? And what are we to make of the parallel
capacities in animals that we routinely sacrifice for food and
medical research? Furthermore, what becomes of human moral status
with the degeneration or disappearance of such a function? While
we might argue that our relational obligations change along with
changes in function, such as occur with senile dementia, we would
not sanction a utilitarian calculus and the purely instrumental
use of such persons no matter how promising the medical benefits
might be. The diagnostic requirements of "brain death" for removing
organs for transplantation, far from being a justification for
interrupting a developing life before "brain birth", actually
point to the moral significance of potential and the stringency
of the criteria for irreversible disintegration and death.
From a scientific perspective, there is no meaningful moment
when one can definitively designate the biological origins of
a human characteristic such as consciousness. Even designations
such as 'the nervous system' are conceptual tools, reifications
of an indivisible organismal unity. Zygote, morula, embryo, fetus,
child and adult: these are conceptual constructions for convenience
of description, not distinct ontological categories. With respect
to fundamental moral status therefore, as distinguished from developing
relational obligations, the human being is an embodied being whose
intrinsic dignity is inseparable from its full procession of life
and always present in its varied stages of emergence.
A Bright Line at Conception
If the embryo has an inherent moral status that is not an accrued
or accumulated quality related to some dimension of form or function,
then that moral status must begin with the zygote (or clonote).
Anything short of affirming the inviolability of life across all
of its stages from zygote to natural death leads to an instrumental
view of human life. Such a revocation of our most fundamental
moral principle would reverse a long and overarching trend of
progress in moral awareness and practice in our civilization.
From human sacrifice,xi
to slavery, child labor, women's rights and civil rights, we have
progressively discerned and prohibited practices that subject
the individual to the injustice of exploitation by others. The
reversal of such a basic moral valuation will extend itself in
a logic of justification that has ominous implications for our
attitude and approach to human existence. This is not a mere "slippery
slope," where we are slowly led downward by the ever more desirable
extension of exceptions to moral principle. It is, rather, a "crumbly
cliff" where the very utility of abrogating a basic moral prohibition
carries such convenience of consequence that the subsequent descent
is simply practice catching up with principle.
The inviolability of human life is the essential foundation on
which all other principles of justice are built, and any erosion
of this foundation destabilizes the social cooperation that makes
possible the benefits of organized society. Medicine is especially
vulnerable to such effects since it operates at the intrinsically
moral interface between scientific technique and the most tender
and sensitive dimensions of personal reality in the vulnerable
patient. As we descend into an instrumental use of human life
we destroy the very reason for which we were undertaking our new
therapies; we destroy the humanity we were trying to heal.
The promise of stem cells lies beyond simple cell cultures and
cell replacement therapies. The fourteen-day marker will not hold
up to logical argument.xii
The technological goal is to produce the more advanced cell types
of tissues, organs, and possibly even limb primordia. Producing
such complex tissues and organs may require the cell interactions
and microenvironments now available only through natural gestation.xiii
The benefits of implanting cloned embryos (either into the natural
womb or possibly an artificial endometrium) so as to employ the
developmental dynamics of natural embryogenesis seem self-evident.
The implantation of cloned embryos for the production of patient-specific
tissue types to bypass problems of immune rejection would further
extend the logic of the instrumental use of developing life. The
public pressure that has already been brought to bear on the politics
of stem cells and cloning by patient advocacy groups has provoked
such a sense of promise that it may propel the argument for allowing
implantation of cloned embryos. Different people may have different
limits to the duration of gestation they find morally acceptable,
but in light of the current sanction of abortion up to and beyond
the end of the second trimester, it is difficult to argue that
creation, gestation and sacrifice of a clone to save an existing
life is a large leap in the logic of justification.
A Speculative Proposal
While maintaining a bright line at conception safeguards our
most fundamental moral principle, the challenge remains to find
an acceptable method of drawing on the great medical promise of
CBR while precluding its use in ways that degrade the dignity
of human existence. Some proponents of CBR maintain that the laboratory
creation of the cloned embryo makes it a "pseudo-embryo" or "artifact,"
a product of human technological production.xiv
The problem with this assertion is that, once created, the cloned
embryo appears to be no different than the product of natural
fertilization. But what if we could use the cloning techniques
of nuclear transfer to create an entity that lacks the qualities
and capabilities essential to be designated a human life in process?
By intentional alteration of the somatic cell nuclear components
or the cytoplasm of the oocyte into which they are transferred,
could we truly create an artifact (a human creation for human
ends) that is biologically and morally more akin to tissue or
cell culture?xv
The intention in creating such an intrinsically limited "clonal
artifact" would not be one of reproduction, but simply the desire
to draw on natural organic potential through technological manipulation
of biological materials. This intention is in keeping with the
purposes of scientific research and medical therapy in which many
"unnatural" manipulations are used for human benefit. In order
to employ such an entity for research, it must be capable of yielding
stem cells while lacking the capacity for the self-directed, integrated
organic functioning that is essential for embryogenesis. The intervention
that precludes the possibility of human development would be undertaken
at a stage before the development was initiated, and thus, no
active potentiality, no human life in process, would be violated.
If the created artifact were accorded a certain cautionary respect
(as with all human tissues), even though not the full protection
of human life, the consequences of such a program would not compromise
any moral principle.
The project of creating these altered "clonal artifacts" for
the procurement of human stem cells could have many loci of scientific
intervention. Techniques might range from removing genes for extra-embryonic
structures, to the alteration of genes for angiogenesis (such
that the stem cells procured could produce differentiated cell
types with therapeutic potential, but would have to rely on the
host into whom they were placed for their vascular connections).
If the created stem cells could only form specific germ layers
or limited lineages of cell types, they still might be useful
for the generation of valuable research models as well as many
cell lines, tissues and organs. Furthermore, in bypassing the
moral concerns associated with full embryonic potential, the created
cells might legitimately be developed within artificial microenvironments
beyond fourteen days. This would allow the production of more
advanced cell types, the study of tissue interactions and the
formation of primordial organismal parts. Just as we have learned
that neither genes, nor cells, nor even whole organs define the
locus of human moral standing, in this era of developmental biology
we will come to recognize that tissues with "partial generative
potential" may be used for medical benefit without a violation
of human dignity.xvi
The fact that one does not need full embryonic integrity for these
partial generative capacities is evident in the well-formed body
parts such as teeth, fingernails and hair seen in teratomas.xvii
Clearly, there will be some point where partial generative potential
is so close to full human development that our basic moral principals
would be violated. We will need to carefully define the circumstances
under which it is acceptable for serious medical purposes to manipulate
human parts apart from their natural context in human development.
Here the fundamental principle of protection of human life must
be affirmed, while the more subtle moral issues concerning respect
and natural integrity are carefully explored.
At this early stage in our technological control of developing
life, we have an opportunity to break the impasse over stem cell
research and provide moral guidance for the biotechnology of the
future. This may require a constructive reformulation of some
aspects of moral philosophy, together with creative exploration
of scientific possibilities, but any postponement of this process
will only deepen the dilemma as we proceed into realms of technological
advance unguided by forethought. A moratorium will allow the cooperative
dialogue that is essential to frame the moral principles that
can at once defend human dignity and promote the fullest prospects
for scientific progress and its medical applications.
