Wyndham Washington Hotel
1400 M Street, N.W.
Washington, D.C.
COUNCIL
MEMBERS PRESENT
Leon
R. Kass, M.D., Ph.D., Chairman
American Enterprise Institute
Elizabeth Blackburn,
Ph.D.
University of California, San Francisco
Rebecca
S. Dresser, J.D.
Washington University School of Law
Daniel
W. Foster, M.D.
University of Texas, Southwestern Medical School
Francis
Fukuyama, Ph.D.
Johns Hopkins University
Michael
S. Gazzaniga, Ph.D.
Dartmouth College
Robert
P. George, D.Phil., J.D.
Princeton University
Mary
Ann Glendon, J.D., L.LM.
Harvard University
Alfonso
Gómez-Lobo, Ph.D.
Georgetown University
William
B. Hurlbut, M.D.
Stanford University
Charles
Krauthammer, M.D.
Syndicated Columnist
William
F. May, Ph.D.
Southern Methodist University
Paul McHugh,
M.D.
Johns Hopkins Hospital
Gilbert
C. Meilaender, Ph.D.
Valparaiso University
Janet
D. Rowley, M.D., D.Sc.
The University of Chicago
Michael J.
Sandel, D.Phil.
Harvard University
James
Q. Wilson, Ph.D.
University of California, Los Angeles
INDEX
- Session 1: The Meaning
of Federal Funding
- Session 2: Stem Cells: The Administration's
Funding Policy: Legal and Moral Foundations
- Session 3: Stem Cells:
Moving Research from the Bench toward the Bedside: The Role of
NIH and FDA
- Session 4: Stem Cells: Moving Research from
the Bench Toward the Bedside: The Role of Nongovernmental Activity
CHAIRMAN KASS: Welcome, Council members, to this, our 13th
meeting. Welcome also to members of the public. I will recognize the
presence of Dean Clancy, our Executive Director, in whose presence this
is a legally constituted meeting.
The Council is moving toward completing three of its major
projects, two of which are the subject of this meeting: today
monitoring stem cell research, tomorrow biotechnology and public
policy.
The four sessions today are all related to the stem cell
project, about which I would like to offer a few general remarks in
order to clarify our task and where we are going.
As everyone knows, this Council was brought into being in
connection with President Bush's August 2001 decision to permit for
the first time limited federal funding for human embryonic stem cell
research.
Although the President's charge to the Council in the
executive order that created us was very broad, he also specifically
charged us in his national address with "monitoring stem cell
research."
And monitoring is just what we have been doing for these
past 20 months. We have been watching, we have been paying attention
to, we have been gathering information about all the relevant
happenings, not only the developments in scientific research but also
the developments in ethics, law, and policy that have taken place since
August 2001 under and in relation to the current federal policy.
We have commissioned papers reviewing stem cell research
over the past two years, both embryonic and non.embryonic, discussed at
the last meeting. We have commissioned a paper on efforts to solve the
problem with immune rejection, for now a major obstacle to many
potential clinical applications of ESC research. We have commissioned
papers on recent ethical writings and discussions as well as on recent
changes in state law.
We have heard a presentation about and kept abreast of the
implementation of the federal stem cell funding policy by the NIH. And
later today we will hear more about efforts to move research from the
bench to the bedside, both through federally funded research conducted
by and administered through the NIH and eventually regulated by the FDA
and through privately funded research conducted by industry or
supported by private philanthropic organizations.
In a word, we have been trying to learn just what is
happening as a consequence of or in relation to the current national
policy in this area. By the end of today's meeting, we will have
completed this round of our monitoring and we will move toward
preparing our report provisionally titled "Monitoring Stem Cell
Research."
In this report, we will convey what we discovered by
monitoring all of these fronts as they have developed these past two
years under the present policy. We owe the President and the nation an
update on how this policy has been implemented and what is happening
beneath and around its aegis. Our report, as currently envisioned,
will include chapters reviewing the scientific findings and the ethical
discussions preceded by an explication of the policy and its moral and
legal underpinnings.
The review essays that we have commissioned will be
included in an appendix, which will also offer a primer on the human
embryo. And it is our hope to have drafts of these materials to you
soon.
To monitor events under the present funding policy, it
makes sense to begin by making sure that we understand what that policy
is. Although the matter might seem on the surface to be quite simple,
public discussions of the policy over the past two years have been
anything but clear or accurate with much understanding and not a little
misrepresentation on all sides. If we were to do nothing else,
clarification of where things stand and why legally and morally would
be a significant contribution. The two sessions this morning aim at
that goal, the first indirectly by way of discussing in general the
meaning of federal funding, the second directly by examining the policy
itself.
The controversial moral, political issue in the public stem cell
debate that was informed by other moral disagreements was about
government funding, not as in the cloning debate about a governmen-imposed
ban with criminal penalties.
In the stem cell case, the issue is about whether or not
government funds will be available for a certain area of contested
research. In the cloning case, the issue is whether research or
reproductive activities should be forbidden or criminalized.
Everyone readily understands the meaning of a criminal ban,
but the meaning of awarding or withholding government support is less
well.known. And no previous bioethics council, to my knowledge, has
ever taken up the subject thematically. To enable us to do so, we have
commissioned a paper by political theorist Professor Peter Berkowitz of
the George Mason University Law School, the Hoover Institution, and
happily part.time senior consultant to this Council, the paper on the
meaning of federal funding.
The discussion we are about to have with Peter's help
doubles as a contribution also to a richer bioethics, seeing as it
takes up certain important political, philosophical issues of morals
and politics in a liberal pluralistic society.
We welcome Peter to the meeting, thank him for his paper,
and look forward to his presentation and the subsequent discussion.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: First, thank you, Leon, for the
invitation to discuss the meaning of federal funding with this
distinguished group.
SESSION 1: THE MEANING OF FEDERAL
FUNDING
PROF. BERKOWITZ: I want to say that I come bearing good
news. This Council has taken upon itself the responsibility to
confront some of the most formidable and excruciating issues of the
day, the ethics of cloning, the meaning of enhancement, the moral
status of the embryo.
But breathe a sigh of relief. The meaning of federal
funding is not one of these excruciating issues. To be sure, the
meaning of federal funding is a subject that needs to be addressed as
part of the effort to understand the President's policy on stem
cell research, but the issues it raises by itself are relatively simple
and relatively straightforward.
What complicates matters, what excites passions is that the
decision to grant or withhold federal taxpayer dollars for some
undertaking or another is a primary means through which government in a
free society expresses enthusiasm, ambivalence, or disapproval,
particularly moral disapproval or approval.
It's silly to deny the government. I mean, a liberal
democracy makes moral judgments. It makes them all the time. In the
decision about how much money to spend on national security, in the
decision to condition federal funding to higher education on compliance
with strict standards of nondiscrimination, on the decision to fund or
not fund abortions abroad and at home, on the decision to fund or not
fund the arts and the humanities, in the decision to provide benefits
to married people that it denies to unmarried couples, in the decision
to provide young people with opportunities for public service, to
decisions about federal funding, government makes moral judgments right
and left.
Tocqueville famously said that all political questions in
America eventually become legal questions. One may add a corollary
pertaining to today's politics. When individuals do not like the
moral judgments embodied in government policy, they are prone to try
and constitutionalize their objections. But when you get right down to
it, the quarrel is usually not with the Constitution but with the
majority preferences permitted by the Constitution.
In our day, constitutional law has become politics or
policy by other means. The basic questions of federal funding are
these, how should the government approach the question of federal
funding of activities that are deemed controversial by the American
people? Is it appropriate to make such determinations on moral
grounds? Can moral grounds be avoided? Whose moral views? And which
source should govern, with what consequences for those in the majority?
Questions of this sort have been discussed frequently in
the wake of President Bush's controversial 2001 decision regarding
federal funding of embryonic stem cell research. In that decision, as
you all know, the President permitted federal funds to be used for the
first time to support research on embryonic stem cells but only those
already in existence.
At the same time, he made it clear that there would be no
federal support for any research that involved or depended on any
future destruction of human embryos. In so doing, he was upholding
both the letter and the spirit of the congressional enactment of the
Dickey amendment, which in 1996 prohibited the creation of embryos for
use in experiments or the use of embryos in research that led to their
destruction.
Most scientists and patient advocacy groups believe that
President Bush made the wrong decision and that the Dickey amendment
was a terrible mistake. Among the objections one commonly hears to the
President's policy are these three. First, by withholding federal
funding for research that involved the creation of new embryos, the
President has effectively banned embryonic stem cell research.
Second, the President's decision was wrong because he
allowed his personal moral views to govern federal policy or along the
same lines, the congressional ban was wrong because it represents the
imposition of moral reviews; even worse, religiously based moral views
to frustrate beneficial public policy.
Third, the President's policy is morally incoherent.
If an act is so moral as to deserve the government disapproval implicit
in withholding funding, it should be accompanied by efforts to prohibit
the activity altogether. But this President Bush has refrained from
doing.
Whatever the merits of the President's policy, the objections,
once examined, these common objections cannot pass muster. The
first refuses a refusal to fund with an imposition of a ban or a
prohibition. The second wrongly supposes that legislating morals
through federal budget decisions is always or in principle wrong.
And the third incorrectly assumes that government has an obligation
to bring to an end all conduct that it believes immoral. Explaining
these errors requires an exploration, a more general exploration,
of the meaning of federal funding.
So, in quick order, several basic points. First, no one
and no activity has a constitutional right to federal funding.
There's no government obligation to fund most activities, not even
the most worthy, save perhaps for such matters as the Constitution
explicitly proclaims to be the responsibility of government, national
defense, maintenance of federal courts, the holding of elections, and
so on, but even here, considering these constitutional essentials, it
is an open question to be decided by the people's representatives
of how government will choose to allocate taxpayer dollars.
The second basic point, no individual or cause has a right
to sit at the government trough. Goods are many and varied. Resources
are scarce. And scarce resources are insufficient to support all
worthy goods, all worthy activities.
People with different causes and interests compete to
obtain them. And in order to succeed, they are forced to bring their
cases to members of Congress. Funds are distributed only through the
political process within limits set by the Constitution; as a result,
this all.familiar deliberation, lobbying, deal.making, log.rolling, and
the like.
Third basic point, in a democracy, people will always have
disagreements, in a healthy democracy, I should say, about what
activities should receive government funding. Sometimes the
disagreements are intense, sometimes not. Sometimes the disagreements
include moral disagreements, sometimes not. Sometimes the political
process generates a compromise. Sometimes one or the other side
prevails decisively.
Fourth, people who lose in an effort to obtain federal
funding will always feel that they did not get what they need or want,
but in the absence of a clear legal entitlement to such funding, they
cannot properly complain that the government has thereby denied their
rights or interfered with their liberty to exercise them.
Fifth, those who lose have several alternatives built into
the democratic process. They can try to persuade their representatives
to reconsider. They can vote in others more sympathetic to their
cause. They can seek to influence public opinion or they can seek
nongovernment private funding for their activities.
All of this, as I said, is straightforward and sensible.
It suggests the legitimacy, even the routine character of the
President's policy, might be regarded as the end of the story.
Yet, many regard the withholding of support for selected
aspects of biomedical research as a special case, an exception that
demands a different approach. It is, I want to emphasize,
understandable, why stem cell research seems to be a special case.
The most important reason that the President's policy
looks like a special case is that it involves the head.on collision of
genuine goods and competing policies. The nation strongly and
overwhelmingly backs biomedical research. It is one reflection, this
devotion to biomedical research, of our respect for human life. And we
generally leave the mapping of research strategies to scientists and
those who administer the institutions in which they work.
The entire biomedical enterprise in the United States,
including also the training of the next generation of scientific
researchers, has come to rely heavily on government support. The
public generally favors this arrangement, has come to rely on
government.funded research for the treatment and for the cure of all
still.untreatable diseases, such as cancer and Alzheimer's disease.
All of this creates a strong presumption in the
public's eye in favor of funding for biomedical research.
Consequently, the decision to withhold public funds from any particular
piece of the biomedical research portfolio looks both to scientists and
to the public like an intrusion of government into a place where it
does not belong and it prompts harsh accusations the government is
engaging in censorship or even outright prohibition of medically
necessary scientific research.
To be sure, the FDA regularly imposes restrictions on
research but mainly on grounds of safety. When, however,
government's objection to research is moral in nature, it strikes
scientists as a deprivation, a restriction of freedom to inquire, a
thwarting of worthy community goals, an imposition of morals.
And it looks to those members of the public who disagree
with the decision as a failure by the government to abide by its moral
obligation, to use its resources to explore all fruitful areas of
research in search of cures for dreaded diseases.
However, those who generally make these objections forget
that their support of government funding of biomedical research is also
moral in nature. as I suggested. It springs from, it reflects our
commitment to the dignity of human life. And they forget as well that
those who oppose the destruction of embryos believe that permitting it
would involve government in a failure to abide by another moral
obligation; that is, the moral obligation to protect human life.
In other words, stem cell research involves a decision
about federal funding where powerful moral principles are at
loggerheads and the nation is deeply and passionately divided. It
poses a confrontation between our commitment, our real, genuine,
admirable commitment, to unfettered scientific inquiry and to the fight
against debilitating and deadly disease and between our respect for
human life, in this case nascent human life.
Moreover, it presents a clash between those who hold that
the moral status of the embryo is no different from that of a fully
developed human being and those who believe that the embryo is a clump
of cells, utterly devoid of moral worth.
I want to emphasize this. The challenge here is
formidable, not merely because of the sociological fact of intense
disagreement - this one cannot debate - but also for the philosophical
reason that genuine moral goods are at stake on both sides of the
question. There's genuine and intense debate in the country -
that's a sociological fact - and real moral goods and stake.
Nevertheless, controversy over federal funding of stem cell
research does not really present a special case, not in principle at
least. It looks like one because of the powerful presumption in favor
of federal funding in biomedical research, one; two, because both sides
to the debate view the moral stakes as exceedingly high; and, three,
because both sides are correct the moral stakes are high. But this
doesn't make it a special case in principle.
Typically the question of whether government will or will
not fund an activity is about more than mere distribution. It's
about shaping choices among various and competing goods or
undertakings.
The child tax credit, for example, reduces the financial
costs of child.rearing. In so doing, it strengthens family in not one
but two ways. It enables families to save money. And it conveys a
judgment, a powerful judgment, about the political importance of the
well.being of the family.
All law requires, forbids, or permits, but as a reflection
on the meeting of funding suggests, government may adopt a range of
attitudes toward that which it permits.
It strongly endorses charity and higher education. It
looks favorably on national service in the arts. It prefers marriage
to cohabitation, frowns upon smoking. It is the distinction between
permitting or tolerating an activity and actively promoting it through
governmental funding that is crucial to understanding the debate over
the President's policy on stem cell research.
Here I do want to emphasize the distinction between
permitting or tolerating an activity and promoting it through federal
funding is crucial, not only to the stem cell controversy.
The question of federal funding routinely implicates
questions about the nation's moral priorities among permissible
activities. And the question of moral priorities is not so simple as
the questions of good and bad. It is a question of better and worse.
This is true to an extraordinary degree in the stem cell
controversy. Both sides are defending moral principles. Both sides
are defending admirable moral principles. To make matters more
difficult, both sides are tending to defend these admirable principles
in their absolute form. Because moral principles are frequently at
stake in the fight for federal taxpayer dollars, decisions like the
stem cell debate can be bitter.
Truer still, when the moral principles are wielded in their
absolute form, both sides make moral claims. And one or another will
have to live with the fact that their moral principles are being
rejected, if not assaulted, by the government in their own name and
with their own taxpayer dollars.