William B. Hurlbut
____________________
- If the fetus is delivered alive during an abortion, there
is a legal obligation to resuscitate and sustain its life. Back
to Text
- To recognize a potential as in some sense "actual" and worthy
of protection, we need only consider how we would react to the
intentional sterilization of a prepubescent girl when her fertility
was only potential yet precious to her larger dignity and developmental
integrity as a human person. Back
to Text
- Such an argument might hold some weight if one could argue
that a given stage of development represents an emergent state
in which a relational property is in ontological discontinuity
with the material from which it emerged. At first consideration,
this seems true of all biological systems where the whole reveals
properties unpredicted within the parts. The problem in this
line of reasoning, however, is that these properties are exactly
that to which the whole is ordered and so are inherent powers,
"actual" within the whole when seen across time. To know what
a biological being is, we must observe it over time, understand
it across its life span. It is the essence of life that it is
ordered to employ these leaps to emergent states as
an agency in development. New realities will emerge; this is
established in the potency of the developing organism. Back
to Text
- A similar problem arises in clinical medicine. It is crucial
that we not equate the statistical probability of a specific
outcome with the actual prognosis of the individual patient
involved. Back
to Text
- The differentiation of the trophoblast, which will form the
extra-embryonic membranes, is generally considered as distinct
from the embryo itself. More true to the nature of life, it
might be recognized as an organ of embryogenesis used and discarded
within the dynamic process of development. Throughout the continuum
of human life, from the embryo to the adult, cells, tissues
and organs are reabsorbed, transcended and transformed. Examples
include the umbilical vein and arteries (which become supporting
ligaments), neurologic cells (more than half of which are culled
by apoptosis and reabsorption), systems of reflexes (such as
the moro reflex which is manifest only in infants), immune organs
and functions such as the thymus (which shrivels in an adult),
and allergies (which change throughout life and generally wane
in mid-life). We do not just develop and then age, but undergo
a continuous transformation and fuller manifestation of our
organismal nature present within the earliest embryo. Back
to Text
- In fact, the first several cell divisions after natural fertilization
do not require a nucleus to be present and therefore may not
involve gene expression from the newly united bi-parental genetic
material. The mRNA essential for protein synthesis at these
early stages appears to be generated during the maturation of
the egg and then remains dormant until after fertilization.
This may very well preclude the possibilities of the optimistic
but simplistic proposal that merely by adding a recipe of cytoplasmic
factors essential for reprogramming we could transform any cell
into a functional zygote. Nonetheless, even without differential
gene expression, cytoplasmic studies reveal unequal cytoplasmic
distributions, and implicit differential cell fates, even at
these early stages. Back
to Text
- The fact that these early cells retain the ability to form
a second embryo is testimony to the resiliency of self-regulation
and compensation within early life, not the lack of individuation
of the first embryo from which the second can be considered
to have "budded" off. Evidence for this may be seen in the increased
incidence of monozygotic twinning associated with IVF by Blastocyst
Transfer. When IVF embryos are transferred to the uterus for
implantation at the blastocyst stage, there is a two to ten-fold
increase in the rate of monozygotic twinning, apparently due
to disruption of normal organismal integrity. It is also interesting
to note that with Blastocyst Transfer there is a slightly higher
rate of male births. Back
to Text
- In some animal studies, it has been noted that particular
components in the culture medium in which the embryo is nourished
increase the size of the offspring during later stages of gestation.
Back
to Text
- It should be noted that this argument could be used as a counter-argument
against the disaggregation of the preimplantation embryo, or
as a justification for the production of more advanced cells,
tissues, and organs either through implantation into an artificial
endometrium or through natural gestation. Back
to Text
- In fact, from a scientific perspective, we should have a measure
of humility when drawing conclusions about moral status from
evidence concerning consciousness or capacities involving subjective
experience. The fact that consciousness and subjective awareness
appear to be mediated by matter does not exhaust their mystery.
Back
to Text
- The sacrifice of infants for the supposed larger flourishing
of life bespeaks the potency ascribed to purity and generative
potential. Back
to Text
- The designation of fourteen days as the moral boundary for
embryo experimentation is in the category of a "received tradition,"
almost a superstition in the sense that it is a belief in a
change of state without a discernible cause. The validity of
this designated moral marker has not been reexamined in the
light of recent advances in our understanding of developmental
biology. As a moral marker of ontological change fourteen days
makes no sense. Even if one disagrees with the discussion above,
the date should be set earlier: implantation is complete by
the twelfth day, the onset of gastrulation occurs between the
twelfth and fourteenth day and twinning is rare after the ninth
day. Furthermore, it is worth noting that fourteen days is not
of current scientific relevance since stem cells can be procured
at the four-five day stage and, with present technology, human
embryos can sustain viability in culture for only eight-nine
days. Back
to Text
- Natural development proceeds within the context of a highly
refined spatial and temporal niche of organized complexity of
positional cues, signal diffusion and cell-cell contact between
cellular lineages of diverse types. See for example the recent
article, "Dominant role of the niche in melanocyte stem-cell
fate determination" (Nature 25 April 2002). Back
to Text
- In fact, there will be several (and perhaps numerous) ways
to produce cloned blastocysts from which stem cells can be harvested.
These include: the current common method of cloning designated
somatic cell nuclear transfer (SCNT) or nuclear transplantation,
embryo splitting, use of animal oocytes as receptacles of nuclear
transfer, fusion of embryonic stem cells and possibly fetal
or adult stem cells into existing blastocysts and possibly the
production of artificial gametes for the transfer of adult nuclear
material, (and probably others more difficult to anticipate
or legally regulate). Back
to Text
- Such a procedure could be designated "Altered Nuclear Transfer"
(ANT). Back
to Text
- Consider blood transfusions, organ transplantation, and the
recombination of human genes into bacteria for the production
of human hormones such as growth hormone and insulin. All of
these raised initial moral controversy until it was recognized
that the locus of human dignity lies not it human parts but
in the full organismal integrity of a human life. Back
to Text
- These benign ovarian tumors, derived by spontaneous and disorganized
development of activated ova, typically have a full array of
primary tissue types and some well-developed body parts. The
possibility that embryonic stem cells could be derived from
entities lacking integrated developmental potential is given
further support from recent studies in which cells from abnormal
early embryos were fused with normal embryos and went on to
produce normal tissues in the developed organism. (See "Dependable
Cells From Defective Embryos." Science 3 May 2002, p. 841, and
Byrne, Simons and Gurdon: Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences (PNAS) online, April 23, 2002.) Back
to Text
* * *
Statement of Dr. Krauthammer
I oppose all cloning, reproductive and research. I would like
to see them banned. But I live in the real world. As I have explained,
both in the Council and in my writings, I oppose research cloning
for prudential reasons. Prudence dictates taking into account
the real world, meaning the realities of American democracy, and
at present there is no consensus for banning research cloning.
I therefore strongly support a moratorium. At this point in the
history of this debate, a moratorium is more than a compromise.
It is an important achievement.
Let's remember. In a democracy, there is no such thing as a permanent
ban in any case. Any ban can be revisited at any time. Thus the
difference between a ban and a moratorium is simply this: Under
a ban, when the issue is reconsidered, the burden of proof is
on those who wish to lift the ban. With a moratorium, when the
issue is reconsidered, the burden of proof is on those who wish
to maintain the ban. I have no trepidation about remaking the
case for a ban when the moratorium expires.
In the interim, I vote strongly in favor of the moratorium over
the alternative proposal of regulation. First, because I am keenly
aware of the power of the scientific imperative to breach frontiers
of ethics, and deeply distrustful of the ability of society to
resist those scientific imperatives. I am highly skeptical about
the ultimate efficacy of regulation in preventing the breaching
of further moral barriers.
And second, because regulation is really just a nicely confectured
way of saying that we are prepared as a society today to utterly
abolish a crucial moral barrier, namely, the prohibition of the
creation of human embryos solely for the purpose of experimentation.