Why should those who lose the political struggle put up
with this, what amounts to a rejection or at least the belittlement of
their moral principles? Well, the answer again here is simple,
straightforward. Living in a democracy means sometimes being in a
minority, even on questions of the utmost importance. And so long as
the laws which one opposes are consistent with the Constitution and
enacted according to legally appropriate procedures, one has an
obligation to obey them.
But is it really a legitimate aim of a liberal democracy to
adopt laws and take actions to shape the moral beliefs of its
citizens? Doesn't government in a liberal democracy have an
obligation to remain neutral toward competing conceptions of a good
life? And so we refrain from enacting morals into law.
Otherwise, doesn't it impermissibly infringe on the
people's right to choose how they ought to live? Well, to be
blunt, the answer is no. Neutrality is a chimera. It's impossible
for any government to remain neutral about morality in the nature of a
well.lived life since public policy for "What purpose is the state
permitted to classify citizens by race? What is the meaning of
marriage? What medical procedures and what biomedical research should
government fund?"; these always or almost always draw upon,
reinforce, or suppress a view about what is deserving, proper, and
good.
Of course, it's possible and desirable as a matter of
public policy in a liberal democracy to tolerate a wide variety of
choices and forms of life, but toleration itself is a moral principle
based on a certain interpretation of how to secure freedom and based on
a certain interpretation of the requirements of respecting the dignity
of the individual.
Law and public policy in a liberal democracy rightly seek
to create conditions in which citizens can make responsible and
informed choices. This is accomplished in a variety of ways. The
first and most taken for granted is through the securing of public
order, also to establishing a system of public schools, promoting
research in the sciences and humanities, supporting the arts, enacting
a wide array of social and economic legislation, and all of this, in
part, with a view toward forming a citizenry that is incapable of
taking advantage of enjoying the blessings of freedom.
Laws designed to respect and encourage respect for nascent
human life can reasonably be seen as contributing to the conditions
under which individuals learn to respect humanity in others and in
themselves.
To be sure, even within the limits provided by law,
government's encouragement of informed and responsible choice can
easily become a tool for the ill.conceived circumscribing or corrupting
of choice.
Well.meaning government efforts to prepare citizens for
liberty and toleration can undermine both. Governmental funding of
education can be, government.funded education can be dogmatic and
ideological. Government.supported arts may disseminate tawdry or
jingoistic sentiments and images. Government.funded programs directed
at the family may fail to adapt or adapt slavishly to changing times.
These familiar abuses, though, are not arguments against
government promoting the conditions that enable citizens to take
advantage of the freedom. Rather, they are reasons for proceeding with
care and with an appreciation of the complexities of contemporary moral
and political life.
American politics furnishes many examples of funding
decisions that effectively inevitably take sides on divisive moral
questions. Here are a few. Consider first the battle over abortion,
which involves a longstanding struggle over the question of government
funding for lawful constitutionally protected conduct.
Shortly after entering office, President Bush ordered the
withholding of funding from international organizations that performed
abortions. The decision was neither required of him nor forbidden to
him, but within his discretion, the principle behind this policy is
common to his position on stem cell research. Government funds should
not be used to destroy nascent human life.
At home, a line of Supreme Court decisions stretching from
1977 to 1991 dealing with abortion and government funding established
the principle that the Constitution does not require government to fund
even those activities that the Constitution singles out for special
protection.
Another example. This comes from higher education. Title
VI of the Civil Rights Act of 1964 provides that no person in the
United States shall on the ground of race, color, or national origin be
excluded from participation in, be denied the benefits of, or be
subjected to discrimination under any program or activity receiving
federal financial assistance. It is this provision that requires
private universities to avoid those racial classifications in
admissions and hiring that would violate the prohibitions imposed on
state action by the equal protection clause of the Fourteenth
Amendment.
Title VI is far.reaching because most private universities rely
heavily on government funding to support basic research. And it
provides a way for the federal government to shape the moral contours
of what is largely private conduct and bring that private conduct
in line with fundamental constitutional principles. Of course, private
colleges and universities are free to continue to practice activities
to disqualify them from federal funding. Close in form to federal
policy on stem cell research are Social Security regulations regarding
marriage and survivor benefits. Although cohabitation without matrimony
is not illegal; indeed, it's quite common, the federal government
refuses to pay Social Security survivor benefits to all but legal
spouses. This is a way for government to provide financial incentives
for marriage and for government to take sides on the good of marriage,
proclaiming the union marked by it is good for individuals and good
for the polity or, from a different angle, consider the question
of elementary level and high school education.
In 1923 in a landmark decision, Mayer v. Nebraska,
the Supreme Court ruled that parents have a right to educate their
children in a foreign language. In 1925 in another famous case, a
companion case, Pierce v. Society of Sisters, the Supreme Court
ruled that parents have a right to educate their children in private
schools.
But nobody or very few argue that these cases prohibit
states from policy decisions encouraging public education. And nobody
claims that the right of parents to privately educate their children
creates an entitlement to have that private education funded by
government.
To conclude, the controversy over stem cell should be seen as
one among many political battles over the allocation of limited
federal funds. The controversy is distinguished not by the presence
of moral principles or the presence of moral principles on both
sides but by the peculiar, by the particular, moral principles at
stake and the peculiar intensity of the compassions their defense
provokes.
When the question of federal funding is placed in
perspective, it can be seen that the common objections to the
President's policy on stem cells are misplaced. A failure to fund
is not a ban. Funding decisions typically involve a moral dimension.
And the complexities of a free society frequently create situations in
which it makes sense for government to express doubt, anxiety,
ambivalence, disapproval, or approval, and enthusiasm for a permitted
activity.
None of this, of course, is to deny that the
President's policy on stem cell research is open to criticism on
the merits. It is only to claim that this policy reflects a perfectly
appropriate exercise of governmental powers.
But what if you still think that this conclusion is
incorrect? What if you think that the President's policy does
represent still a special case and an inappropriate exercise of
governmental powers? Then it seems to me it's incumbent upon you
to craft an argument that accomplishes the following.
First, you need to distinguish the President's policy
in principle from the other cases: abortion funding, federal funding
in higher education, arts funding, subsidies for marriage, refusal to
subsidize private education, and so on.
And, second, you must articulate a more satisfactory
resolution of the contest between competing goods or, alternatively,
you must be prepared to show why the controversy over stem cell
research is anomalous in the sense that unlike all of the other
important political controversies that we face, it does not involve
competing goods on the other side of the question.
I should stop there.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Peter, thank you very much. Your paper and
formal presentation are open to discussion. Professor Sandel calls on
Professor Meilaender -
(Laughter.)
CHAIRMAN KASS: - because he wants to go second. Would you
like to lead off?
PROF. MEILAENDER: Sure. It's a very clear and useful
paper, Peter, maybe too clear. That's the problem. And I
don't disagree with the basic thrust of it.
I wonder if you would say a word about what sort of word we
should use to describe this general tendency that you have
characterized in so many cases of the circumstances in which we permit
but do not necessarily promote and avoiding in a certain sense a
substantive decision on the matter, we handle it procedurally.
Is this the best way to deal with such questions, at least
in a liberal democracy, or is it a compromise, a kind of a second best,
or I just wonder what you think on that question? Is it desirable and
good that we find ourselves in circumstances like this regularly or are
we sort of stuck and, therefore, rightly fall back? It makes a little
difference, I think, how we describe it.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Right. I think we should take some
solace. First, we should recognize that liberal democracy is itself a
compromise. If we knew somebody who knew all the answers to all the
tough questions, we could make him king or president for life and he or
she could decide matters for us.
So liberal democracy is, in part, a response to an
appreciation; in part, a response to an appreciation, that on the tough
questions we don't have access to all we need to know personally to
make the right decisions.
Second, I would say that in such a situation, the situation
that we find ourselves in as citizens in a liberal democracy, there is
a natural frustration when you feel strongly, believe strongly, believe
your arguments are compelling, and you can't get them, you
don't get them enacted into policy.
It's not surprising that when people fail to persuade a majority,
we look to other means to get our preferences and our principles
enacted. Recourse to the courts is one of the solutions both sides
adopt in different circumstances.
So I'm inclined to say that what we have here is one of
the frustrations that naturally arises in a complex free pluralistic
society. And what we have to do is learn to live with it better and
manage it better.
It is not a reflection of some kind of pathology in
American liberal democracy that an intense debate has arisen about stem
cell research, and people are bitterly divided.
I myself regard this as a sign of health in our liberal
democracy.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Gil would like to follow.
PROF. MEILAENDER: Yes. You have to wait, Michael.
So it makes perfectly good sense, then, for someone to
think that according to his lights, the best solution would be some
solution other than just the permitting but not promoting and to
continue to try to argue for and press for that while, nevertheless,
supporting these sorts of decisions in all of the different areas that
you have outlined?
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Yes. And, of course, I don't mean to
suggest that every controversial issue, every issue that becomes
controversial for us either is deeply imbued with moral significance or
is subject to resolution through statesman.like compromise.
There are familiar examples when one has no choice but to
man the barricades. And there are other debates in which it is
difficult to get overly excited, even if there is a moral dimension to
the debate.
So I am suggesting it is my own opinion that the debate
over stem cell research is one which does not involve, at least
certainly not at this stage, a need to man the barricades. And it does
involve competing moral goods on both sides of the question.
I can well imagine a policy controversy where the moral
question is remote. And I can well imagine our history furnishes
familiar examples in which the time for debate runs out. But I
don't think either of those two extreme situations represents the
situation we now find ourselves in.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Michael Sandel?
PROF. SANDEL: Well, first of all, thank you, Peter, for,
really, a thoughtful and judicious and subtle paper. I want to add
that I think the Council is fortunate to have enlisted your efforts in
its work. This paper really is enormously helpful to thinking about
this question.
What I would like to do is to bring out what I take to be
an assumption implicit in your defense of President Bush's
decision. Bringing this assumption out may also help explain why my
colleague Gil is antsy in the questions that he was asking.
You deal with three familiar objections to the
President's policy. It seems to me that your answers to those
objections are entirely correct. The first one is that withholding
funding is not the same as banning. And that's an important point
that you stress.
Secondly, there is nothing wrong with the President or
public officials embodying in federal policy moral judgments. We do
that all the time. I think that is certainly persuasive.
What I would like to focus on is the third. The third
objection is that the decision is morally incoherent for if an act is
so immoral as to deserve the federal disapproval implicit in
withholding funding, it should be accompanied by efforts to prohibit
the activity altogether.
You show that this isn't the case. And the way you
show that this isn't the case is you point out there are degrees of
moral disapproval. Their government can express doubt or anxiety or
ambivalence or outright condemnation, in which case we man the
barricades. But not every moral judgment that federal policy expresses
is of that last kind, the manning the barricades outright condemnation
kind.
So there may be some acts that are so immoral that they
should be accompanied by efforts to prohibit the activity altogether,
but there may well be a range of other acts that while we may morally
disprove of them, we don't want to encourage them, they aren't
so immoral that we should man the barricades or ban them. And we can
register that lesser moral disapproval or ambivalence or doubt in
withholding federal funding.
Now, the question, of course, is whether embryonic stem
cell research falls into the first category or the second. You have
given us some examples of activities that fall into the category of
things that are morally questionable that we, nonetheless, don't
ban, like cohabitation without matrimony.
So we don't ban it because we don't think that the
federal government needs to condemn it outright. It's not that
grave a sin. On the other hand, neither do we want to encourage it.
And so we discriminate against those who cohabit in the case of Social
Security survivor benefits. And it's a legitimate discrimination
because it registers this moral disapproval or anxiety. We want to
encourage marriage, but we're not going to go out and ban people
who live together outside of marriage.
And then there are other cases. You mentioned our
history. Slavery would be one where it would seem odd to say,
"Well, we're going to deny federal funding or tax breaks to
slave holders, but we're not going to ban it" or, to take
another hypothetical example, if there were a practice of killing
children to take their organs for transplant, that would be like
slavery, not like the marital cohabitation.
We wouldn't say we're going to deny funding for
those organ transplants because we want to register moral disapproval,
but we're not going to ban it. It would make no sense. That would
be morally incoherent to take that position in the case of the practice
of killing children for organ transplants.
So the implication of your analysis is that for the
President's position to avoid the charge of moral incoherence, it
must be more like cohabitation without marriage than like killing
children for organ transplantation.
So the President's position can be defended on a
principled basis as being morally coherent if it presupposes that the
activity in question is not morally comparable to killing children for
organ transplants but only if there is some doubt or anxiety about the
sacrifice of nascent human life.
Would you agree?
CHAIRMAN KASS: Your lawyers are ready to help you out,
too.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: I understand. I would agree, yes, that
the more one adopts the extreme position or at least the - I should say
the absolute position that there is no fundamental moral distinction
between embryos, any stages, and a human being, fully developed, grown
human being.
The President's policy becomes less coherent in the way
I have described. So in other words, the presupposition of my analysis
exactly as you have identified it is that the President's policy
supposes that the moral status of an embryo is an open and difficult
question.
In that vein, I want to remind everybody of what the
President said when he announced his decision. He said in his speech
in August of 2001, "On the first issue, are these embryos human
life? Well, one researcher told me that he believes that this
five.day.old cluster of cells is not an embryo, not yet an individual,
but a pre.embryo. He argued that it has the potential for life but it
is not a life because it cannot develop on its own. An ethicist
dismissed that as a callous attempt at rationalization. 'Make no
mistake,' he told me, 'that cluster of cells is the same way
you and I and all the rest of us started our lives. One goes with a
heavy heart if we use these,' he said, 'because we are dealing
with the seeds of the next generation.'"
So I mention this to say in theoretical point, I think you
are right. To the extent that one regards embryos as absolutely
indistinguishable, one cannot defend the President, the policy in the
way I have, but I also want to emphasize that is not the way the
President defended his policy. The President in announcing it
emphasized the difficulty of the question, what he found after
consulting for a couple of months, the intractability of the issue, the
presence of good arguments on both sides of the question and,
therefore, the need for further debate.
So while that approach may be foreclosed to some people, I
think it wasn't the presupposition, as a matter of fact, of the
administration. That is, the premise that you suggest would be
inconsistent with my third point.
CHAIRMAN KASS: There are people in the queue, but there
are also I think some who want to join on this particular question,
rather than letting it come back to it later. So if someone wants to
just on this last exchange between Michael Sandel and Peter. Robby?
PROF. GEORGE: Yes. Peter, my colleague Michael I think
assumed that the distinction that you were trying to draw or implicit
in what you were trying to draw was a distinction that turned on the
matter of degree of immorality, that it was the degree of immorality of
an act or judgments about the degree of immorality of an act that
determined where it was reasonable to come down as a matter of policy.
But there is another possibility, and it is consistent with
everything you say. Now, you can choose between them or there may be a
way to have some combination. It's certainly logically possible
and consistent with what you say to make the matter turn not on degree
of immorality but on something distinct, which is degree of confidence
in one's judgments of the immorality of the act.
One may think that a certain act may be very, very wicked
indeed, but one may have only limited confidence in one's judgment
about it. What you said a moment ago in responding to Michael was that
the President's own judgment seemed to be that this was an open and
difficult question, but one can believe that entirely consistent with
the belief that one's judgment to the extent that one has
confidence in it is a judgment that the act is indeed a very wicked
thing, in this case perhaps a judgment that the embryo is not of lesser
value, at least in respect to the right not to be killed, than more
developed human beings.
One might make the judgment from a statesman's point of
view, in part, based on one's view about the extent of reasonable
disagreement among people of good will. One thing that has to be said
I think by anybody on any side of this debate is it is a debate on
which we have very substantial disagreement among reasonable people who
are people of good will.
And there is no reason, again, in principle, why that
shouldn't factor into a statesman's judgment of the matter and,
indeed, into any particular individual and particularly a
statesman's judgment as to whether it is, in fact, an open and
difficult question. And it seems to me it ought to affect one's
judgment about the degree of confidence one can have given one's
own knowledge of one's own fallibility.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: I agree with Robby. And I take it as a
refinement of the exchange between Michael and me that one can put at
issue or what we have to take into consideration is not only the
content of the moral judgment but the degree of confidence we have
about that judgment and, moreover, the fact of how deep disagreement is
in the society. This is partly what I was gesturing at when in the
presentation I distinguished between the sociological fact of deep
disagreement in the country.
One can count up. One can count, measure, and weigh that.
One can look at the polls. People disagree strongly. That's a
fact about what is.
I distinguish that from the philosophical claim that there
are moral goods on both sides. And one might then refine that point by
saying the arguments that we have available to support our moral
judgments are less strong than we would like them to be.
And we think one day as we think through a puzzle, that
could not have presented itself to us before relatively recent
developments in science and biotechnology. As we think through it more
carefully, the arguments may become clearer to us.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Still on this point, Frank Fukuyama?
PROF. FUKUYAMA: I think there is a simpler defense, which
is just pragmatism. I mean, until the Battle of Gettysburg, Lincoln
was not willing to press for the abolition of slavery. And I believe
that he believed that it was a very serious moral wrong.
Prior to that, he was only willing to press for its
banning, banning it in its extension into the territories. And that
was based on a pragmatic judgment of what was politically possible at
the time.
And so you can believe that something is a severe wrong but
still refrain from doing things you know will not work politically.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Still on this point, Gil?
PROF. MEILAENDER: I wasn't at all antsy. I liked what
I heard and wanted to draw it out a bit. It suggests to me that
commitment to this sort of resting place isn't commitment to some
final position, but, rather, it's precisely a way of allowing an
argument to continue.
And if we forget the stem cell research thing, just think
about another of Peter's examples, the abortion case, where we do
have that whole string of court decisions, making clear that a right to
something is not an entitlement to have it funded, people on both sides
of that issue don't have to regard that as the best place for the
argument finally to end.
You are entitled to argue that it would be a good thing
that if government were, in fact, to fund it. You're entitled to
argue that it would be better were we to prohibit more abortions. But
the argument continues in a way - and this is a way we find to permit
that to happen - in a way that shows a decent amount of respect for the
competing positions involved.
That seems to me to be a good thing. It simply doesn't
mean that you, as it were, adopted a new principle. You found an
additional principle that allows democratic argument to continue. That
was my thought anyway.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I have -
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: One more point on this still.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Yes, please, Charles?
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: I just want to add one other
consideration on Michael's question about how you can have moral
compromise or policy compromise on issues where you feel, then, a deep
moral wrong is being committed.
And that is, to follow up on Frank's point, which is he
calls it pragmatism, there's also a question of settle social
practice. I mean, some people may believe that the disruption of
embryos at IVF clinics is equivalent. It's a very, very great
moral wrong.
I think you can make a reasonable argument that when you
have an already accepted social practice widely supported, you are
required to make a pragmatic political judgment about overturning that
kind of practice.
I think that also enters into stem cells and into the
compromise that the President has arrived at. It's not just a
question of the valence, the moral valence, of the activity. I think
it has to do, as Rob indicated, with a question of the confidence one
has in one's judgment, which is related to the depth of the
opposition and the respect one would have for that opposition.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Michael?
PROF. SANDEL: First, I don't think that Peter was
defending this as a compromise, nor does the other discussion paper
defend this as a political compromise. So that might be a way of
defending the decision. I thought here we were discussing whether this
could be justified as a principal decision, not just as a political
compromise. And so I was taking seriously Peter's attempt to do
this.
As for Frank's example of pragmatism in the case of
Lincoln's position on slavery, that was in the face of
Lincoln's fear that to try to ban slavery where it already existed
would bring civil war. And he was right in his judgment that it would
bring civil war.
I don't think that banning embryonic stem cell research
would run anything like that kind of risk. I mean, it's less,
rather than more contentious, than the abortion question. And so I
don't think that the stakes, the political stakes, are anything
comparable.
I think that if a president really did believe that
embryonic stem cell research were morally equivalent to killing
children for organ transplantation, that that president could perfectly
well politically and morally call for a ban on the activity.
And the fact that the President doesn't support a ban
on the activity implies, it seems to me, - and following Peter's
analysis reinforces this - that he doesn't consider it morally
equivalent to killing children for organ transplant.
And as for Robby's suggestion that it's possible,
there's a difference. Of course, Robby's right that
there's a difference between how bad you think something is and how
confident you are that it's bad. But at a certain point, that
distinction becomes difficult to sustain.
I was tempted to ask Robby, can he give me an example of
one thing that he believes, really believes, is very, very wicked, in
his phrase, and, yet, he's not sure he's right about. I think
in the case of if we really did believe, - he can offer an example
later if he wants to; I won't put him on the spot - if a president
really believed that embryonic stem cell research were morally
equivalent to killing children for organ transplantation, it seems to
me the moral thing to do would be to ban it.
CHAIRMAN KASS: But, Michael, may I suggest to my learned
colleague that there is something in between something like
cohabitation and murder and that one might not have to regard this as
the equivalent of killing a two.year.old child for transplant, to think
that it is, nevertheless, of sufficient moral gravity, quite apart from
the confidence in one's own opinion?
PROF. SANDEL: Yes. I am agreeing with that. I am saying
that the President's position presupposes some version of what we
here have been calling the special respect view of nascent human life.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: But, Michael, there's hardly a
greater social sin or offense than racial discrimination. We ban it in
just about every area that we can. But when it's practiced in a
purely private club like Augusta National, we don't say the
President, therefore, has an obligation to pass a law that bans it in a
purely private arena. We do have limits on what the state does, even
with great moral issues.
PROF. SANDEL: Even that doesn't involve murder.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Peter. Then I'm going to go to the
queue. I have Bill, Mary Ann, and I'm also there.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: I think we should avoid distinguishing
too sharply between sticking to principle and achieving a compromise.
Sometimes it's the best way to defend a principle to compromise on
its basis.
Moreover, I think we should distinguish the sense in which
the President's policy can be seen as principled and a sense in
which it can be seen as a compromise.
The principle is, as I understand it, - Yuval Levin will
speak more about this in the next session - that government money
should not be used in the creation and in the destruction of nascent
human life, but the goods in conflict have to do with the moral status
of the embryo as against scientific research.
It seems to me you can adhere to the principle which has a
relationship to these goods, the principle being no use of government,
the principle being no use of government, federal taxpayer dollars for
the destruction of human life. And the compromise, the balancing
between these goods, one's opinions about the moral status of the
embryo, and one's respect for free inquiry, and one's desire to
promote free inquiry.
And, again, just to pick up on something that Robby and
Frank said in different ways, every compromise is not a tarnishing of
principle. Some compromises are the best kind of defense in the
principle in the social and political circumstances.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Bill May?
DR. MAY: A comment about your last paragraph. None of
this is to deny that the President's and stem cell research is open
to criticism on the merits. It is only to claim that this policy
reflects a perfectly appropriate exercise of governmental powers.
A word about your choice of phrase in the last sentence.
To say "perfectly appropriate" kind of moves in the direction
of having almost dealt with the merits of the case. Why not simply
"constitutionally permissible," leaving room for stating
there are other constitutionally permissible exercises of government
powers?
And you don't deal with the question of the merits of
the case. Maybe as a professor of law, you feel you are not obliged to
think about that. But do you have any comments to make about the
merits of the case, particularly since you have left that undiscussed,
the impacts of a practical surrender to the marketplace and the whole
question of regulation of the marketplace?
PROF. BERKOWITZ: First, I should say if you were my
editor, I would not man the barricades on the question of whether
"perfectly" should modify "appropriate." I would
fight different battles but not that one. "Perfect" can go.
But what I meant to emphasize, though, was appropriate in
the sense of its formality. What I wanted to say was from the merits.
DR. MAY: And, therefore, permissible.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: And, therefore, permissible. As far as
the policy, as far as the merits of it go, - and this harkens a bit to
what Michael Sandel was saying - surely on the merits of the case, to
the extent that in looking upon an embryo, you can see nothing of moral
worth. You will find the President's policy extremely
objectionable. I can understand that.
I myself am torn about the issue. And so I regard it as a
salutary compromise on the merits. But I am not an expert on matters.
I haven't come here to discuss that.
But it is I imagine implicit in my paper in the way I bring
it out that I actually do think this is an issue in which there are
serious and profound arguments on both sides of the question, as the
President said in August of 2001.
CHAIRMAN KASS: To this or do you want to get in the
queue? Okay. Mary Ann?
PROF. GLENDON: I want to join the chorus of people who
thought this was a wonderful paper and very helpful to us. If I were
your editor, on page 5, the last paragraph, I would want to submit for
your consideration where say, "our liberal democracy," the
words "one version of liberal democracy."
I don't make that suggestion in a nitpicking way at all
but, rather, because it seems to me the goods in conflict that we are
discussing, the hard questions that you have identified do, in fact,
involve another hard question that your definition of liberal democracy
sort of glosses over.
And that is what kind of liberal democracy are we, a
subject that Michael Sandel has written about a great deal. Michael
will say whether I am right, but, Michael, I don't think you would
agree with the statement that our liberal democracy privileges the
autonomous or freely choosing life.
As I understand Michael Sandel's writings on this
subject, there is an ongoing tension in the United States between the
version of liberalism that does privilege autonomy and free choice of
individual understood in a certain way and another version of liberal
democracy that I think I understand you to favor that is more complex
and gets into questions that are intimately related with the stem cell
debate, such as what do we mean by an individual. Do we think of an
individual as really radically autonomous or do we think of an
individual as constituted, in part, by relations with others and then
the other range of questions about present and future?
So I would have expected - this really is maybe a question
more directed to my colleague Michael than to Peter. I would expect
Michael Sandel to support the President's policy on the basis of
Michael's understanding of a rich and complex liberalism that has
to attend to preserving the conditions for its own survival.
PROF. GEORGE: What should Michael say to that?
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Michael should say sort of. We both
should be so lucky to have you as an editor. I hope you will not
regard this as mealymouthed, but, just as I wanted to suggest we
shouldn't draw too sharp a distinction between decisions based on
principle and compromise, my own view is that we should not draw too
sharp a distinction between the liberal democracy that celebrates or
privileges the autonomous individual and the strands of our political
tradition that Michael has written at length about and educated us
about.
My own view is that one discovers in our country - and, by
the way, I take this to be consistent with Michael's view, although
I may not put it in a way that he finds congenial - I take it that our
country is, in large measure, constituted by this running debate over
the meaning of freedom. But freedom and individual freedom, how much
attention to put to the individual as self.reliant, how much attention
to give, how much weight to give to the individual as he or she
flourishes, grows up and flourishes in family, neighborhood, house of
worship, state, and the various communities that constitute us.
Again, what that is is a debate about the meaning of
freedom. It is not a debate about something else. So the larger point
is, once again, the thinking in terms of public policy's role in
securing the conditions for the enjoyment of freedom is not an
alternative to taking into account considerations of attachment,
community, to borrow one of Michael's phrases, duties we don't
give ourselves but are given to us and to which we are born. It is not
an alternative to that. That is part of the larger ambition and larger
public policy struggle.
What are the conditions that promote and enhance individual
freedom?
CHAIRMAN KASS: Mary Ann, follow-up?
PROF. GLENDON: Yes. Well, I would just like to clarify
that what I was suggesting is that the President's decision
involved, among other things, a position in that ongoing debate about
what kind of society we are bringing into being.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you.
I have myself next, Peter. The details of the
President's policy will be part of the discussion really more in
the second session. So let me try to formulate this in more general
terms.
Actually, the staff working paper for the second session also
has some discussion of federal funding and its meaning. And it
makes an argument that you haven't made or at least if you have
made it, I haven't heard it. I heard it emphasized. And that
has something to do with the fact that a decision to fund is not
just a financial encouragement, but it is also an expression of
the seal of governmental approval and that one might say that the
existence of this intense debate as regarding the moral meaning
of embryonic destruction in the service of medical good is something
on which the very fact that the nation is divided might be an argument
for withholding official national approval.
And a person might, in fact, think that the embryo might
not be worth very much but, nevertheless, say, "I understand that
lots of my fellow citizens think otherwise." And it would somehow
be a mistake for a polity on a question so hotly contested for my side
to prevail if prevailing means the national approval.
I quote two sentences, "While embryo destruction may
be something that some Americans support and engage in, it is not
something that America as a nation has officially supported or engaged
in. And one has in the background the congressional legislation, which
is, in fact, the constraint here."
So the question, I guess, to generalize it, not to add to
the polity, couldn't one make an argument that because federal
funding is an expression of national approval, there might be grounds
for arguing that that approval should be withheld, even if you are on
the side that would benefit from the award of funds? That would be
question one.
Let me just add the second. I think I would add a kind of
small asterisk to the way you formulated the controversy. This is now
into the substance, where you say that you have got a genuine moral
goods at stake, powerful principles at loggerheads, and defended in
absolute terms.
Well, as a description of the way the debate has gone, I
think that is true, but there is a certain complication in that if this
is simply a matter of moral goods at stake, those sorts of things tend
to be handled by compromise.
But what do you do if the contest is between what might be
called right and good; in other words, where on one side, you have a
principle that something should never be done because it is a moral
evil and, on the other side, you have something that this is good to be
preserved but that it is not the same kind of moral imperative.
We had this discussion last time about what kind of an
imperative research is. In other words, does the fact that we are
dealing here with an issue that isn't like the usual funding
questions, where there are competing goods simply but where one side at
least claims to uphold some kind of absolute moral principle, which
they're not only defending in absolute terms but they regard as a
moral absolute; whereas, while others might defend it in absolute
terms, it's very hard to say that the case for doing medical
research has the same kind of moral absolute status.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Difficult questions. First, on let's
call it the moral meaning of division in the country, here I do want to
go back to something I did say in the presentation. It seems to me
that in characterizing the division in the country, one does have to
distinguish the fact of division from the reasons that people give in
support of their opinions.
So in my view, it's very important in stem cell debate
that when I read the arguments that are put forward on both sides, I
find what I regard as serious moral arguments on both sides.
The fact of division in the country would have less weight
if one side were clearly right and one side were clearly wrong. It
could still have pragmatic weight. Law is still designed and crafted
and implemented and adjudicated for real people to live under. You
can't have laws under which people cannot live.
But these two features of the debate are very important,
what I call the sociological fact of it and the philosophical features
of it. There are good reasons on both sides.
Second, as far as your suggestion that there is a kind of
asymmetry in the debate, where there is a good on one side, a good we
all affirm, scientific research, free inquiry, and an absolute
principle on the other side, actually, I don't quite see it that
way.
Again, referring to the President's August 2001, the
principle is actually, as I see it, embodied in the policy. It's
not an absolute principle. The principle, it may actually be
something the President holds, people on this Council hold, people in
the country hold, but one certainly could defend it in these terms.
The principle is that we don't use government taxpayer dollars to
destroy nascent human life.
One need not subscribe to that principle based upon the
absolute, inalterable, extraordinarily confident opinion that a
two.week.old embryo is of the same moral status and dignity as a fully
developed human being.