That is a serious moral barrier. The argument that we already
crossed that barrier when we permitted the use of discarded embryos
from IVF clinics for stem-cell research is simple sophistry.1
Creating human embryos solely for their exploitation in research
and therapy is new. It is dangerous. It is something that we will
live to regret. A moratorium will prevent that for now, and allow
a restatement of the case for its unwisdom and its danger when
the issue is later reconsidered.
I support the moratorium on research cloning for several additional
reasons. First, because the impasse on research cloning has led
to congressional failure to enact any anti-cloning legislation.
That is absurd. There is a unanimous national feeling that reproductive
cloning should be banned. Our proposal provides a compromise that
both sides can embrace so that cloning legislation can be passed.
Second, for those who support regulation, the moratorium is the
only effective way to move toward serious regulation. The vague
call for regulation, made by proponents of Position Two, has no
political traction. None of the relevant players has any incentive
to prepare the regulations. The scientific community is largely
opposed to any interference in this research. And while people
are dithering, the cloning research in the private biotech industries
will put facts on the ground that will be difficult to challenge.
Only a moratorium can test the good faith of those who say they
want regulation. Moreover, Position Two does not explicitly say
that the existence of the strict regulations it calls for is a
precondition for allowing the research to go forward. There is
no talk here, as there was in the public Council sessions, that
this proposal amounts to a de facto moratorium.
Third, this proposal does not abandon the strong anti-cloning
position. It stops cloning at the very beginning, namely at the
point of creating a cloned embryo. It is thus much stronger than
the pseudo-ban on cloning proposed by those who want regulation,
which would block only implantation.
A ban on reproductive cloning and a moratorium on research cloning
allows the country to clearly express itself: definitively make
law regarding reproductive cloning and at least temporarily prevent
the launching of an industry whose business is the manufacture
of (cloned) human embryos purely for experimentation. And it allows
the country to engage now in a serious and extended debate on
the virtues and pitfalls of such an enterprise, on the promise
and problems of regulation, and, ultimately, on the question of
not only where these cells come from, but where these cells are
taking us.
I include here a memo that I circulated to Council Members during
our deliberationsii
:
The conquest of rejection is one of the principal rationales
for research cloning. But there is reason to doubt this claim
on scientific grounds. There is some empirical evidence in
mice that cloned tissue may be rejected anyway (possibly because
a clone contains a small amount of foreign-mitochondrial-DNA
derived from the egg into which it was originally injected).
Moreover, enormous advances are being made elsewhere in combating
tissue rejection. The science of immune rejection is much
more mature than the science of cloning. By the time we figure
out how to do safe and reliable research cloning, the rejection
problem may well be solved. And finally, there are less problematic
alternatives such as adult stem cells that offer
a promising alternative to cloning because they present no
problem of tissue rejection and raise none of cloning's moral
conundrums. These scientific considerations raise serious
questions about the efficacy of, and thus the need for, research
cloning. But there is a stronger case to be made. Even if
the scientific objections are swept aside, even if research
cloning is as doable and promising as its advocates contend,
there are other reasons to pause.
The most obvious is this: Research cloning is an open door
to reproductive cloning. Banning the production of cloned
babies while permitting the production of cloned embryos makes
no sense. If you have factories all around the country producing
embryos for research and commerce, it is inevitable that someone
will implant one in a woman (or perhaps in some artificial
medium in the farther future) and produce a human clone. What
then? A law banning reproductive cloning but permitting research
cloning would then make it a crime not to destroy that fetus
an obvious moral absurdity.
This is an irrefutable point and the reason alone to vote for
the total ban on cloning. Philosophically, however, it is a
showstopper. It lets us off too early and too easy. It keeps
us from facing the deeper question: Is there anything about
research cloning that in and of itself makes it morally problematic?
Objection I: Intrinsic Worth
For some people, life begins at conception. And not just
life if life is understood to mean a biologically functioning
organism, even a single cell is obviously alive but
personhood. If the first zygotic cell is owed all the legal
and moral respect due a person, then there is nothing to talk
about. Ensoulment starts with Day One and Cell One, and the
idea of taking that cell or its successor cells apart to serve
someone else's needs is abhorrent.
This is an argument of great moral force but little intellectual
interest. Not because it may not be right. But because it
is unprovable. It rests on metaphysics. Either you believe
it or you don't. The discussion ends there. I happen not to
share this view. I do not believe personhood begins at conception.
I do not believe a single cell has the moral or legal standing
of a child. This is not to say that I do not stand in awe
of the developing embryo, a creation of majestic beauty and
mystery. But I stand in equal awe of the Grand Canyon, the
spider's web, and quantum mechanics. Awe commands wonder,
humility, appreciation. It does not command inviolability.
I am quite prepared to shatter an atom, take down a spider's
web, or dam a canyon for electricity. (Though we'd have to
be very short on electricity before I'd dam the Grand.)
I do not believe the embryo is entitled to inviolability.
But is it entitled to nothing? There is a great distance between
inviolability, on the one hand, and mere "thingness," on the
other. Many advocates of research cloning see nothing but
thingness. That view justifies the most ruthless exploitation
of the embryo. That view is dangerous. Why? Three possible
reasons. First, the Brave New World Factor: Research cloning
gives man too much power for evil. Second, the Slippery Slope:
The habit of embryonic violation is in and of itself dangerous.
Violate the blastocyst today and every day, and the practice
will inure you to violating the fetus or even the infant tomorrow.
Third, Manufacture: The very act of creating embryos for the
sole purpose of exploiting and then destroying them will ultimately
predispose us to a ruthless utilitarianism about human life
itself.
Objection II: The Brave New World Factor
The physicists at Los Alamos did not hesitate to penetrate,
manipulate, and split uranium atoms on the grounds that uranium
atoms possess intrinsic worth that entitled them to inviolability.
Yet after the war, many fought to curtail atomic power. They
feared the consequences of delivering such unfathomable power
and potential evil into the hands of fallible
human beings. Analogously, one could believe that the cloned
blastocyst has little more intrinsic worth than the uranium
atom and still be deeply troubled by the manipulation of the
blastocyst because of the fearsome power it confers upon humankind.
The issue is leverage. Our knowledge of how to manipulate
human genetics (or atomic nuclei) is still primitive. We could
never construct ex nihilo a human embryo. It is an unfolding
organism of unimaginable complexity that took nature three
billion years to produce. It might take us less time to build
it from scratch, but not much less. By that time, we as a
species might have acquired enough wisdom to use it wisely.
Instead, the human race in its infancy has stumbled upon a
genie infinitely too complicated to create or even fully understand,
but understandable enough to command and perhaps even control.
And given our demonstrated unwisdom with our other great discovery
atomic power: As we speak, the very worst of humanity
is on the threshold of acquiring the most powerful weapons
in history this is a fear and a consideration to be
taken very seriously.
For example. Female human eggs seriously limit the mass production
of cloned embryos. Extracting eggs from women is difficult,
expensive, and potentially dangerous. The search is on, therefore,
for a good alternative. Scientists have begun injecting human
nuclei into the egg cells of animals. In 1996 Massachusetts
scientists injected a human nucleus with a cow egg. Chinese
scientists have fused a human fibroblast with a rabbit egg
and have grown the resulting embryo to the blastocyst stage.
We have no idea what grotesque results might come from such
interspecies clonal experiments.
In October 2000 the first primate containing genes from another
species was born (a monkey with a jellyfish gene). In 1995
researchers in Texas produced headless mice. In 1997 researchers
in Britain produced headless tadpoles. In theory, headlessness
might be useful for organ transplantation. One can envision,
in a world in which embryos are routinely manufactured, the
production of headless clones subhuman creatures with
usable human organs but no head, no brain, no consciousness
to identify them with the human family.