One may adhere to that principle because one is still
uncertain. One believes that the embryo is different from clumps,
different from collections of cells, but because it's a kind of new
problem, we didn't have access. We could not manipulate
two.week.old cells.
So there is a way at least of seeing the debate as not
quite as imbalanced as you put it, although I wouldn't deny that
some people do view it as you suggest.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I wasn't speaking about the President's
decision. I should make the more general point. What happens if
you've got a contest, not between things that people acknowledge
as competing goods simply but in which at least the key partisans
in the debate - and I am thinking more about Congress - regard this
as a contest between the right and the good, between something which
would be a right or a wrong in more absolute terms and an optional
good, however powerful optional good or is this just the sort of
thing that you see in the rough and tumble of politics and it gets
worked out in the usual way?
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Well, I wouldn't quite put it only
that way. I do not see a philosophy or a moral philosophy providing us
a formula or algorithm for figuring out what happens when a right
clashes with a good.
But I like the phrase "rough and tumble of
politics." And I would like to apply it also to moral and
political philosophy. The clash between the right and the good in this
case involves the rough and tumble of thinking, thinking rigorously
about the problem and figuring out the kinds of the moral weights we
attach in this case to the right and the good.
There's a rough and tumble of serious thought, too,
but, again, I haven't gotten and I don't believe there is an
algorithm or formula that tells you what to do when an important right
clashes with a good.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you.
Rebecca, Rebecca Dresser?
PROF. DRESSER: A suggestion and a question. If you would
like to flesh this out more, you might want to follow up on the fetal
tissue transplant research history because there was a similar
acrimonious longstanding debate over federal funding. And then
eventually the Congress got into it and established a policy. And then
a new administration came in. So it might be a nice way to illustrate
some of the points you are making.
The question I had was, had you thought about - and maybe I
am just being a law professor and being procedural - principles for
responding to situations like this? How should we deliberate when
there is controversy over funding policy? How should the different
sides engage each other?
It seems to me that some of the animosity around stem
cells, the stem cell funding debate, is related to how the debate is
being conducted. And it's generating perhaps unnecessary
animosity.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Well, first, thank you for the
suggestion, and I'll have a look.
And, second, once again, just as I didn't have an algorithm
or formula, I am afraid I haven't gotten principles ready at
hand. But I can say this. Just as hard cases make bad law, I would
be reluctant to generalize overly much from this particular controversy,
again, not because I think that in formal structure, it represents
something anomalous but because I think in content, it represents
an issue that is very difficult, goods or right and the good, serious
ones on both sides of the question, excites high passions.
And the kind of problem that history and the history of
moral and political philosophy doesn't help us as much as it does
in other areas because the amazing advance of science has enabled us to
do something that we couldn't do before. Actually, we have created
a moral problem for ourselves.
So I am inclined to say that as far as my limited
imagination will take me, that this was not a bad idea to deal with.
The Council on Bioethics was not a bad idea to deal with this vexing
moral question. Congress passed a law. The President conferred.
His speech suggested that he had not come to a firm
resolution. It suggested that the reason that he had not come to a
firm resolution was because he was confronting extremely difficult
issues on which the country was divided and on which the country was
divided for good reasons.
And one response to that is to gather a diverse and
distinguished group of people to engage in both the rough and tumble of
politics and the rough and tumble of serious inquiry and conversation.
I fear that's not very satisfying, but I say without too much fear
that I think it is the best we can do.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Elizabeth? Elizabeth Blackburn?
PROF. BLACKBURN: Well, I wanted to address the issue of
the consequences of when federal funding is not granted. And you say
to go chapter and verse, page 8. Of course, private institutions are
free to continue to practice activities that disqualify them from
federal funding. All they have to do is refuse to take federal funds.
I think what I didn't get from the chapter, which would
have been nice, - it was very clarifying in many ways - in different
contexts, the consequence of not granting funding is so very different
and, as somebody rightly pointed out, people can cohabitate and refuse
and they don't have federal funding and that doesn't prevent a
common practice, for example. But in the case of this particular
activity, because of its nature, not granting federal funding is very
effectively a ban.
And you could say, "Oh, wait a minute. This could be
done in the private sector." But I think that is to misunderstand
the nature of basic biomedical research at the stage before it is
really commercially viable in a realistic sort of fashion.
And so I think that because this, in effect, was a ban on
such research taking place in ways that are known to be the way that
scientific research can proceed best with the proper peer review and
proper open exchange of public information and publicly funded
information and all of those things that are held to be the right way
to do biomedical research, then it has a somewhat different effect from
what you rather lightheartedly talked about at the end of this
paragraph on page 8. Of course, they can just refuse to do it.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Right.
PROF. BLACKBURN: And I think that is a distinction we
should really face up to -
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Yes.
PROF. BLACKBURN: - because you are technically right, of
course, that, in effect, it didn't work out that way.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: There are others who are much more able
than I am to speak to the consequences. In fact, I understand that the
next session will be, in part, devoted to that issue. So I both
don't want to encroach and, even if I wanted to, couldn't very
effectively.
So I will just make one or two small points. Supposing you
are right. An effective ban is still different from an actual ban.
And, second, - and I don't mean for a moment to underestimate,
although I understand it is a subject also of intense debate and
controversy, what actually are the effects on scientific research of
the ban on creating embryos today or creating stem cell lines from
existing embryos. I understand that that, too, is a subject of debate.
There is - and this is the sense in which I address this
question in the presentation - a ready.at.hand expedient for scientists
and for those in the public who think that the President's policy
is wrong and should be changed. It's the democratic expedient.
It's to gather a majority of fellow citizens and persuade your
congressman.
So in that sense, it's, once again, the sort of thing
that happens in a liberal democracy, our liberal democracy, which gives
fairly wide latitude, fairly wide latitude, to majorities. And no
doubt on some individuals, especially individuals whose livelihood is
devoted to such research, this policy falls with a special heaviness.
PROF. BLACKBURN: Nobody has devoted their life to this
research yet because -
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Those who wish to.
CHAIRMAN KASS: The record really should show, Elizabeth,
that this is not a ban. In fact, this was the first awarding of
federal funds.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Yes.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I mean, let's be clear about that. And
we will this afternoon from Dr. Zerhouni about research that goes
forward now for the first time with federal support.
Whether it is sufficient encouragement for the field, to
take off is another matter, but it would be simply a mistake to let the
record say that -
PROF. BLACKBURN: Right. I think my point was that
technically this is all correct, but I think it is worth pointing out
that how it works is so very context.dependent, how not granting
federal funding is extremely context.dependent.
And in one case, there is a ready recourse to the private
sector. In other cases, there aren't.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Even though I am aware that there is a
debate, even among scientists, about the promise of stem cell research,
nothing I said should be understood as suggesting that the
President's policy is not a significant obstacle to conducting
scientific inquiry.
What I meant to say is that it struck me as both a
constitutional and reasonable obstacle.
CHAIRMAN KASS: We are near the break. Robby, are you in
the queue? You are?
PROF. GEORGE: Yes, but if there's anybody who
hasn't spoken yet -
CHAIRMAN KASS: The only two I have left are you and
Michael. So if we can make it brief?
PROF. GEORGE: Michael, would you? Well, you might get
back to Michael quickly here.
Peter, I'm curious about your own view. Do you think
that we know enough based on what the President himself has said and
the content of the position that he adopted and put in place? Do we
know enough to be able to say whether the President's position
logically entails either of the two competing views of the moral status
of the embryo that are on the table here, either what Michael calls the
special respect view or what might be called the full moral respect
view?
PROF. BERKOWITZ: As it was put on the table in August
2001, I certainly don't think it entails the - how did you describe
the latter, the full -
PROF. GEORGE: The full moral respect.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: The full moral respect.
PROF. GEORGE: Well, I don't either.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: It certainly doesn't entail.
It's obviously not - well, I shouldn't say "obviously
not." I don't believe it's inconsistent with that view.
PROF. GEORGE: So it doesn't entail either. If
it's not inconsistent with the first view, then it can't entail
-
PROF. BERKOWITZ: I'm sorry. I meant that it's not
inconsistent with the full moral respect view.
PROF. GEORGE: Right. But if you believe that, then you
also must believe that it doesn't logically entail the special
respect.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: I suppose it could still. It could have
flowed if we're speaking strictly logically here. It could have
flowed from a genuine uncertainty, confronting both arguments and
saying, you know, "Special moral respect, to what extent and what
quality, sounds like there's something to it. I'm not sure.
Scientific research should proceed, nevertheless. Not sure. Let's
inquire and let's for the time being adhere to the principle that
the federal government doesn't support the destruction of nascent
human life" because one could give a perfectly respectful argument
that it has to those of you who spend your lives doing such things, it
will have echoes of Kant.
But it's also essential to respecting your fellow human
being in a liberal society could believe that this principle, no
federal taxpayer dollars, is necessary to creating a society in which
individuals respect humanity in themselves and others.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Michael?
PROF. SANDEL: I just wanted to reiterate my agreement with
Peter's analysis and the way in which it highlights this important
implication, which is that the President's position of denying
funding but not banning can be saved from the charge of moral
incoherence but only if you assume that he is agnostic or unsure about
the moral status of the embryo or if he accepts an intermediate view of
the embryo, that it's not merely a clump of cells but neither is it
morally equivalent of a fully developed human being because if a person
held that view, if embryonic stem cell research were a merger or
infanticide for the sake of saving other people, then there would be no
good principled reason not to ban it short of averting civil war if
civil war were really the consequence.
But since the President didn't ban it, then either he
must be unsure about who is right in the debate about the embryo or he
must hold some version of the intermediate view.
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Well, I need to say there is one other
possibility, which is the President could have concluded that the
attempt to implement what Robby George calls the fuller view would be
impossible or have destructive consequences.
And so one morally could conclude, it seems to me, that it
is both saner and wiser to attempt to implement the principle and to
refrain from implementing the principle in its maximal and absolute
form.
PROF. SANDEL: That would be like Frank's civil war
worked, -
PROF. BERKOWITZ: Yes, that's right.
PROF. SANDEL: - Lincoln's Civil War. Something like
the civil war will loom if you try to ban the infanticide.
DR. FOSTER: Can I say one sentence?
CHAIRMAN KASS: Dan Foster, please?
DR. FOSTER: One sentence. If my memory has not failed me,
at the time the President met with this Council at its initiation, he
seemed to make clear his interest in finding out more about embryonic
stem cells with a clear conclusion on my part that he was in the
position that has been articulated here this morning of not being
certain about what to do.
Unless my memory completely fails me, that was a major
thrust of the meeting that day.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Yes. Very briefly, Bill, because we're
going to break. Briefly.
DR. HURLBUT: Michael, I just want to understand what you
are saying. When the President issued his statement in August, he was
speaking about federal funding. And he was upholding the Dickey
amendment, right, the Dickey clause, whatever you call that.
And so he wasn't even addressing the question of a
total ban on anything. He was addressing the issue of federal
funding. Isn't this right? So why would we conclude from that one
way or another about his larger position?
CHAIRMAN KASS: It would have been my question, too. I
mean, you misframed I think the situation. There is a law on the
books. The question is, is there a legal loophole against the spirit
of the law but within the letter?
And that was a loaded question. You can say you can fault
them for not at the very same time calling for a congressional ban on
all embryo research, but that was not the question at issue.
PROF. SANDEL: Why would you look for a legal loophole in a
law that banned infanticide if you really considered infanticide an
evil?
CHAIRMAN KASS: I'm saying he wasn't looking for a
legal loophole. It was -
PROF. SANDEL: Sorry. I was just using the phrase that you
had.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I think this will come up in the next. The
way the question is formulated is I think terribly important.
Let's thank Peter very much for a very clear and lucid
paper and for discussion.
(Applause.)
CHAIRMAN KASS: We are not very late, 15 minutes. We will
convene at ten minutes of the hour.
(Whereupon, the foregoing matter went off the record at 10:38
a.m. and went back on the record at 10:57 a.m.)
SESSION 2: STEM CELLS: THE ADMINISTRATION'S
FUNDING POLICY: LEGAL AND MORAL FOUNDATIONS
CHAIRMAN KASS: All right. We move from the general
question of the meaning of federal funding, to a session entitled
"Stem Cells: The Administration's Funding Policy: Legal and
Moral Foundations." The basis for the discussion is a very fine
and lucid Staff Working Paper on the topic, one which, if I might be
allowed a personal rather than official opinion, is the clearest and
best explication of this matter that I, at least, have seen anywhere.
The paper provides a brief background history of the embryo
funding debate, leading up to the Dickey Amendment, and the different
approaches taken by the Clinton and Bush Administrations in executing
that law, that law still setting the background for all of the
discussions that follow.
The Staff Working Paper then explicates the present funding
policy, and clearly articulates the moral legs on which it rests.
Among its most important contribution, in my view, this part of the
working paper points out that the President's policy rests, at
least in part, on moral principle, not a political compromise or a cost
benefit calculation, and draws from this fact the following
conclusion. And I'm reading from page 7 of the Staff Working
Paper. Well, let me read the whole paragraph.
"This character of the decision, namely, that it's
been based on moral principle, has been overlooked by both its
opponents and by many of its defenders. As a result, the debate has
tended to focus on the precise balance of benefits and harms resulting
from the combination of the Administration's policy and the state
of the relevant science. It is focused on whether there are enough
cell lines, or whether the science is advancing as quickly as it could,
and has proceeded as though this Administration sought simply the same
end as the previous one; that is, to allow for maximal progress in
embryonic stem cell research within the limit of the law.
Had the decision been based on that desire, then claims or
evidence of slowed progress alone might constitute an argument against
it in its own terms. But since the decision was grounded firmly in a
clearly discernible, if controversial principle, it does not appear
simply to be overturnable on its face by a shift in the ratio of harms
and benefits. Judgments made in matters of calculation and weighing of
competing goods and bads are, of course, altered decisively by the
changing weights of what is placed on the scales. But judgments made
as matters of principle of right versus wrong, rather than better
versus worse, can only be altered on the level of principle.
To argue with the President's decision on its own terms, one would
need to argue with its moral and political premises; namely, its
view that a human embryo ought not to be violated. Its view, therefore,
this is indeed a matter of principle rather than a balancing, and
its assessment of the significance of government funding of the
contested activity. All of these are, of course, appropriate subjects
for public debate." Finally, the Working Paper also treats the issue of federal funding
and its significance, the topic of our last session, and offers
its own take on what kind of a decision, the decision to withhold
or offer federal funding, really is. I think it's perfectly
compatible with Peter's paper, though there are some interesting
different nuances.
The paper is now open for discussion, and let me suggest
that we begin with questions of clarification, or questions that go to
the accuracy of the explication offered in the Working Paper. Once
again, before we move into an argument about the issues, we should try
to be clear and reach agreement on what it is that we're arguing
about. So if we could begin with those kinds of questions and
comments, and then we can move to a more substantive discussion.
I should say, this paper is largely the work of Yuval
Levin, who's had critical comments from others, but it's his
very fine handy work, and if I get stuck in any places, I will feel it
appropriate to call on him for assistance. Robby George.
PROF. GEORGE: Would it be possible for you or Yuval to
give us a little more detail about the change in policy toward the end
of the Clinton Administration, and when the Bush Administration took
over. There's a nice short summary of that in the paper, but I
wonder if there's more detail that could be given.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Let me try. I'm not sure that this is
much more than what's here, but the language of the Dickey
Amendment says "no federal funds may be used for the creation of a
human embryo or embryos for research purposes, or research in which a
human embryo or embryos are destroyed, discarded, or knowingly
subjected to risk of injury, et cetera."
Reading strictly according to the letter, and reading, I
think, in the spirit of what the paper identifies correctly as the
basic sort of thrust of the Clinton Administration's view of the
matter, the political question there was how can embryonic stem cell
research be maximally aided within the limits of this law as written?
Well, the law as written says you can't fund research
in which the embryos - an embryo or embryos are destroyed, discarded or
subjected to risk, but it doesn't say that you may not fund
research on cells derived from prior destruction. So the argument
would be if the stem cells were - stem cell lines were derived from
embryos destroyed not with federal funds, and no further embryo
destruction is now entailed in the further use of those cells, then
those cells could be - research on those cells could be funded without
violation of the Dickey Amendment. That was the reading of the law by
Council within HHS in the latter part of the Clinton Administration.
Rebecca, am I so far okay?
PROF. DRESSER: Yes. I was just wondering if Robby was
interested in the proposed guidelines that NIH was going to adopt with
Secretary Shalala.
PROF. GEORGE: Yes, Rebecca, I was. That's what I was
interested in learning more about, because it was the - where it
wasn't - what wasn't clear to me from the paper is what
happened as far as implementation once the administration had decided
upon this reading. I know at the end it was kind of left hanging
because there was a change of administrations, but how far did things
go?
PROF. DRESSER: Well, this is my recollection. The NIH put
together a committee which proposed guidelines for federal funding.
And I believe they went through a comment process, and then I think
they were formally published in the Federal Register, but they
hadn't taken effect before the election. And they did have some
substantive provisions; such as - one which I think is of interest here
is that no funding for stem cells from embryos created through
cloning. And they did have some other limitations, so it might be
helpful to include some of the substance of them in this document.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you. Janet.
DR. ROWLEY: Yeah, because Shirley Tilghman was the Chairman
of that committee, and they met for quite some time before the recommendations
were made. And they were subject to federal comment. And it's
my impression that the members of that review board, which would
review all of the research proposed to be done under this new permitted
research was going to be reviewed by a committee that would be housed
at NIH, just like the RAC is. But it was so close to the election
that, in fact, that review committee never met.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Well, I think it would be important for us
to get that information and make it part of the historical background
of this chapter.
Rebecca, please continue.
PROF. DRESSER: I had another question just about the term
"loophole". Is that something that was intentionally used,
and do we really want to use it? Let's see. I think it was on the
top of page 4, about the middle of the first full paragraph. And
it's been referred to earlier in this discussion as a loophole. I
mean, it seems a pejorative term. Perhaps an exception in the area
where the application did not - I don't - I'm just throwing it
out for discussion.
PROF. SANDEL: A lacuna.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Yeah, it will be altered. I think it's
certainly fair to say that it was an attempt to use the statutory - to
find openings in the statutory language that would permit activity
against the spirit of the law itself. I think that's not
controversial, but I don't think we will strike anything that
suggests that there's something improper about that.
PROF. DRESSER: Well, I mean if it is a loophole, it's
a loophole that the current policy also, to some extent, rests on.
Isn't that correct? Because the current policy is a way of funding
stem cell research consistently with the Dickey Amendment.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Well taken. Jim Wilson.
PROF. WILSON: I think the text suggests for reasons it
does not make explicit, and I emphasize the word "suggest",
there was a difference in motivation between the Clinton and Bush
Administrations, but it doesn't make explicit what the text
suggests. And as Rebecca just pointed out, however we may characterize
Mr. Clinton's personal motives or Mr. Bush's personal motives,
that the present policy is consistent with prior policy in the Clinton
Administration; that is to say, a private funding led to the
destruction of an embryo. Then the cells from that embryo could be
analyzed using federal funds. And is there a difference? And if so,
it should be made explicit.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Does someone want to comment on this? Gil
Meilaender.
PROF. MEILAENDER: Well, I think there is this difference,
that the policy in place now in the Bush Administration does not reckon
with the possibility that newly derived embryonic stem cell lines could
become the subject of research; that is to say, the derivation/use
distinction doesn't continue indefinitely. Whereas, presumably
with the policy of the previous administration, it could have - there
could have been an indefinite number of stem cell lines derived without
federal funding, but then the use of federal funds to do research with
them. And in that sense, there's a clear distinction.
PROF. ROWLEY: But I think that's a point of specific
information, that as we get more details about what the precise
language was of the committee that Shirley Tilghman was chair of,
we'll see whether, in fact, what you just said is correct or
not.
PROF. MEILAENDER: I'm perfectly happy to have us see
that.
PROF. BLACKBURN: Just a clarification. I thought it said
at the end of that first full paragraph on page 4, it said,
"Because such research would require no new embryo
destruction", it seems as if the previous administration's did
have that provision in it.
PROF. WILSON: That's exactly what I'm trying to
clarify. That phrase put me off. It was my understanding from my
memory of the time, quite shaky at best, that it would have allowed
continued destruction of embryos by private funding. If that's the
case, then this sentence is in error. That's what I wanted to have
clarified. Yes.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: I think it might be just amended to
read, "Because such research would require no new embryo
destruction by federally supported research", and that would cure
the problem.
PROF. BLACKBURN: It needs to be clarified what it was.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Someone was in the queue. Mike, why
don't you just - Mike Gazzaniga.
DR. GAZZANIGA: Well, just a point of clarification. The
principle that you're referring to that must be changed in order
for the President to change his position; namely, that the human embryo
ought not to be violated, I was wondering if Michael Sandel would
comment on that, given his argument this morning. Does this argument
force upon him a - force upon us a different way the President should
have stated his principle?
CHAIRMAN KASS: Do you want a clarification of the question
that's put to you?
PROF. SANDEL: I didn't quite catch the first part.
DR. GAZZANIGA: Well, just the discussion we had this
morning about, in order for the policy of his to be morally coherent,
there had to be this assumption of the fact that he was not yet decided
on the moral status of the embryo. That seems to me, if that is true,
if that argument is valid, then the principle that you're referring
to in the paragraph you just read should be amended.
PROF. SANDEL: Well, we're going to, I assume, get into
this. It seems to me that the whole issue here rests on the complicity
issue, what is complicity, and in what kind of moral evil is there
complicity if you use the fruits of the morally evil act for good
ends? And then the question is, well, just how morally evil can the
act be for you to use the fruits of it, and not be morally complicit in
the wrong? But I think the issue of complicity is, that's the
heart of the moral position here. And we need to get into that, but I
don't know that -
CHAIRMAN KASS: Let's hold that - I'm sorry.
PROF. SANDEL: But I think we're going to come to that,
I assume.
CHAIRMAN KASS: We will come to that. Let's see if
there's still questions of clarification. Jim Wilson, sorry.
PROF. WILSON: On page 5, there is an effort to distinguish
the Clinton position from the Bush position. And we assert President
Clinton, like many Americans, did not believe that the destruction of
an in vitro human embryo is inherently or necessarily a moral evil.
And in the next paragraph, President Bush had a very different
question in mind. Like many Americans, he does believe that these are
- these are statements. It would be better if they were quotations of
the Presidents so we'd know what, in fact, they said, if they said
anything.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Point taken. Janet.
DR. ROWLEY: Because to follow on, but skip to the
conclusions under number 2, the conviction held by the President that
nascent moral human life should be deemed inviolable, and we spent the
earlier part of today saying that in fact we - it was our impression
that he hadn't come to a decision on that.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Yeah, I'm not - by the way, Jim
Wilson's counsel is, of course, as it often is wise, and if we
attribute opinions to various people, we should find the text.
I don't think, by the way, that - and I think we can
find it. I don't think that the argument that agnosticism - the
argument that the President is agnostic on the question can be settled
by the quotation that Peter gave from the fact that he heard two
different opinions, and cited those opinions in the Address of August,
2001. And he has, on other occasions, said things that are very much
like this in public speeches, but we will find - we will get the
evidence. Rebecca.
PROF. DRESSER: A question of clarification, that this
first paragraph at the top of page 5, the very last sentence. I
wondered if that should say "nascent human life ought not be
violated for research", because, I mean, that seemed rather
broad. And if I remember correctly, isn't there federal funding
available for abortion under certain circumstances? Say if the
mother's life is in danger, so that seemed rather absolute.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Point taken. Robby George.
PROF. GEORGE: Leon, a bit more if you know more, back to
my original question, about the source of the cell lines funding on
which was authorized by the President in his August 9th, 2001 Address.
Do we know the circumstances under which those cell lines were
created? Presumably, they were created - the destruction of the
embryos to generate the cells to begin the lines was privately funded.
Is that right?
CHAIRMAN KASS: That's my understanding, yes. All
those lines were checked out under Whitehouse direction, but by people
at the NIH.
PROF. GEORGE: And do we know when?
CHAIRMAN KASS: When were they checked?
PROF. GEORGE: No, when were they created?
CHAIRMAN KASS: I think at various times in the preceding
years.
PROF. GEORGE: Going back five years, ten years?
CHAIRMAN KASS: The first stem cell lines were derived and
reported on anyhow in 1998. That's the first publication. Whether
they existed prior to publication for a short period of time, I
don't know. Yeah, we have one of the pioneers here. Elizabeth.
PROF. BLACKBURN: And should we add some of the lines
counted in the original 76 I believe were from foreign sources too, and
those might have been from -
PROF. GEORGE: Yeah. I was wondering about that.
PROF. BLACKBURN: Those might have been from those
countries' equivalent of federal funding. I'm not sure line by
line about that, but that's a possibility.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Yeah. No, I mean what was - while speaking
just about that question, and we need to get more information in here
because I think it's going to be relevant to the document. A
certain kind of confusion was created by failure to observe the
distinction between eligible and available. Some 60, and then
eventually it grew to some 70 lines were eligible, eligible in the
sense that they met the criteria of having been derived prior to the
date of the policy by informed consent, et cetera, et cetera, and not
derived with government funds.
Available meant, in fact, that they were characterized that
there were no commercial or other impediments to their being shared, so
that there was a certain amount of confusion. When people said there
were some 70 lines available, what they meant really was that there
were 70, 71, I've forgotten, eligible for funding. I believe the
number now actually available to the NIH is 12, so that of the 70
original available lines, most of them from international sources, in
fact, they are now a dozen of them that are actually available for
use. And we'll get some more information about - to fill in that
part of the history. Janet.
DR. ROWLEY: And I think that's a very important
distinction because when one uses the term "characterized",
that means a different level of real scientific analysis to different
people. But that was one of the issues, that many of the so.called
lines are not lines and that they cannot be grown indefinitely.
Secondly, their karyotype was not established, and so many of them may
be abnormal and, therefore, not suitable, so that this is why you go
from 77 down to 12. And this is part of the concern about the
availability.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Okay. Still a clarification, Jim? Please
go ahead.
PROF. WILSON: Yes. Janet raises a question that I thought
will be answered in the document, possibly it should be answered in
this document; namely, very practical questions. How long, and under
what circumstances does a cell line endure? To what extent do we know
the physiological origin of the cell line?
At some point obviously we may summarize information about
what has been done, what has been accomplished with these cell lines,
but just practical terms. Where do they come from, and how long do
they last? And will at some point, some President, if not this one,
the next one, have to consider re.authorizing other cell lines to make
up for a deficiency?
CHAIRMAN KASS: All right. Then if this exhausts the
matters of clarification, I think we can now sort of get into
discussion of the more substantive questions. And maybe we should go
back to this question of complicity. Michael, do you want to proceed,
or do you want to have the question put to you again?
PROF. SANDEL: Well, the moral heart of the issue seems
to be this question of complicity, and the paper brings this out
at the bottom of page 5, and on page 6. And it suggests an answer
in the third paragraph on page 6. The question is "whether
one can benefit from the results of an immoral act without becoming
complicit in the act." That's the heart of the moral test
of this position, and the discussion paper says that one may make
use of such benefits if, and only if three conditions are met; one
doesn't cooperate or actively involve oneself in the commission
of the act, and does nothing to abet or encourage the repetition
of the act by providing incentives and so on. And in accepting
the benefit when - re-annunciates and reaffirms the principle violated
by the original deed in question.
One question I have, and it may be a small question, but at
the top of page 5 there were some restrictions on eligibility for
federal funding of stem cell lines that I hadn't been aware of
until I read this, which are only those pre-existing lines. It's
not only that they must be pre-existing, but that they must be somehow
certified not to have been derived from excess embryos created for
reproductive purposes, and made available with the informed consent of
the donors, and without financial inducement.
So an initial question I have is, if the conditions for non-complicity
are correct and adequate, then why worry about these other considerations?
Presumably, these other considerations matter because even where
you're using pre-existing stem cell lines, where the evil deed
has already been committed, and where you're not complicit in
that evil deed. You don't perform it, you don't abet it,
you don't provide incentives for its being committed in the
future. Even in those cases, there would still be complicity, or
would they if you're using pre-existing lines that, let's
say, where the donors have been given some payment?
That would create complicity, but the underlying evil act
itself wouldn't, and that's very strange. So the only way of
making sense of those additional requirements of the pre-existing lines
is that they somehow make it even worse, but could they make it even
worse if the underlying moral evil were already tantamount to murder or
homicide? It seems unlikely if I'm not complicit - and the same
way to think about this we've discussed before using the fruits of
the Nazi experiments, medical experiments in the concentration camps.
Under what conditions can we use the medical data that came from these
Nazi experiments without being complicit in them? And maybe the answer
would have something to do with well, we didn't cooperate. We
didn't abet the practice. We don't encourage it in the
future. But then it would be odd to say, if that were the relevant
analogy, it would be odd to say but we can only - we're only not
complicit really if it turns out that the data was from these people
who were tortured and abused, was made available, you know - oh, no
they didn't give their consent. Oh well, in that case, no, no,
then we would be complicit even though we're meeting these other
requirements. Or if we're thinking of an example of using organs
that had been extracted from prisoners, let's say, in a prison camp
in some totalitarian society where it's reported that prisoners are
killed for their organs in various countries.
Now would we say well - what would be the policy? Would we
say well, it's an evil to kill someone for his organs? We're
not going to desist from using those organs, provided that those organs
- that the killings were done before a given date, so we don't
encourage it in the future. But we remove our complicity, provided
we're not encouraging - we didn't cooperate in the killing and
the extraction of the organs in this prison camp. We don't
encourage it in the future, because from now on we're not going to
do it. But we can use these organs to save lives. Let's suppose
they're still available, been preserved. They're fresh enough
so that they can - we'll use these ones.
And furthermore, we'll even provide federal funding for
the use of these organs, provided you don't do it again, provided
you don't it in the future. Would we satisfy ourselves and say
well, that's not really - we're not complicit. We're just
using what's available. In fact, we're giving federal funding
for those organs, but we're laying down these restrictions to make
sure it doesn't happen again, and that we're not complicit.
I think that would be a strange moral position to take if
we really did believe that these organs did come from human beings in a
prison camp who were killed to extract them, to get federal funding -
but under these - I think we would still say we're complicit. So
that's simply putting this together with the discussion we had of
Peter Berkowitz' paper. What this suggests - the complicity
discussion here suggests is that we would still consider it morally
complicit to avail ourselves of the organs we found in that prison
camp, even though we didn't kill the people, we didn't extract
the organs, and we're not going to provide incentives to do it
again, because from here on out, you can't do it. But in the
meantime, they're there, we can save life. Let's get federal
funding for these organs.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Does someone want to respond directly to
this? Mary Ann and then Jim, and Bill.
PROF. GLENDON: I think maybe there's a simpler
explanation for these conditions, which is that there are a number of
policies being followed here. And one is that the government
doesn't want to do anything to encourage the creation of embryos
for other than reproductive purposes. Another is, you always want to
support informed consent to procedures. And another is, you don't
want to encourage commercial trafficking in human material.