The heart of the problem is this: Nature, through endless
evolution, has produced cells with totipotent power. We are
about to harness that power for crude human purposes. That
should give us pause. Just around the corner lies the logical
by-product of such power: human-animal hybrids, partly developed
human bodies for use as parts, and other horrors imagined
Huxley's Deltas and Epsilons and as yet un imagined.
This is the Brave New World Factor. Its grounds for objecting
to this research are not about the beginnings of life, but
about the ends; not the origin of these cells, but their destiny;
not where we took these magnificent cells from, but where
they are taking us.
Objection III: The Slippery Slope
The other prudential argument is that once you start tearing
apart blastocysts, you get used to tearing apart blastocysts.
And whereas now you'd only be doing that at the seven-day
stage, when most people would look at this tiny clump of cells
on the head of a pin and say it is not inviolable, it is inevitable
that some scientist will soon say: Give me just a few more
weeks to work with it and I could do wonders.
That will require quite a technological leap because the
blastocyst will not develop as a human organism unless implanted
in the uterus. That means that to go beyond that seven-day
stage you'd have to implant this human embryo either in an
animal uterus or in some fully artificial womb.
Both possibilities may be remote, but they are real. And
then we'll have a scientist saying: Give me just a few more
months with this embryo, and I'll have actual kidney cells,
brain cells, pancreatic cells that I can transplant back into
the donor of the clone and cure him. Scientists at Advanced
Cell Technology in Massachusetts have already gone past that
stage in animals. They have taken cloned cow embryos past
the blastocyst stage, taken tissue from the more developed
cow fetus, and reimplanted it back into the donor animal.
The scientists' plea to do the same in humans will be hard
to ignore. Why grow the clone just to the blastocyst stage,
destroy it, pull out the inner cell mass, grow stem cells
out of that, propagate them in the laboratory, and then try
chemically or otherwise to tweak them into becoming kidney
cells or brain cells or islet cells? This is Rube Goldberg.
Why not just allow that beautiful embryonic machine, created
by nature and far more sophisticated than our crude techniques,
to develop unmolested? Why not let the blastocyst grow into
a fetus that possesses the kinds of differentiated tissue
that we could then use for curing the donor?
Scientifically, this would make sense. Morally, we will
have crossed the line between tearing apart a mere clump of
cells and tearing apart a recognizable human fetus. And at
that point, it would be an even smaller step to begin carving
up seven and eight-month-old fetuses with more perfectly
formed organs to alleviate even more pain and suffering among
the living. We will, slowly and by increments, have gone from
stem cells to embryo farms to factories with fetuses in various
stages of development and humanness, hanging (metaphorically)
on meat hooks waiting to be cut open to be used by the already
born.
We would all be revolted if a living infant or developed
fetus were carved up for parts. Should we build a fence around
that possibility by prohibiting any research on even the very
earliest embryonic clump of cells? Is the only way to avoid
the slide never to mount the slippery slope at all? On this
question, I am personally agnostic. If I were utterly convinced
that we would never cross the seven-day line, then I would
have no objection on these grounds to such research on the
inner cell mass of a blastocyst. The question is: Can we be
sure? This is not a question of principle; it is a question
of prudence. It is almost a question of psychological probability.
No one yet knows the answer.
Objection IV: Manufacture
Note that while, up to now, I have been considering arguments
against research cloning, they are all equally applicable
to embryonic research done on a normal i.e., noncloned
embryo. If the question is tearing up the blastocyst,
there is no intrinsic moral difference between a two-parented
embryo derived from a sperm and an egg and a single-parented
embryo derived from a cloned cell. Thus the various arguments
against this research the intrinsic worth of the embryo,
the prudential consideration that we might create monsters,
or the prudential consideration that we might become monsters
in exploiting post-embryonic forms of human life (fetuses
or even children) are identical to the arguments for
and against stem-cell research.
These arguments are serious serious enough to banish
the insouciance of the scientists who consider anyone questioning
their work to be a Luddite yet, in my view, insufficient
to justify a legal ban on stem-cell research (as with stem
cells from discarded embryos in fertility clinics). I happen
not to believe that either personhood or ensoulment occurs
at conception. I think we need to be apprehensive about what
evil might arise from the power of stem-cell research, but
that apprehension alone, while justifying vigilance and regulation,
does not justify a ban on the practice. And I believe that
given the good that might flow from stem-cell research, we
should first test the power of law and custom to enforce the
seven-day blastocyst line for embryonic exploitation before
assuming that such a line could never hold.
This is why I support stem-cell research (using leftover
embryos from fertility clinics) and might support research
cloning were it not for one other aspect that is unique to
it. In research cloning, the embryo is created with the explicit
intention of its eventual destruction. That is a given because
not to destroy the embryo would be to produce a cloned child.
If you are not permitted to grow the embryo into a child,
you are obliged at some point to destroy it.
Deliberately creating embryos for eventual and certain destruction
means the launching of an entire industry of embryo manufacture.
It means the routinization, the commercialization, the commodification
of the human embryo. The bill that would legalize research
cloning essentially sanctions, licenses, and protects the
establishment of a most ghoulish enterprise: the creation
of nascent human life for the sole purpose of its exploitation
and destruction.
How is this morally different from simply using discarded
embryos from in vitro fertilization (IVF) clinics? Some have
suggested that it is not, that to oppose research cloning
is to oppose IVF and any stem-cell research that comes out
of IVF. The claim is made that because in IVF there is a high
probability of destruction of the embryo, it is morally equivalent
to research cloning. But this is plainly not so. In research
cloning there is not a high probability of destruction; there
is 100 percent probability. Because every cloned embryo must
be destroyed, it is nothing more than a means to someone else's
end.
In IVF, the probability of destruction may be high, but it
need not necessarily be. You could have a clinic that produces
only a small number of embryos, and we know of many cases
of multiple births resulting from multiple embryo implantation.
In principle, one could have IVF using only a single embryo
and thus involving no deliberate embryo destruction at all.
In principle, that is impossible in research cloning.
Furthermore, a cloned embryo is created to be destroyed and
used by others. An IVF embryo is created to develop into a
child. One cannot disregard intent in determining morality.
Embryos are created in IVF to serve reproduction. Embryos
are created in research cloning to serve, well, research.
If certain IVF embryos were designated as "helper embryos"
that would simply aid an anointed embryo in turning into a
child, then we would have an analogy to cloning. But, in fact,
we don't know which embryo is anointed in IVF. They are all
created to have a chance of survival. And they are all equally
considered an end.
Critics counter that this ends-and-means argument is really
obfuscation, that both procedures make an instrument of the
embryo. In cloning, the creation and destruction of the embryo
is a means to understanding or curing disease. In IVF, the
creation of the embryo is a means of satisfying a couple's
need for a child. They are both just means to ends.
But it makes no sense to call an embryo a means to the creation
of a child. The creation of a child is the destiny of an embryo.
To speak of an embryo as a means to creating a child empties
the word "means" of content. The embryo in IVF is a stage
in the development of a child; it is no more a means than
a teenager is a means to the adult he or she later becomes.
In contrast, an embryo in research cloning is pure means.
Laboratory pure.
And that is where we must draw the line. During the great
debate on stem-cell research, a rather broad consensus was
reached (among those not committed to "intrinsic worth" rendering
all embryos inviolable) that stem-cell research could be morally
justified because the embryos destroyed for their possibly
curative stem cells were derived from fertility clinics and
thus were going to be discarded anyway. It was understood
that human embryos should not be created solely for the purpose
of being dismembered and then destroyed for the benefit of
others. Indeed, when Senator Bill Frist made his impassioned
presentation on the floor of the Senate supporting stem-cell
research, he included among his conditions a total ban on
creating human embryos just to be stem-cell farms.
Where cloning for research takes us decisively beyond stem-cell
research is in sanctioning the manufacture of the human embryo.
You can try to regulate embryonic research to prohibit the
creation of Brave New World monsters; you can build fences
on the slippery slope, regulating how many days you may grow
an embryo for research; but once you countenance the very
creation of human embryos for no other purpose than for their
parts, you have crossed a moral frontier.
Research cloning is the ultimate in conferring thingness
up on the human embryo. It is the ultimate in desensitization.
And as such, it threatens whatever other fences and safeguards
we might erect around embryonic research. The problem, one
could almost say, is not what cloning does to the embryo,
but what it does to us. Except that, once cloning has changed
us, it will inevitably enable further assaults on human dignity.
Creating a human embryo just so it can be used and then destroyed
undermines the very foundation of the moral prudence that
informs the entire enterprise of genetic research: the idea
that, while a human embryo may not be a person, it is not
nothing. Because if it is nothing, then everything is permitted.
And if everything is permitted, then there are no fences,
no safeguards, no bottom.
_____________________
- As I elaborate in my memo to Council
Members, reprinted below. Back
to Text
-
- A longer version of this argument appears in my article, "Crossing
Lines," The New Republic, April 29, 2002, pp. 20-23.
Back
to Text
CHARLES KRAUTHAMMER
* * *
Statement of Dr. McHugh
I am concerned that section (g) of Part I of Chapter Eight
does not adequately describe my views about somatic cell nuclear
transfer (SCNT), expressed at several meetings of the Council.
That section says, "[P]roposals to engage in cloning-for-biomedical-research
necessarily endorse the creation of human (cloned) embryos solely
for the purpose of such research. Public policy that specifically
promoted this research would thus explicitly and officially
approve crossing a moral boundary." (Italics in the text.)
I believe (1) those words imply that the prime effect of SCNT
is the creation of a new individual human being and (2) that
implication prejudges the problem before us and does not comport
to my opinion of this matter.
I hold that SCNT rests on a major discovery in cellular biology,
the implications of which need much more discussion and debate
than it receives in Chapter Eight (and especially in section
(g)). With this discovery we now know that every one of our
somatic cells not only has a full complement of our genes but
as well that every one of our somatic cells, if manipulated
in a particular fashion, has the power to recapitulate in growth
its own beginnings.
When a technician takes a donor's somatic cell and proceeds
with it to follow the method of somatic cell nuclear transplantation,
he or she evokes an intrinsic program present within that nucleus
that brings about cellular multiplication and differentiation.
One need not hold that a new and unique human individual starts
up immediately as these cells are made and multiply. One could
see this process as an engineered culturing of cells from the
somatic nucleus that recapitulates embryonic development but
rests upon a potential for growth and replication resident in
and intrinsic to all somatic cells. The cellular products are
direct extensions of the donor as with other forms of tissue
culture and as such have some licit potentials for further use.
I agree with those who say that my argument that the
products of SCNT and the products of impregnation are crucially
different places a strong emphasis on origins of these
products and less emphasis on potentials that we deplore. But
I would hold that the section (g) from Part I of Chapter Eight
places all the emphasis on potential and no emphasis on origins.
It thus ignores the fact that an overemphasis on potential would
lead us to the unreasonable position that since every one of
our somatic cells has "potential" for producing a human, it
should receive some reverence. I believe that in our presentation
to the American people we must acknowledge that some of the
arguments in favor of the use of SCNT rest upon the view that
what is emerging here are cells and not human beings. This very
fundamental disagreement should be thoroughly aired, as it carries
with it quite different policy implications.
PAUL McHUGH
* * *
Statement of Dr. May
Substantial moral debate on cloning-for-biomedical-research
focuses on the question as to whether the preimplanted embryo
is "one of us" or not. The group in favor of unregulated research
would define "one of us" narrowly in order to exclude the microscopic
material in the petri dish from "one of us." Therefore we can
do with it what we will. Proponents of a ban define "one of
us" broadly to include the preimplanted embryo. Therefore they
would refuse to clone/kill a preimplanted embryo used in research,
even at the expense of the relief that successful research might
offer some patients who are seriously impaired or face premature
death. Both parties seek to escape the stigma (and perhaps the
regulatory burdens) that might accompany therapy that owed something
to "one of us."
However, there is a way of thinking about the preimplanted
embryo that does not rely on the inclusionary/exclusionary language
of "one of us." The somewhat awkward language of the intermediate
status of the embryo (neither a mere thing nor a full human
being) both permits research but also requires
regulation. The status of the preimplanted embryo permits research
because it does not hold such a claim on us as to ban a line
of inquiry that might thwart grave human suffering and premature
death. However, the source of this research in the
human argues for the necessity of regulations. The preimplanted
embryo is more than a yard lot of building materials; it is
a cluster of cells moving toward, if implanted, nourished, and
protected, a human life. In removing it, through research, from
the circle of life, we cannot remove it from the circle of human
indebtedness.
This position has powerful implications for the content
as well as the necessity of regulations. Most discussion has
centered on regulations as they might bear on the generation
of knowledge and therapies (for example, the protection of women
as the source of eggs, the time limit on research to a fourteen-day
period before the onset of the neural streak, the development
of licensing and monitoring procedures, and extending the scope
of regulations to private as well as publicly funded projects).
However, the acceptance of a human source for the conduct of
this research has equally powerful consequences for the distribution
of knowledge and therapies. Gratefully accepting a human source
that makes possible the conduct of this research requires the
most inclusive destination of its fruits in the common good.
The element of gift in origin requires common human access to
benefits. It does not permit the capture of knowledge and benefits
in such a way as to thwart their eventual arrival to all in
need.
William F. May
* * *
Statement of Professor Meilaender
Like some of my colleagues on the Council, I believe that a
ban on all forms of human cloning (including a ban on what in
this report is called cloning-for-biomedical-research) would
be the optimal policy for this Council to recommend and for
our society to adopt. Nevertheless, because other Council Members
who have serious moral reservations about human cloning are
not at this time prepared to recommend a permanent ban on all
human cloning, we have joined with them to support a policy
that would ban cloning-to-produce-children and would place a
four-year moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research. Even
if the policy I regard as optimal is for now impossible, we
need not settle for no policy at all. Nor should we think of
the majority recommendation as simply a compromise position.
On the contrary, we have found genuine though only partial
agreement with some of our colleagues on the Council,
and I prefer to try to use and build on that partial agreement
than to act as if it were unimportant or insignificant. Were
the majority recommendation enacted into law, it would prohibit
all human cloning (whether publicly or privately funded) for
four years. That would be a considerable achievement. It would
give us a period in which the optimal policy was in place, during
which time we would hope that further moral debate and advances
in alternative forms of research (that would not involve human
cloning or destruction of embryos) would persuade others to
continue that optimal policy indefinitely.
In the Council's deliberations, those who oppose all human
cloning have worked very hard to respect and acknowledge the
views of Council Members with whom we disagree or do not fully
agree. In particular, the following points are worth noting:
(a) For the sake of continued conversation, we have acquiesced
in terminology that some of us do not fully accept and that
to some extent distorts our position. That is, any human cloning
is morally objectionable, and there is for some of us no crucial
moral divide between cloning-for-biomedical-research and cloning-to-produce-children.
Put differently, research cloning is also reproductive cloning,
since it brings into existence a new human being (in the very
earliest stages of developing human life). Agreeing to converse
in terms that do not fully acknowledge this has inevitably been
problematic; nevertheless, we have accepted this burden so that
the Council's work could proceed. I believe that the definitions
of cloning-for-biomedical-research and cloning-to-produce-children
given at the end of Chapter Three of the Council's report make
clear that, however the proximate or ultimate purposes of those
engaged in cloning may differ, the nature of the act remains
the same.