I just don't think that there needs to be or were thought
of as involved at the complicity issue. I think the complicity
issue...
PROF. SANDEL: Let's just ask, Mary Ann, about that,
what you've just said. But remember, this is in the context
of only pre-existing one.
PROF. GLENDON: Well, I'm coming to that. So the
complicity issue has to do with pre-existing, to take your analogy to
the use of materials that were obtained from victims of national
socialism. One of the reasons why the complicity issue is not as acute
in that case as it is here, is that behavior is not ongoing. It's
finished. Here we're dealing with an ongoing situation, and the
risk of encouraging future production of these lines is greater.
PROF. SANDEL: So what would you do with the organ case of
the prisoners in China, hypothetically, which could be ongoing?
PROF. GLENDON: I'm sorry?
PROF. SANDEL: Well, how would you respond to the organs
derived from prisoners in a prison camp in the complicity issue? Do
you think that comes closer to this example?
PROF. GLENDON: If it's an ongoing situation.
PROF. SANDEL: No, but if we say we're only going to
use those organs that we came upon yesterday, and we'll get federal
funding for those transplantations because the deed has already been
done. But we're not going to allow any federal funding for any
organs from prison camp victims after August 9th, after today.
CHAIRMAN KASS: That one I think is easy, don't you
think, Michael? Let me give you an American version, the eminent Dr.
Kavorkian, mostly known for his interest in assisted suicide, actually
had combined those proposals with a desire to get organs for
transplantation. This was a double.barreled project of his.
Imagine that you have the Good Samaritan euthanizers led by
the good doctor, and that he doesn't get just ordinary healthy
people. He waits for the terminally ill but not yet dead, and the
cadre come in and extract the organs from the almost dying, and
you've got a freezer full of these. And they're properly
stored, and you catch them. And the question is, you've got a
freezer full of good organs. You throw them out. And if you use them,
or even if you use them, and use them in federally supported hospitals,
are you, in effect, complicit in the dirty deed that was done?
PROF. SANDEL: What do you say?
CHAIRMAN KASS: I say no. And I say no under certain kinds
of specified conditions; which is to say, you round them up. You
punish them severely, and you make it perfectly clear in doing so
that you're re-affirming the principle that they themselves
have violated, but you can't somehow undo those deeds. And
the use of those organs to save life does not make you guilty of
the act, I don't think. That's, I think, debatable, but
that would be a kind of analogy.
PROF. SANDEL: But you would be complicit if this were not
a case of euthanasia where people gave their consent, which meets one
of these requirements. But if, instead, it were a prison camp where
there was no consent -
CHAIRMAN KASS: Do that to me again.
PROF. SANDEL: You changed the case so that we have
euthanasia with consent that generates these organs, the freezer full
of organs. And I assume you did that to meet the requirement here.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I didn't say with consent.
PROF. SANDEL: So then it's not really euthanasia, or
euthanasia against the will of the people. It's murder.
CHAIRMAN KASS: They're comatose. What do they know?
PROF. SANDEL: But to clarify the case of complicity,
let's assume that these are people in a prison camp whose organs
are taken out, and the organs populating your freezer are from victims
of a prison camp or concentration camp.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Yeah, I -
PROF. SANDEL: Then there is no complicity. Even there in
availing, in using them to save lives.
CHAIRMAN KASS: That's, I think, my - I think that this
kind of traditional moral - these are sort of - this is kind of a
traditional moral approach to this question. It tries to deal with
that, and I think would answer in the way in which I just did.
PROF. SANDEL: But if even that's not complicit, then
it would be strange to add these other requirements of the pre-existing
organs in the freezer, that they be made available with informed
consent, that there were no financial inducements and so on,
wouldn't it?
CHAIRMAN KASS: Gil, do you want to -
PROF. MEILAENDER: I was just going to say, I mean, I think
Mary Ann's answer is still the relevant one there. I mean, it
would be possible to argue that that doesn't affect complicity, but
there might be other things that one has concerns about, which we have
traditionally had concerns about. I think that that - that these are,
in a certain sense, separable from the complicity issue, because
complicity itself does not depend on the gravity of the evil. It
depends on the way in which one's will is aligned or not aligned
with the act.
PROF. SANDEL: So would you agree with Leon that there is
no moral complicity in availing yourself of the organs from the freezer
created in the prison camp?
PROF. MEILAENDER: I agree that you wouldn't be
complicit in the technical sense. You might still have reasons why you
wish to distinguish that, the use of those organs from the first case.
And there would be powerful reasons why one might prefer to die than to
get those organs in transplant, but I wouldn't say that someone who
took them or used them was complicit in the moral evil.
PROF. SANDEL: And would you go so far as to say that
federal funding should be devoted to the use of these organs?
PROF. MEILAENDER: I can't even imagine how to think
that through at the moment. I mean, it's too far a stretch for me
to figure that out, because Mary Ann is right, once again, that there
would be a whole range of things I'd need to think about.
PROF. SANDEL: But it's not such a stretch because
that's morally analogous to the federal funding of pre-existing
stem cell lines.
PROF. MEILAENDER: No, I think it's not. I think that
what we have to give thought to is what these other factors were, how
much emphasis we wanted to place upon them.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: If I could make a point here. If the
President's policy had been not that we would only accept lines
pre-existing on August the 9th, but we would accept in the future
lines derived only from IVF, only from IVF for reproduction, only
with informed consent, and with no commerce involved, then those
three conditions would make sense.
What's hard to understand is, if the policy was one of
saying that will not happen in the future because that would be aiding
and abetting otherwise, but the policy will be that only pre. existing
lines can be used, it is hard to understand why these conditions are
attached.
Let's assume that there was a clinic, and there are
clinics that create embryos for IVF purely for research, and one of
those had developed a line, not for reproduction, before August the
9th. Why would we then want to say that that line ought to be
prohibited?
CHAIRMAN KASS: Bill, and then Jim Wilson.
DR. HURLBUT: When I looked at this, when I read this, my
thought was . and this goes to your question and to Charles'
comment . my thought was that all the criteria on page 6 could again
surface if a different President took over say five years from now, and
said well, now I'm going to issue the same statement, because in
the meantime, there was no federal funding. There are more cell lines
created independent of federal funding, and so forth. All three could
theoretically meet the same criterion as the original cell lines.
Well, when I saw the President make his statement on August
9th, something struck me at the time, which I think maybe is the answer
to this question. And that was, it seemed to me that he was adding
something else into the equation, not just that these cell lines were
created under the conditions that did not have the three objections,
but that there was one other thing; and that was, that they were
created in a climate of a certain moral ambiguity and innocence, if you
will. And that it was before there was broad public debate, and that
it was a very difficult subject, and difficult issue. And that up to
now, these were made, but now it's time to say we need to take
seriously this issue, not the three before, which were clear moral
principles, but this new issue of what do we do with these IVF spares
and so forth.
That was the - it seems to me that that's why in five
years from now another President can't turn around and say well,
now I'm going to let another five years worth of - and keep the
same position as the current President. Does that make sense?
CHAIRMAN KASS: Jim Wilson.
PROF. WILSON: I'm not sure whether Michael's
concern is with the wording of the language here with the substance of
the problem he poses. The substance of the problem, it seems to me, is
easily managed. If we find in a recently occupied prison camp organs
that have been extracted by clearly inappropriate, even torturous
means, and we discover in the same prison camp a young girl whose life
is in danger because her liver has been destroyed, we transplant one of
those discovered livers into the girl, provided it is medically
suitable. And we're not complicit in anything, especially since
we're going to go about punishing as severely as we can the doctors
and other barbarians who engaged in these illegal extractions. So the
substance of the problem doesn't raise, for me, the word complicity
at all.
The interesting question is about the text. And it has
nothing to do with whether we are going to use federal funding or not
for prison guards to extract livers in American prisons from unwilling
persons. It's whether the President, this President or some other
President, is going to say the existing cell lines are running out. We
need more. We don't have enough. We're not sure of the
paternity of some of these, or maternity of some of these cells and,
therefore, should people donate more cells. So I'm trying to
clarify which of these two issues are you really talking about? Could
I get Michael to just to give a brief answer?
CHAIRMAN KASS: Yeah. It's a question to Michael.
Please respond.
PROF. SANDEL: All right. Well, just as a brief response,
I think we're talking about whether the worry about complicity
makes sense if you assume that — o go to the organ case from
the prison — does the following position make sense?
You find all these available organs in the prison that were
extracted by evil means. You say we can use them without being morally
complicit. We can even use federal funding to use them, provided we
resolve that no federal funding will be used for organ extraction in
the future. And furthermore, that it won't be legally prohibited
for people to extract organs in this way in the future, but it will be
- they can do it with private funding. But it will be - but there will
be no federal funding for any ones that are done that way in the
future, only private funding. That's the moral strangeness of the
position if you believe that the analogy to the organ transplant is a
good one.
There's no incoherence — this goes back to the discussion
in the first session — there's no incoherence if you reject
the analogy to organ extraction. If people aren't being killed,
but there's still a morally questionable activity, it's
perfectly sensible to say we're not going to give it federal
funding. We'll allow the pre-existing lines without complicity.
It's morally dubious, but it's not killing people for their
organs. So if you put this worry about complicity together with
the permission of doing it, provided it's not federally funded,
I think it shows that the organ transplant, that killing people
for their organs makes no sense.
PROF. WILSON: Well, of course, but the assumption is, I
thought, was that if we find prison guards who evilly extracted these
organs, they would be punished, ideally shot. The question, therefore,
is are couples who go to an artificial reproduction center and donate
and create fertilized eggs, and some are left over, should they be
shot? Well, I don't think anybody has made an argument for them to
be shot. So then the question is, what do we do with their leftover
eggs? And the question that raises for the President's speech is,
obviously, why did we suddenly say that eggs only up until August 9th,
2001 voluntarily donated can be used, but no eggs voluntarily donated
after August 9th, 2001 can be used. That, to me, is a puzzle.
PROF. SANDEL: Right. Well, I share that puzzle.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: Well, that's the point I tried to
make, is that I think by building in those conditions for the pre-existing
lines, the President's policy does create sort of a logical
problem. Those would be the conditions you would expect if he had
annunciated a policy that allowed ongoing use of discarded embryos.
In fact, I remember when I listened to that speech, which I
must say was the most unusual Presidential speech I've ever heard.
I've never heard a Presidential speech in which a President
seriously considered both sides of a serious issue. Normally, when you
hear a Presidential speech, you know exactly where he's headed on
line two. And I don't think anybody who listened knew which way he
was going to end up on line two. I didn't even know on line
seven. In the middle of that speech, I remember I turned to my son,
and I said he's going to allow new lines as long as it's from
discarded embryos, and he said no, he's going to make a line at
August 9th. Of course, he was 16, and he was right, so I give him
credit for that, you know, sort of respect he gave to both sides. But
I, personally, would have come down on a position of allowing ongoing
use of discarded embryos, and given the conditions he attached,
you'd expect that would have been his position. At least logically
I think it would have been expected.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Bill May, then Elizabeth.
DR. MAY: Two comments. One, I have a basic question about
what the fundamental purpose of this council is. Is it retrospective,
trying to figure out what the mind of the President was on that
occasion, or offering a kind of apologia for the President in
relationship to his right flank; that is, those who worried about the
moral consistency of his accommodation to pre.existent destroyed
embryos and stem lines? Or an attempt to offer an apologia in the
other direction, hey, it could have been worse. He could have extended
a ban to the private arena, you know. But that would all be
retrospective debate, and it seems to me the council has an interest
retrospective, but its basic interest should be prospective, what kind
of advice does this council have to offer the President, which requires
one to visit the issue of the merits of the case.
Now if we offer this retrospective, then I think we . for
the sake of completeness so it doesn't simply look as though
we're blessing the President's action in the past . we do have
to deal with the prospective issue. That's my first comment. And
whether our discussions, both this paper, if it stands alone without
discussion of the merits of the case, whether it makes sense for us to
issue this paper without revisiting this other issue, which we dealt
with at the beginning of the council's deliberations.
My second point relates back to this retrospective glance,
and the way in which we equip ourselves with moral language. Earlier,
Leon talked about right/wrong. The tendency is we're talking there
about absolutes not susceptible to compromise, as opposed to areas in
which there are competing goods. And there, one is dealing with issues
which are susceptible to compromise.
As a matter of fact, the word "compromise" has
different meanings in those two different areas. In the first area, if
it's a clear distinction between right and wrong period, then to
compromise is to defect from one's duty, pure and simple, and maybe
from one's vocation, as well.
In the latter area, we recognize compromise as a striking
of some kind of balance and weighing. But as I read this paper,
there's a tendency to look back to the Clinton Administration and
say well, its reflections were technical, political, and so forth, but
in the second case, we're dealing with moral principles. And then
the contrast between consideration of moral principles and one's
duty, one tends to see everything else as cost benefit analysis, harms,
benefits, utilitarianism lurks out there in the wings.
My problem is, I am a duty.oriented thinker. I think I
am. But one of my duties is to consider harms and benefits, I mean,
because I've got a duty to beneficence. I've got a duty to
non. maleficence. It's not my only duty. That's where I
differ from the utilitarians who weigh and balance all possible rules
of the road in the light of what will produce the greatest net balance
of good over evil. But I am pluralistic in my understanding of
duties. And it isn't the case that I occupy high ground only when
my duties are absolute. Because my duties are plural, that doesn't
mean I'm a relativist. It does mean, however, I am caught in
circumstances where I may need to strike off a policy line and so
forth, that recognizes a duty, a principle, reaches a territorial limit
when it comes up against another principle, which in the particular
case is more overriding, and that solution isn't merely in terms of
weighing harms and benefits.
And furthermore, even when I reach a decision, which may
have tragic dimensions to it, (a) I will have further duties of
reparation; (b) the duty that yields to another duty, even under those
circumstances, may maintain some pressures upon me, and how I pursue
the particular line of duty that I face. So I've offered two
comments here, one is what is the basic agenda purpose of this
council. And second, whether we have too readily assumed on the one
hand are those who are duty.oriented in their thinking,
principle.oriented, and those duties do not admit of any exception as
opposed to those who are merely awash in the sea of the relative, and
all the precariousness of cost benefit analysis.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Does someone want to join this comment
directly? Dan, Elizabeth.
PROF. BLACKBURN: We've had examples of extreme
situations where we've talked about organs taken from prisoners and
prisoners being killed, but we do have a very, you know, on the ground
example which is very widespread in society, so we give a multitude of
pediatric vaccines to the population in general. And we shouldn't
forget the fact that a large fraction of those were based on fetal
cells. That's where they came from, and so we have made that
decision in this case where I think the issue that you raised of
relative potential goods, you know, has been weighed, and the decision
has been made very clearly. That's just a historical fact that
we've done that.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I have Paul. Robby, are you still on the
list? No. Gil, and then myself.
DR. FOSTER: I just wanted to follow.up on one thing that I
think Bill was talking about. One - we've been talking about five
a great deal. I'm sort of nervous about trying to interpret what
is the soul of Presidents, and so forth. I remember early. on in this
council, I used to say to Leon, before we became really good friends,
I'd say well, what you think is this when we were arguing the whole
cloning thing, and he would always respond, "You don't know
what I really think." He never explained it to me what he really
thought, but he said - Leon, won't remember that. And what I'm
saying is, if we do such a paper as this, and also hear about the
future, I think that under paragraph 3, it would be much more helpful
to, instead of personalizing this to President Clinton or to President
Bush, to simply say that this is what - in the Clinton Administration,
this is what happened, without making a judgment about what his moral
thoughts are on here. I mean, how do we know what his moral thoughts
are, or President Bush's, for that matter. So I would certainly
want to depersonalize this. It puts it like it's a conflict
between a previous President and the sitting President, and that's
not what we're here to talk about at all.