(b) In supporting a proposed four-year moratorium on cloning-for-biomedical-research
(even though some of us are quite prepared to support a permanent
ban) we have sought to make common cause with those Council
Members who worry more about cloning-to-produce-children than
about cloning-for-biomedical-research and for whom control of
the latter is chiefly a means to control of the former. I myself
incline to think, on the contrary, that an industry of routinized
embryo cloning (which would be the inevitable result of approval
of cloning-for-biomedical-research) would be an even greater
moral evil than the gestation and birth of a cloned human being.
Nevertheless, recognizing that some colleagues on the Council
who support a moratorium do not yet share this view, others
of us have chosen to endorse the partial agreement that we do
now share.
(c) We have accepted in good faith the assertion and
it has seldom been more than an assertion that advocates
of cloning-for-biomedical-research have a principled commitment
to drawing a line at a very early point in embryonic development
and permitting no research beyond that point. We have accepted
this in good faith even though we have been offered no coherent
argument to support the "developmental" view of human status
put forward by cloning proponents. Other Members of the Council
have offered a variety of arguments against that view. We have
offered evidence that embryologists do not make the sort of
distinction on which cloning proponents rely. We have noted
that the embryo's "potential" is something actual, something
present in the developing human being, and that it is a misuse
of the idea of potential to describe the embryo as merely a
potential human being. We have argued that, while it is true
that we would be unlikely to feel the same grief at the death
of an embryo as we do at the death of a child, this hardly means
that the embryo's life should not be protected. We have noted
that criteria for "protectability" offered by at least one Council
member (namely, the presence of brain activity) would clearly
permit research to a point well beyond the development of the
early embryo. Indeed, I do not think that the Council has been
fully willing to take up the question of the moral status of
the embryo. Nevertheless, despite the belief of some of us that
the morality of human cloning probably cannot be addressed satisfactorily
without doing so, we have agreed that the Council must examine
the morality of cloning in ways alert to the many other important
moral issues it also raises.
(d) Most of all, we have been willing to join in this report's
majority recommendation of a policy that would prohibit cloning-to-produce-children
and prohibit for four years all cloning-for-biomedical-research,
even though such a policy is not, in our view, the optimal one.
We have concurred in this recommendation in order to join with
some Council Members who, because of their moral concerns about
human cloning, endorse a moratorium for reasons somewhat different
from ours. I, for instance, specifically decline to think of
a moratorium as simply providing time to put in place regulations
after which cloning-for-biomedical-research could proceed.
For me a moratorium is good because it prohibits all human cloning
for four years and provides opportunity to continue the argument
and the research that may, one hopes, make the case against
cloning still more persuasive four years hence. Although some
of us would favor a ban on all cloning, including cloning-for-biomedical-research,
we have recognized that such a policy proposal would, in effect,
have said to fellow Council Members who, for their own different
reasons, support a moratorium: "We're not prepared to continue
this discussion." Rather than adopt such a position, we have
been willing to support a position we regard as good even if
less than optimal. As I noted above, however, this is not simply
a compromise position. On the contrary, it is a partial agreement
which may, I hope, give rise to still greater agreement in the
future.
Finally, I note the following about the moral (and not simply
the policy) aspects of the human cloning debate:
(a) A number of Council Members, of whom I am one, hold that
the human embryo is fully deserving of our moral respect and
that such respect is incompatible with its deliberate destruction
in research. That judgment about the status of the human embryo
(whether cloned or resulting from union of egg and sperm) is
not, so far as I can see, based on our religious beliefs. We
have taken seriously what the science of embryology teaches
us. We have taken seriously what careful philosophical reasoning
about the meaning of "potentiality" teaches us. We have taken
seriously the lessons of human history in which the limits of
our sympathy for fellow human beings who seem "different" from
us have more than once had to be overcome in order to learn
a more inclusive and egalitarian respect for human life. This
does not mean, for me at least, that religious belief should
play no role here. On the contrary, Jews worship a Lord who
favors the widow and the orphan, who teaches us to speak on
behalf of those no one else defends. And Christians worship
a crucified God who has himself accepted vulnerability. Instructed
by our religious traditions, we may see in the weakest and most
vulnerable of human beings those unable to speak in their
own behalf special objects of our care. Such care for
the vulnerable seems to me incompatible with an industry of
routine manufacture, use, and destruction of cloned embryos
even if the goal is to help others who are also vulnerable.
(b) The position of those who support cloning-for-biomedical-research
(while opposing cloning-to-produce-children) amounts, in effect,
to criminalizing the implantation of cloned embryos. Nothing
could be more revealing of the moral underpinnings of their
position. In their view, moral status is conferred not by belonging
to the human species but by the will and choice of some human
beings (those like us who are stronger and in control). We cannot
pretend that being unimplanted is somehow a natural fact about
an embryo; on the contrary, it is what we choose. First we produce
the cloned human embryo, then we decide to use it for our purposes
in research rather than to implant it, and then we argue that
until implanted it lacks the capacity for continued development.
This reasoning is specious, it should be rejected, and it can
find no support in the definitions given at the close of Chapter
Three of this report.
(c) Because the defense of cloning-for-biomedical-research
rests ultimately upon a view that the will and choice of some
confers moral status on others, and because no coherent defense
of the "developmental" approach to human dignity and worth has
been offered by proponents of research cloning, I think it very
unlikely that research if allowed to proceed can
really be confined to the early blastocyst. With no principled
reasons to place limits on our will, and with the likelihood
that more developed embryos or fetuses will actually be much
more useful for researchers, I doubt whether the momentum of
cloning research can be stopped in any way other than by stopping
all human cloning. Indeed, I suspect that, if cloning-for-biomedical-research
proceeds, the distinction between cloning-for-biomedical-research
and cloning-to-produce-children will come to seem artificial.
Having accustomed ourselves to use cloning techniques to shape
and mold the next generation, we will be hard-pressed to explain
why we should not, in fact, exercise an even fuller control
by cloning-to-produce-children. Our earlier opposition to it
will seem to have been merely sentimental.
I am happy, therefore, to join with other colleagues on the
Council in recommending a policy that would prohibit for at
least four years all human cloning, whether for the purpose
only of research or for the additional purpose of producing
children, but it is imperative to emphasize that this good policy
is less than optimal. We should hope that four years from now
our society will be able to do still better.
GILBERT C. MEILAENDER
* * *
Statement of Dr. Rowley
Support for Position Two
During the deliberations of the President's Council on Bioethics,
we asked many questions about the comparative usefulness of
embryonic compared with adult human stem cells to treat a host
of fatal and non-fatal but debilitating diseases. We never received
a clear answer; thus the role of stem cell treatment is largely
based on promise, rather than on persuasive evidence of efficacy.
Given the intense interest of scientists in this research problem
for at least a decade, the public can reasonably ask why we
do not have convincing data on the use of embryonic stem cells
to treat diabetes, Parkinson's disease and other medical problems?
The answer is shockingly clear! American scientists have been
prevented from working on these very critical problems because
of a ban on any federally funded research using cells from human
embryos. Progress in our understanding of human diseases and
the development of effective treatment for these diseases has
come largely from federally funded research, primarily supported
through NIH. Thus, a consequence of the present Congressional
ban (instituted in 1994 after an NIH panel established guidelines
and oversight to allow such research) has been that the only
research on the development of embryonic stem cell lines and
on the use of embryonic cells has been limited to private and
for-profit ventures. Not only are these efforts relatively small
as compared with those funded by NIH, the results are largely
hidden from the general scientific community and the benefits
are likely to be available to the public on a very restricted
basis, usually based on the ability to pay whatever price is
asked. The effect of extending and expanding this moratorium
will be to maintain our ignorance by preventing any research
for four more years; this proposal will force American scientists
who have private funding to stop their research. It will also
accelerate the scientific "brain-drain" to more enlightened
countries.
The recent publication of reports on the plasticity of human
stem cells from adult bone marrow has raised the possibility
that the problem is solved, that we do not need stem cells derived
from embryos. However, even Dr. Catherine Verfaillie (author
of one such report) emphasizes the need for research on embryonic
stem cells to complement work on adult stem cells. Will adult
stem cells have the same unlimited capacity for renewal as is
present in embryonic cells? Will embryonic and adult stem cells
both be suitable for somatic cell nuclear transfer? Will embryonic
or adult stem cells be more amenable to manipulation to reduce
the problem of immune rejection? These are just a few of the
critical questions that are urgently in need of answers
answers that NIH is prohibited from allowing American scientists
to answer.
As summarized here, it is clear that there is an urgent need
immediately to fund research on the actual potential of human
embryonic stem cells to treat human disease. However, it is
equally clear that research using cells from human embryos requires
great sensitivity and careful thought. It is thus appropriate
to accompany the lifting of the NIH ban with the simultaneous
implementation of an appropriate regulatory mechanism. It is
important to emphasize that every US academic institution has
an Institutional Review Board in place, whose function is to
review all research related to human subjects before a grant
can be submitted to any agency for funding; this ensures that
the research proposal protects the health, safety and privacy
of the individuals involved in the project. In 1998, the NIH
Director established a task force to review the policy regarding
stem cell research. This task force developed Guidelines for
Pluripotent Stem Cell Research which were approved after extensive
public comment (more than 50,000 responses) and which were published
in the Federal Registry, August 2000. The task force proposed
the establishment of The Human Embryonic Research Board. This
Board would represent a broad constituency including consumers,
ethicists, lawyers, as well as scientists knowledgeable in all
aspects of human and animal embryonic stem cell research appointed
by the Secretary of HHS. Thus there is no need to delay research
until a Board is in place because the design of the Board is
already in place.
Our ignorance is profound; the potential for important medical
advances is very great. We must remove the current impediments
to this critical research. Congress should lift the ban and
establish a broadly constituted regulatory board, NOW.
JANET D. ROWLEY
* * *
Statement of Professor Sandel
After six months of searching ethical and scientific inquiry,
a majority of this Council has rejected a ban on cloning-for-biomedical-research
of the kind passed by the House of Representatives last year.
Among those of us who reject a ban, some prefer a moratorium,
while others would permit such research to proceed subject to
regulation. (See table in Chapter Eight.)
I will first give my reasons for concluding that cloning-for-biomedical-research
should not be banned, and then explain why I believe such research
should be permitted subject to regulation.
Any ethical analysis of cloning-for-biomedical-research must
address the moral status of the human embryo. Before turning
to that question, however, it is important to place cloning-for-biomedical-research
in the broader context of embryonic stem cell research. Some
who find cloning-for-biomedical-research morally objectionable
support stem cell research that uses spare embryos left over
from fertility clinics. They argue that it is wrong to create
embryos for research (whether cloned or non-cloned) but morally
acceptable to use excess embryos created for reproduction, since
these "spare" embryos would otherwise be discarded. But this
distinction is not persuasive. If it is wrong to carry out stem
cell research on embryos created for research, it is wrong to
carry out any embryonic stem cell research.
Those who oppose the creation of embryos for stem cell research
but support research on embryos left over from in vitro fertilization
(IVF) clinics beg the question whether those IVF "spares" should
have been created in the first place: if it is immoral to create
and sacrifice embryos for the sake of curing or treating devastating
diseases, why isn't it also objectionable to create and discard
spare IVF embryos for the sake of treating infertility? After
all, both practices serve worthy ends, and curing diseases such
as Parkinson's, Alzheimer's, and diabetes is at least as important
as enabling infertile couples to have genetically related children.
Those who would distinguish the sacrifice of embryos in IVF
from the sacrifice of embryos in stem cell research might reply
as follows: the fertility doctor who creates excess embryos
does not know which embryos will ultimately be sacrificed, and
does not intend the death of any; but the scientist who deliberately
creates an embryo for stem cell research knows the embryo will
die, for to carry out the research is necessarily to destroy
the embryo.
But it is hard to see the moral difference between a practice
that typically sacrifices embryos (by the tens of thousands,
in the case of the IVF industry) and one that inevitably does
so. If IVF as currently practiced in the United States is morally
permissible, its justification does not rest on the idea that
the sacrifice it entails is only typical, not inevitable. It
rests instead on the idea that the good achieved outweighs the
loss, and that the loss is not of a kind that violates the respect
embryos are due. This is the same moral test that must be met
to justify the creation of embryos for stem cell research and
regenerative medicine.
Comparing the range of practices that sacrifice embryos clarifies
the stakes: if cloning-for-biomedical-research is morally wrong,
then so is all embryonic stem cell research, and so is any version
of IVF that creates and discards excess embryos. If, morally
speaking, these practices stand or fall together, it remains
to ask whether they stand or fall. The answer to that question
depends on the moral status of the embryo.
There are three possible ways of conceiving the moral status
of the embryo as a thing, as a person, or as something
in between. To regard an embryo as a mere thing, open to any
use we may desire or devise, misses its significance as nascent
human life. One need not regard an embryo as a full human person
in order to believe that it is due a certain respect. Personhood
is not the only warrant for respect; we consider it a failure
of respect when a thoughtless hiker carves his initials in an
ancient sequoia not because we regard the sequoia as a
person, but because we consider it a natural wonder worthy of
appreciation and awe-modes of regard inconsistent with treating
it as a billboard or defacing it for the sake of petty vanity.
To respect the old growth forest does not mean that no tree
may ever be felled or harvested for human purposes. Respecting
the forest may be consistent with using it. But the purposes
should be weighty and appropriate to the wondrous nature of
the thing.
One way to oppose a degrading, objectifying stance toward nascent
human life is to attribute full personhood to the embryo. Because
this view is associated with the religious doctrine that personhood
begins at conception, it is sometimes said to be a matter of
faith that lies beyond rational argument. But it is a mistake
to assume that religiously informed beliefs are mere dogmas,
beyond the reach of critical reflection. One way of respecting
a religious conviction is to take it seriously to probe
and explore its moral implications.
The notion that the embryo is a person carries far-reaching
consequences, some of which emerged in the course of this Council's
deliberations. One is that harvesting stem cells from a seven-day-old
blastocyst is as morally abhorrent as harvesting organs from
a baby. This is a bold and principled claim, even if deeply
at odds with most people's moral intuitions. But the implications
do not stop there. If the equal moral status view is correct,
then the penalty provided in recent anti-cloning legislation
a million dollar fine and ten years in prison is
woefully inadequate. If embryonic stem cell research is morally
equivalent to yanking organs from babies, it should be treated
as a grisly form of murder, and the scientist who performs it
should face life imprisonment or the death penalty.
A further source of difficulty for the equal moral status view
lies in the fact that, in natural pregnancies, at least half
of all embryos either fail to implant or are otherwise lost.
If natural procreation entails the loss of some number of embryos
for every successful birth, then perhaps we should worry less
about the loss of embryos that occurs in IVF and in stem cell
research. It might be replied that a high rate of infant mortality
does not justify infanticide. But the way we respond to the
natural loss of embryos suggests that we do not regard these
events as the moral or religious equivalent of infant mortality.