And along the same lines, I do think that when we say that
the majority of people want to do this, or a significant portion want
to do that, I think there ought to be at least a footnote or something
to give some sense of what the, you know, polls or percentages show.
But I certainly would like to depersonalize this. It makes me very
nervous to have somebody try to say what I'm thinking, and so
forth.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Paul.
DR. McHUGH: I think this goes a little along the lines
that both Bill and Michael, and Charles were saying, because I also
don't want to say what's in the President's mind. But I
can tell you what's in my mind, especially after listening to the
President, and also contributing to this council.
I thought that the President did an important thing at the
time of his speech in August; namely, by enhancing a moral position,
and bringing some moral distance to recognizing what had previously
been a more casual approach to the embryonic life, human embryos, and
wanted to call our attention to the fact that maybe we had been much
too casual about our thinking about that.
I also, though, felt as a doctor, and as a person
interested in conditions that might respond to stem cells, that he did
an important - made an important addition to the science by saying here
are some stem cells, and now the ball is in your court, scientists, to
show us that this is an important tool for the treatment of, the
success of some aspect of the developing human science that we could
use. We are not going to go farther along this road until something
much more compelling comes from you scientists. Okay?
Now although I have views about what might or might not
ultimately lead to a further development like Jim was mentioning, I
thought that this was a coherent and practical policy in relationship
to where Americans were in this complicated matter. He showed us that
there was moral significance in the embryo, and he said to the
scientists that claimed there should be total license in what they were
doing. Here you can do something and prove to us that you need more.
And ultimately, that's why I ask at this council again and again
when people come in and say they object to the limits that President
Bush put onto the use of these cells, I ask them always well, have you
exhausted the cell lines that are now available to the point where you
have a compelling case that there should be more?
I think when the American people come to that decision in
relationship to real data and real experience, we will face another
moral problem, I agree, but a problem that will be a more matured
problem and, in fact, a problem that we scientists can look at and
speak about from data.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I have Gil, myself, and then Michael.
PROF. MEILAENDER: Two comments. One, in terms of what
our task is, whether prospectively or retrospectively, I think our
charge is to monitor the stem cell research that's going on, that
has begun in light of the President's policy announced in 2001.
And I would interpret that literally. In other words, we're
supposed to monitor and report on what, in fact, is being done.
We may have different views about whether that's enough
that's being done, or too much being done, or just the right
amount, or whatever, but it seems to me our task it to monitor that,
and so we should keep that in mind.
The second is, the thing that I think is good about this
Staff Paper is that it does show a way in which, again rightly or
wrongly . I'm not worried about that right now . there is a certain
kind of moral foundation built into that policy announced in 2001. And
the paper captures it nicely.
The general question is, well, will these cell lines be
enough? I mean, that's the way the question is always formulated.
It was formulated immediately, in fact, after the announcement of the
policy. And the one thing that's clear in all the complications of
the complicity argument, is that a complicity argument will only work
if the answer to that question is well, I guess they'll have to be
enough.
In other words, if it's a shifting line, then you
can't, in fact, make the complicity argument work. The complicity
argument depends on doing nothing to encourage future. And as say,
whether that's a good policy or bad policy is a separate question,
but I think the document nicely captures what, in fact, is the essence
of the policy. It will not work as an argument about moral complicity,
or avoiding such complicity unless the answer is well, it will have to
be enough.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Does someone want to piggyback quickly on
what - because it looked like people were leaping to say something to
Gil, and I'll yield. Michael, did you -
DR. GAZZANIGA: To Paul's point, I think we have to
step back a little bit and keep in mind how science works. And for
every dollar invested, you get about a 1 percent return on a successful
piece of science, so the compelling logic that you suggest there in
come on scientists, it's your turn, is a little bit misleading in
the sense that 1 percent of 12 lines finally hitting the ground here
isn't much. And you're really asking the scientists with their
hands tied behind their back, you're giving them a couple of test
tubes, one centrifuge for the whole nation. You know, it's just
not of the scale that any scientific community would go after a
problem. And that's what everybody is complaining about, and
that's the underlying issue here. It's not of the scale to
find things out in an efficient and intelligent way. That's the
issue.
DR. McHUGH: By the way, Michael, I know that, but because
this becomes an issue of much more intense moral concerns, I think the
scientists are going to have to work with a little sand in their
saddlebags and should stop complaining about it.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Let me try to respond to some of the things
that have been very nicely said by several people. Let me start with
Bill May's, which is sort probably a meta.question about what
we're doing here.
This document is hardly a report, and would be simply the .
after an introduction, an opening chapter. And there are criticisms
properly made already about what's stated in here, both about
personalization, any suggestion that only one side has moral principles
will be eliminated, if there's any hint at that. That wasn't
the issue.
And indeed, for my money, the most important contribution
that one could make here is to have - never mind how this policy
differs from the previous administration. It's terribly important
if you're trying to discuss - if you're trying to monitor
activities that are taking place under the current policy, you should
be fairly clear what the current policy is, and on what its foundations
are. Because if you mean to try to propose some changes in the policy,
you ought to be able to see what kind of arguments and what kind of
evidence might be relevant to seeing that that policy is changed, so
that's the first point.
I mean, to be sure, this is - and it's not meant to be
an apologia, but it's meant to be an explication. And I have read
countless things, countless statements about what this policy is or
what it rests on, which are simply wrong, simply wrong. And we have an
obligation, I think, as part of laying out of what's going on in
this field to try to do the best we can as a preamble to our
monitoring, to say under what aegis is this activity now taking place,
and how do we understand it. That would be the first point.
And I think I've partly given an answer to your second
point about moral versus merely prudential or calculative. We will
adjust, I think, the way this is presented.
Next, let's see. I think the next comment, I think,
should go to - let me leapfrog the comments that are directed to
Michael to come to Paul's remark. Paul's formulation of this,
and also echoed in part by Jim Wilson, is to say look, we've got a
wait and see policy here. Let the scientists go and do their work,
come back to us in two years, five years, ten years, and we'll
rethink this.
Now that's a sensible way to think about this if, in
fact, the policy rests upon a kind of cost benefit analysis of the
weight of the research as over against something else. But it matters
a great deal, I think, whether the policy is right or not is another
matter, but it matters a great deal if it's really the case that
the policy has been based upon a foundation such that empirical
evidence on the ground of the state of the research could change it.
That's your wish, and I think is probably Jim Wilson's wish,
but I'm not sure that it's a correct understanding of the
foundation of the policy, and that matters. I mean, that is probably
implicit in what Gil said.
Now let me try to say something with respect to articulated
moral foundations of the policy, and whether or not the complicity
argument works. Let me, for the moment, bracket those possibly
embarrassing, but I think Mary Ann may well have taken care of
additional given reasons for maybe, maybe. But Jim Wilson seems to be
bothered by the fact that this arbitrary deadline of the 9th of
August, if something is wrong after the 9th of August, then it was
wrong before the 9th of August. But that, I think, can be really
explained entirely on the complicity argument.
It's not that you've been complicit in the previous
act, but if you say we will continue to fund research on lines derived
after this date, we are, in effect, rewarding the subsequent activity.
We are participating in it. We are in a way declaring that we will
take advantage of the results of previous destruction, without being
complicit. We didn't cooperate in it in the first place. We will
not reward this activity in the future. And, therefore, we are
providing any encouragement. And by the way, we're saying we
don't believe federal funds should be spent on this at all,
period. We affirm the language of the Dickey Amendment.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: In what way are we encouraging if you
continued to use discarded embryos after August 9th?
CHAIRMAN KASS: With federal funds?
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: Yes, there's no commerce involved. I
mean, assuming -
CHAIRMAN KASS: You're, in effect, saying that people
can continue to do so with the expectation that once the deed is done,
the lines are available for research.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: Right, but what's the encouragement?
I mean, you go to IVF to have a child. You sometimes end up with
discarded embryos.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Fine.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: What's the connection to the research
in terms of encouragement?
CHAIRMAN KASS: You would be offering financial reward
after the fact to those who would be deriving new cell lines.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: That's my question. I was assuming
there would be no - we're assuming there's no commerce here.
If there were, you could simply say that we ban the commerce, without
banning the use.
CHAIRMAN KASS: You are rewarding the researchers who will
be doing the research on those lines and, therefore, you'll be, in
a way, countenancing the future act. That, I think, is clear.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: But my question was about encouragement
of the "original sin". You can dispute whether it is.
I'm not - I mean, the argument that if you were to permit the use
of discarded embryos created after August 9th, you'd be encouraging
- creation of discarded embryos is a tenuous one, and I'm trying to
pursue how that encouragement works, if there's no - if they're
donated and there's no commerce.
PROF. MEILAENDER: You're encouraging not their
creation, but their destruction.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: But they're going to end up being
destroyed anyway, whether -
PROF. MEILAENDER: Maybe, maybe not.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: Maybe they end up in freezers eternally.
PROF. MEILAENDER: There's no good solution, I
understand that.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: No, but I still have a trouble with -
DR. FOSTER: Gil, entropy - there's no doubt that
ultimately nothing lives forever in freezers or anything. There's
no doubt that those embryos are going to be gone, absolutely no doubt.
Entropy does not disappear because one objects to the fact that . .
CHAIRMAN KASS: The issue is not about - it's not just
about the destruction. It's - the operative issue is may federal
funds be used on research in which embryos are destroyed or damaged?
That's the language of the Dickey Amendment.
If you say in the future, federal funds may be used for the
products of embryo, for research on the products of embryo destruction,
are you not, in advance of that fact, saying you will reward the
results of that act with research funds?
PROF. WILSON: No. I mean, we're struggling once again
to redefine the special, but not conclusive respect that is owed to an
embryo. If we believe that an embryo at the fifth or tenth day of its
existence deserves the same respect as a eight and a half month old
fetus, or a newborn child, then the answer is that President Bush
should not have allowed any research at any time, using any kind of
money. If we think the nascent human life in a five or ten day old
blastosphere is meaningless, then they should use federal money to
encourage people to produce them at random, and pay women to do it.
The position we have, I think many of us have tried to
take, is that blastospheres - embryos created as a result of in vitro
fertilization, left aside because they're not needed, headed
ultimately to destruction, as Dan correctly says, are a continuing
opportunity to possibly solve important human lives, provided these
blastospheres are not kept alive for more than a certain number of days
in their active stage. That's what we're trying to do by way
of defining special respect as an intermediate position. And,
therefore, I don't follow your argument.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Rebecca, can you help? I'll try one
more time if Rebecca doesn't solve this for me.
PROF. DRESSER: Okay. I'm sure you'll get another
chance. This is the same argument that was played out with fetal
tissue transplant research. The whole concern was by making federal
funds available for research, will this create a new incentive for
abortion, so that there might be some women on the fence who might say
well, since I have this option available that has some positive
dimensions, maybe I'll go ahead and terminate the pregnancy. So
the way it eventually got worked out was, they set up a procedure where
enough people were comfortable that the decisions would be separated.
That is, you couldn't raise the issue of donation for research
until after the woman had made the decision to go ahead and have the
abortion.
So here, I guess the question would be, are there
individuals who go through IVF and they are deciding they've had a
child or two, and they're deciding okay, well, here we have all
these extra embryos. Perhaps there would be people who might say if
the donation for research option is available, well, okay, let's do
that, because some good could come of this. Whereas, if that option is
not available, at least the federal funds are not supporting that
option, then they might be more likely to say well, maybe we'll try
to have another child, or maybe we'll give them to another couple
to try to allow them to have a child. So I guess that would be the way
that there would be some sort of incentive created for destruction if
federal funds, whereas, it wouldn't be there without them.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: I understand the train of logic. I just
- I think the universe of people who would be affected by that logic is
rather small.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Are you disputing that the formulation of a
decision that - are you disputing the formulation of the moral
foundations of this policy as articulated? Never mind whether it's
a good one or not, are you -
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: Disputing the?
CHAIRMAN KASS: The description of - that this was a
question, given that these lines exist, given that the law prohibits
federal funding for the creation of those lines, isn't the question
that remains, especially when lots of one's supporters are saying
this research shouldn't be funded, because if you fund it
you're, in fact, complicit in the dirty deed. Isn't the
question that remains whether one could support research on the lines
that exist, though the destruction has taken place, and I believe in
the President's speech he alluded to the fact that those - that the
embryos from which these lines came are already gone.
Isn't the question then, can one support research on
these existing lines without, number one, being in some way complicit
in the deed that created them? And (b), can one not by saying no
funding for any new lines, is one not asserting the kind of principle
and removing any kind of reward for researchers would derive them
subsequently. I take it that's the way to make - whether you like
it or not, I think it's a way to make morally consistent coherence
out of exactly what was done.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: I think that was the intention of the
final policy. I'm not sure that the logic, the Point B that you
raised really holds up to scrutiny.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Why not?
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: Because I don't think it's very
realistic to think that if you were to use discarded embryos from IVF
clinics on an ongoing basis, you are encouraging the creation of those
embryos. And, therefore, if - the prohibition on that seems to me to
be illogical, given the original position.
And I think the point that Michael made, that in the
original policy where they built.in those conditions for discarded
embryos from lines created before August 9th, those conditions
don't make a lot of sense because, as he argued I think with the
analogy of the prisoners, however you would have derived earlier lines
from anything, since we were clearly not complicit, having those
restrictions does not make a lot of sense. It seems to me those
restrictions, no commerce, consent, and embryos created for the purpose
of reproduction, those conditions logically apply to embryos, to stem
cell lines derived from embryos produced after August 9th.
CHAIRMAN KASS: It seems to me Bill Hurlbut gave - between
Mary Ann and Bill Hurlbut, I think they've given a perfectly
adequate answer; namely, those lines that existed prior to that
date would have been - in fact, those kind of conditions would probably
- the text of the guidelines produced by the Tilghman Committee
would probably support this. Those particular criteria would have
been operative for permission - conditions attached to the lines
available for funding previously.
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: Let's assume that we discovered that
one of our 12 lines came from an embryo created in a clinic where the
parents were not given informed consent, or were paid . would we
destroy those lines tomorrow?
CHAIRMAN KASS: Would we destroy them, or would you -
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: Would we not use them?
CHAIRMAN KASS: Would you render them ineligible for
funding?
DR. KRAUTHAMMER: Of course. And the answer would be no,
so what I'm arguing is, those pre.conditions are not logical.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Does someone want to join?
PROF. MEILAENDER: Let me try to join, because I - my
problem is I'm incoherent. And that is the whole purpose of a
growing moral experience, to make yourself steadily more coherent over
time. And what I appreciated about the President's position, I
really notice the same concerns that Michael and Charles are raising.
On the other hand, I felt that if the President had said we
couldn't use any cells, and human stem cell research was -
embryonic stem cell research was outlawed, that this message would be
an inappropriate stopping of our moral development. And even though
I'm against embryonic research, by the way, I am against that, I
feel that over time if the scientists have an opportunity to do their
work, that they can show these benefits to us in some ways, and then we
might be able to get stem cells in a way that would not offend me and
my views about future embryonic research. And that would be a moral
progression along with a scientific progression, and that's why I
support this idea. And why I don't go quite along with you, Leon,
when you say that if I take this view, that ultimately I'm going to
say well, eventually I'm going to want to do that research but
start killing off those embryos. No. I want to be able to say here
are some stem cells, here are available stem cells, here's what we
can do with them. And then we have to find a way to get similar stem
cells in less morally obnoxious fashion.