Otherwise, wouldn't we carry out the same burial rituals and
the same rites of mourning for the loss of an embryo that we
observe for the death of a child?
The conviction that the embryo is a person derives support
not only from certain religious doctrines but also from the
Kantian assumption that the moral universe is divided in binary
terms: everything is either a person, worthy of respect, or
a thing, open to use. But as the sequoia example suggests, this
dualism is overdrawn.
The way to combat the instrumentalizing impulse of modern technology
and commerce is not to insist on an all-or-nothing ethic of
respect for persons that consigns the rest of life to a utilitarian
calculus. Such an ethic risks turning every moral question into
a battle over the bounds of personhood. We would do better to
cultivate a more expansive appreciation of life as a gift that
commands our reverence and restricts our use. Human cloning
to create designer babies is the ultimate expression of the
hubris that marks the loss of reverence for life as a gift.
But stem cell research to cure debilitating diseases, using
seven-day-old blastocysts, cloned or uncloned, is a noble exercise
of our human ingenuity to promote healing and to play our part
in repairing the given world.
Those who warn of slippery slopes, embryo farms, and the commodification
of ova and zygotes are right to worry but wrong to assume that
cloning-for-biomedical-research necessarily opens us to these
dangers. Rather than ban stem cell cloning and other forms of
embryo research, we should allow them to proceed subject to
regulations that embody the moral restraint appropriate to the
mystery of the first stirrings of human life. Such regulations
should include licensing requirements for embryo research projects
and fertility clinics, restrictions on the commodification of
eggs and sperm, and measures to prevent proprietary interests
from monopolizing access to stem cell lines. This approach,
it seems to me, offers the best hope of avoiding the wanton
use of nascent human life and making these biomedical advances
a blessing for health rather than an episode in the erosion
of our human sensibilities.
MICHAEL J. SANDEL
* * *
Statement of Professor Wilson
Regulated Cloning-for-Biomedical-Research
I would allow regulated biomedical research on cloned embryos
provided the blastocyst is no more than fourteen days old and
would not allow implantation in a uterus, human or animal.
I take this position because I believe that research on human
blastocysts may have substantial medical value in finding ways
of improving human life. As our report indicates, such research
may help doctors deal with Parkinson's disease, Alzheimer's
disease, juvenile diabetes, and spinal cord injury. Members
of the Council disagree as to how best to do that research.
The group that favors a moratorium on the use of cloned embryos
for such research may think that the study of adult stem cells
or in vitro fertilized eggs that are not used to impregnate
a woman will produce all the knowledge we need to discover whether
stem cells have therapeutic value. The other group, of which
I am a part, favors regulated research on cloned embryos because
it believes that all sources of stem cells, including those
produced from cloned blastocysts, must be studied if we are
to discover whether great medical advances are possible. That
is because the use of cloned blastocysts may be the only important
way of overcoming the problems of immune rejection and learning
more about genetic diseases. If substantial medical benefit
can be had from research, then it is unlikely that those benefits
will derive from studying only stem cells derived from adult
tissue or from leftover IVF eggs. To follow the policy recommended
by the majority of this Council would be to do research with
one hand tied behind our backs.
Moreover, I do not think there is any moral difference between
a fertilized egg created in an in vitro fertilization clinic
and one created by cloning an embryo. Both eggs are deliberately
produced by scientific intervention and both (except for the
IVF egg used to impregnate a woman) are destroyed.
Having said that there is no moral difference between these
two sources of eggs does not mean, I believe, that using either
kind of egg does not raise important and difficult moral questions.
Every human begins as a fertilized egg, even though not every
fertilized egg becomes a human. But the issue before us is not
whether any human life should be destroyed but whether every
fertilized egg should be preserved. To oppose the willful destruction
of any fertilized egg is to oppose in vitro fertilization (since
all fertilized eggs beyond that needed for successful implantation
will be destroyed). Yet, in vitro procedures have produced (as
of 1999) about thirty thousand babies for otherwise infertile
couples. Initially, in vitro fertilizations were opposed by
many who have since changed their minds, because the great benefits
(many healthy new infants) so greatly outweighed the trivial
costs (some tiny cells frozen or destroyed).
A fertilized cell has some moral worth, but much less than
that of an implanted cell, and that has less than that of a
fetus, and that less than that of a viable fetus, and that the
same as of a newborn infant. My view is that people endow a
thing with humanity when it appears, or even begins to appear,
human; that is, when it resembles a human creature. The more
an embryo resembles a person, the more claims it exerts on our
moral feelings. Now this last argument has no religious or metaphysical
meaning, but it accords closely, in my view, with how people
view one another. It helps us understand why aborting a fetus
in the twentieth week is more frightening than doing so in the
first, and why so-called partial birth abortions are so widely
opposed. And this view helps us understand why an elderly, comatose
person lacking the ability to speak or act has more support
from people than a seven-week-old fetus that also lacks the
ability to speak or act.
Human worth grows as humanity becomes more apparent. In general,
we are profoundly grieved by the death of a newborn, deeply
distressed by the loss of a nearly born infant or a late-month
miscarriage, and (for most but not all people) worried but not
grieved by the abortion of a seven-week-old fetus. Our humanity,
and thus the moral worth we assign to people, never leaves us
even if many elements of it are later stripped away by age or
disease.
This fact becomes evident when we ask a simple question: Do
we assign the same moral blame to harvesting organs from a newborn
infant and from a seven-day-old blastocyst? The great majority
of people would be more outraged by doing the former than by
doing the latter. A seven-day-old blastocyst that is no more
than one millimeter in diameter and contains only a hundred
or so largely undifferentiated cells does not make the same
moral claims on us as does a live infant. Unless everyone who
makes this distinction is wrong, then the moral status of a
blastocyst is vastly less compelling than that of a neonate.
Some people believe that human life begins at conception and
ought to be free from any human attack from that moment on.
The difficulty with this rejoinder is that a large fraction
(perhaps one-third or one-half) of fertilized cells fail to
implant in the uterus or, if implanted, fail to develop into
an embryo. Knowing this, one who offers this rejoinder would
have to say that there is at best only a reasonable chance that
the event of conception begins a human life.
But even blastocysts and leftover IVF eggs deserve some protection,
because if society authorizes their destruction it has taken
a dramatic and morally significant step. It has intervened in
a profoundly important human process in ways that may lead future
generations to take what may then appear to be the easy next
steps, such as implanting a cloned embryo in a uterus or killing
a fetus to extract some supposedly beneficial substance.
To avoid this, I favor federal regulations that would ban implanting
a cloned embryo in any uterus, animal as well as human, and
would insist that every cloned embryo raised in a glass dish
exist for no more than fourteen days.
There is always some risk that allowing even strongly regulated
research will create conditions that lead some scientists to
ask for access to fertilized eggs beyond the blastocyst stage.
But I do not believe we can object to this by making a generalized
slippery slope argument, since virtually every medical procedure
that involves entering or affecting the human body would also
be liable to such an argument, a conclusion that would leave
us (for example) without surgery. The slippery slope argument,
stated baldly, would lead us to oppose allowing doctors to remove
an inflamed appendix because they might later decide to remove
a kidney, and after that a heart, and to oppose as well doctors
prescribing a drug that will harm 0.5 percent of its recipients
because we suspect that, once they do this, they will later
insist on prescribing drugs that harm 1 percent, and then 10
percent, and possibly 50 percent of their patients. There may
be good slippery slope arguments, but they cannot rest simply
on the phrase "slippery slope"; they must also point clearly
to a serious moral hazard and contain some reason for thinking
that this hazard will become much more likely if we take the
first step.
James Q. Wilson
|