CHAIRMAN KASS: We are close to the end. Michael Sandel,
anyone else in the queue? Janet. Michael first, and then Janet.
PROF. SANDEL: Bringing the two sessions, what we've
been trying to do, as I understand it, is to identify or draw out the
moral logic of the position that the President took. What would be the
best way of making moral sense of a position that prohibits federal
funding on new stem cell lines, but does not ban embryonic stem cell
research done privately. And that even extends federal funding to
pre-existing ones.
What assumptions make moral sense of that position? And
the argument has been that it's not possible to make moral sense of
that position, if you assume that embryonic stem cell research is
infanticide, is like yanking organs from infants. It's not
possible to assume that because in that case, there would not be a good
reason not to ban the practice, short of civil war. It also
doesn't make sense of the restrictions, the much discussed
restrictions on the pre-existing lines, because if complicity isn't
a problem with the - if complicity with infanticide or prison extracted
organs, if that's not a problem, then it certainly - then dealing
with consent or financial inducement is not necessary.
And so the best way of making sense of the position is on
the assumption that the status of the embryo is in the category of the
intermediate view, that we've much discussed here.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Or in doubt, right?
PROF. SANDEL: Either in doubt, or the intermediate view.
And the other part of the discussion has been taking that assumption as
the best way of making sense of the position. Either it's in
doubt, or the intermediate view, some version of the intermediate view
is correct. And then trying to apply that assumption in ways that Paul
did, and that Charles and Jim did, to suggest the practical
implications for future federal funding beyond what's already been
embodied in the policy. And so it makes perfect sense of the position
construed in this way, which I think is the most charitable way of
making - to say as Paul did well, maybe the reason for the restriction
now in the federal funding to the pre-existing is to say to the
scientists the ball is in your court. Show us what you can do, and
then come back to us.
That makes sense on the intermediate view, or in the view
of doubt, because it says look, the embryo is not to be toyed with for
nothing. It's not to be used wantonly. But if you can show really
significant and morally compelling, and scientifically promising things
can be done well, then given the intermediate view, or the view of -
the agnostic view, then we may revise the policy in the light of what
you can show us. So Paul's extending the underlying principle in
that direction, and Charles is suggesting an extension in another
direction.
If what underlies this policy is some version of the
intermediate view, then that would give reason to consider the use now
of leftover spares from IVF clinics, if the intermediate view is the
one that's underlying this policy anyhow.
Now, of course, you would reject Charles' position, if
you reject the intermediate view, but the whole discussion today, going
back to Peter's paper, shows that this policy itself only makes
sense if you accept the intermediate view, and so it's open to the
kind of question that Charles and Jim, and Paul have raised.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I think there are . and they'll speak
for themselves, I'm sure . not everybody shares your conclusion
that the conversation has shown that last point. Various people have
suggested that they're either settled practices, or they're
questions of prudence as to what you can try to do when. And if
you're suggesting that the authors of the Dickey Amendment are
somehow being morally inconsistent, while at the same time insist on an
absolute ban of all embryo research, that doesn't necessarily
follow as a matter of consistency.
You seem to suggest that people of principle have to be
fanatics in order to prove that they're men of principle, and that
if they don't sort of push for the whole hog, you sort of suspect
the grounds of their judgment. It seems to me that we live in a
complicated society where sometimes people of profound principle will,
just as people who might favor this research, might be willing to cede
publicly that their fellow citizens who oppose it on deep moral grounds
have enough standing to say that the regime ought not to officially
pronounce its blessings on it. So it seems to me that in these kinds
of matters where there is settled practice, and the embryos are in the
freezers, and people are donating and the research is going forward,
that Members of Congress, either as a matter of respect or as a matter
of the sense that they cannot now muster the will to stop this, muster
the support to stop this, would settle for this matter.
I don't think the conclusion that you draw from the
existing arrangements implies what you say it implies, but -
PROF. SANDEL: May I quickly, I'm not suggesting that
there's any - I don't think that people are fanatic to insist
on their principles. I think that people who both oppose federal
funding of abortion and who also argue for banning abortion are not
fanatic, they're principled. And it's a position that makes
perfect sense against - given a certain view of when human life
begins. There's nothing fanatic about that, any more than
there's anything fanatic about abolitionism.
PROF. MEILAENDER: But there's also nothing
unprincipled about not pushing dogmatically forward to get everything
that one might think best at any given moment.
PROF. SANDEL: It depends what's at stake here. If
murder is at stake, if infanticide is at stake, and that's what you
believe, then you would push forward.
PROF. MEILAENDER: That is not -
PROF. SANDEL: If you believe it's short of
infanticide, then there would be good reasons for not pushing forward,
and I think that's what the President very reasonably has done.
PROF. MEILAENDER: That's not necessarily true. I
mean, I don't know who the "you" is in that sentence. It
may be that that's what you would do but, you know, to construe the
argument as having gone in a certain way is mistaken. Not everyone
thinks that holding certain positions means that they - that you must,
in a sort of a dogmatic spirit, push for the whole of them at any given
time. You may have reasons, both moral and prudential, for stopping at
certain places.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Janet, you've been patient. I'll
give you the last word.
DR. ROWLEY: Well, I'm not sure that I'm going to
have necessarily the last word, but I would like to make two points.
One does follow on from the discussion that we've been having, and
it does relate to the way the paper, or some of the tone of this
particular draft.
I think it is important as one looks at some of the
statements, that when one talks about the embryo being inviolable, you
know, this should be modified because, as has been pointed out by a
number of the participants, that may be an inappropriate word to use in
the context of this report.
My major concern is that the report stops short of discussing
the consequences of these decisions. And it's okay for Paul
to say well, scientists have to put up or shut up. I think Michael's
point was well.taken, that to put up requires money. Now the report
indicates this is not a problem, you just do it privately, so you
don't need federal funds, though there are some federal funds
available. But I think that at the present time, the amount of
federal funding of research, and we'll find out from Dr. Zerhouni
fairly soon, is fairly minor as compared with what really needs
to be done in this particular area. And I'm not sure whether,
in fact, this Staff Working Paper will be followed on by a second
paper that does deal with the consequences of this policy, or else
the consequences of this policy need to be included within this
to make it a - put it in, I think, a more appropriate or - that's
the wrong word - a more complete perspective.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you. We are at 12:30. We will have
Dr. Zerhouni, and then Dr. McClellan in the session from 2 to 3:30.
Both of these men are taking time out from very busy schedules to
join us, so let's be sure to start promptly at 2:00.
(Whereupon, the proceedings in the above-entitled matter went
off the record at 12:32 p.m.)
SESSION 3: STEM CELLS: MOVING RESEARCH
FROM THE BENCH TOWARD THE BEDSIDE: THE ROLE OF NIH AND FDA
CHAIRMAN KASS: I think we should get started,
notwithstanding the fact that a few of our members are delinquent.
We'll just keep them after school.
This session is entitled "Stem Cells - Moving Research from the
Bench Toward the Bedside: The Role of the NIH," and then in
the second of this session, the FDA.
This afternoon we move from the principles of the stem cell
policy to its implementation with a review of the contributions of NIH
and the FDA to efforts aimed at bringing research from the bench toward
the bedside.
Administering government funding of stem cell research is
largely the task of the National Institutes of Health where, as we
heard from Dr. Baldwin over a year ago, vigorous efforts have been made
from the very beginning to make cell lines available to characterize
their properties to support research, training, and infrastructure.
Today we are very pleased, and greatly honored, to have
with us the Director of the NIH, Dr. Elias Zerhouni, who has kindly
agreed to give us a progress report on the developing field of stem
cell research as it looks from the strategic center of federal support
and direction.
Dr. Zerhouni will make a presentation after which we will
have discussion. He has to leave sharply at 3:00.
Dr. Zerhouni, we are in your debt for taking the time to
give us the benefit of your observations and insights. Thank you very
much.
DR. ZERHOUNI: Thank you, Dr. Kass, and members of the
Council. It's a pleasure for me to be here and to share with you
what NIH is doing in promoting the field of embryonic stem cell
research in particular, and stem cell research in general.
What I'd like to do is really give you an overview of
what has happened since the implementation of President Bush's
policy on August 9, 2001, at NIH, how NIH is tackling the field of stem
cell research, what we are seeing as the major priorities and
challenges that we need to overcome as we speak.
I will not spend too much time on the promise of stem cell
research. I think this Council knows all of the implications of
cultured pluripotent stem cells and the challenges that are needed -
that need to be met to transform these cells in differentiated elements
that can serve in overcoming loss of function and help regenerating
lost function.
You know also the hierarchy of stem cells that go from totipotent to
pluripotent to multipotent stem cells. To this point, we've
never demonstrated a return from a pluripotent to a totipotent stem
cell, but there is one paper that indicates that that may be happening
in mouse stem cells. And we will talk about that a little bit;
we'll touch upon it.
But clearly, there are two known ways currently to make
pluripotent stem cells. One is obviously using the inner cell mass,
and one is using germ cells. This method was promoted by Dr. Gearhart
at Johns Hopkins and Dr. Jamie Thomson at Wisconsin.
So when you then ask yourself, what is so unique about
human embryonic stem cells, clearly two properties come to mind - the
fact that they have an unlimited capacity for self-renewal and culture,
and that potentially they can differentiate into any adult cell type
under the right conditions.
From the standpoint of NIH, as in any field of research
that begins to be funded at the federal level, there is an approach
that needs to be followed in the sense that research is done by people
with resources, with strategies.
And in the area of stem cell research, as soon as I became
director, I convened groups of scientists at NIH, and we tried to
define what the milestones should be and what the pathways should be
for this area of research to grow as rapidly as possible to fulfill its
promise.
And when we look at that, there are several phases that
need to be understood, and this is the underlying strategy that
supports our activities at this point. One, clearly, is you need to
build scientific capacity. Remember that prior to the President's
decision there was no federal funding for this kind of research, and,
therefore, the scientific capacity in the country was likely to be
underdeveloped. So the number one priority was to create career
development pathways, training courses, and, more importantly,
establish the infrastructure needed to do the research.
Then, when you look at the field itself, there is a need to prove
the long-term stability of the cells, characterize them very fully
at the molecular level, and understand both theirgenetic stability
and their stability in the host, understanding the differentiation,
the growth factors, the gene regulation - all of the events that
control that specialization.
End cell cycle control - obviously, these cells are
pluripotent, and one of the safety fears that everyone has is that they
would divide uncontrollably in the host. So we need to understand that
mechanism. And, obviously, since we're talking about regaining
lost function in a host, we need to understand cell host interactions.
To do so, one of the first actions that I took as NIH
Director was to create a stem cell task force at NIH. Prior to my
arrival, I think NIH had put together the beginnings of an
implementation policy.
But I thought that given the challenge and given the
wide-ranging spectrum of activities that the agency needed to get into,
I thought it was very important to elevate this activity at the level
of the director and to have a specific task force, including both
intramural and extramural researchers, to look at what were the most
important roadblocks to overcome, the most important avenues of
research to stimulate quickly, and where was the - where were the
pressure points, if you will, where we needed to intervene to
accelerate the field.
Well, obviously, the task force divided itself into working groups,
as you can see. And, no surprise, career pathways, resources, the
peer review, since obviously NIH is based on peer review and we
needed to have a cadre of competent reviewers. And in a new field
it's always a challenge. Tools and technologies, and obviously
the ability for us to reach out to the research community throughout
the country.
This stem cell task force has members who are both active in the
field or have knowledge in the field of developmental biology and
cell cultures and other fields and are advising the director through
the task force, which is chaired by Dr. Jim Battey.
As we looked at the challenges, it was quite obvious that
the immediate challenge for NIH and the human ES cell research
community was first to generate and characterize the distribution
quality human ES cell lines from the NIH.
It's very important to understand what
"distribution quality" means. It is not - a cell line being
available is not enough. A cell line having been derived is not
enough. It needs to be characterized, it needs to be quality
controlled, it needs to be expended, and it needs to be immediately
available to the research laboratories that need it.
The second was the need to stimulate more research on basic
biology, and the third was the training of investigators.
In the basic tools of the field, first and foremost, before
the use of stem cells and the approach of hypothesis-driven research,
we needed to have a cadre of confident and competent investigators in
the field. So those were the action lines that started pretty much
last year, a little bit over a year ago.
Now, when you look at the issue of lines, I know that the
public always tries to understand why is it that the President's
policy talks of 78 lines, and we talk about 12 lines that are
available. And there is always a little bit of confusion, so let me,
if you don't mind, give you the steps that are needed to go from a
derivation to a fully available line. And I think that semantics
sometimes get in the way.
But fundamentally, as you know, derivations occur when you
are collecting the inner cell line - cell mass, and you're
developing your primary colonies. And then, through subcultures, about
1,000 cells per well, you then expend these cell lines with about a 10
percent survival rate.
So as we know today, these cell cultures are not as
efficient or effective as we would like them to be. Then, you have to
basically then multiply these lines through multiple passages.
Well, obviously, because these cells have the potential differentiation,
you need - at each passage you need to characterize through molecular
marker studies and assure yourself that these have remained stem
cell lines. So one flask grows up to 100,000 cells, and one bank
that would be capable of fulfilling distribution needs requires
at least two billion cells. That takes about nine months to a year.
So, and when you distribute these cells, depending on the
distributor, there are about two million cells needed per vial, and
that means ready for distribution.
So when people look at this, they forget that on August 9, 2001,
there were 64, 78 lines, whatever the number of qualified lines
was at the exact time. We end up qualifying 78 sources, but to
make those sources expended and characterized to the point where
you need - you have lines available — takes about 12 months.
So when you look at the schedule, what we have accomplished is
about — last year there was one line that was widely available,
and today there are 12. And that's the reason between the 78
versus 12 numbers that you hear around.
There are other lines that are being expended as we speak.
There are agreements that are being signed. One has to remember that
these lines do not belong to the Federal Government; they belong to
their own derivers, and, therefore, are subject to intellectual
property agreements, which sometimes are easy to negotiate and
sometimes are not so easy to negotiate.
But I think our role was to increase as quickly as possible the
number of widely available lines that the researchers could have
access to to do the research. So the way we did this was by rapidly
awarding to organizations with entries on the NIH-eligible cell
line registry, funds to develop those lines into distribution quality
cell lines, and that's the difference between eligible and distribution
quality.
We gave them a two-year period of support. We granted
eight awards for a total of over $6 million, and we have about 12 lines
now ready for shipment, meaning in my criterion for that, which I
insisted be the criterion which is listed on the website, is you can
pick up the phone and get the line delivered to you within a measurable
matter of days.
So the program announcement will be reissued, because we
have now other sources of lines that are interested as they have
learned more about the expendability of the lines, interested in making
their lines commercially available.
In addition to that, I think there are many sources of
lines that have reserved derivations for further expansion as we learn
more in the research. So those are the infrastructure awards that
accomplish that.
Then, NIH has two means, really, of supporting research.
One is obviously training; the second is to fund investigator-initiated
research, which can be either spontaneously generated or can be
stimulated by NIH.
And the way NIH stimulates research is by issuing program
announcements or requests for applications around areas of research
that are either aligned with the mission of the Institute that issues
these RFAs and PAs, or are general announcements that the entire NIH
wants to support.
So one of the program announcements we made was to have
grantees develop short-term courses in human embryonic stem cell
culture techniques. We use the T15 mechanism, and it's supported
by 11 NIH institutes.
And basically, we have been able to award four of these.
These are courses that can take up to two or three weeks at certain
centers, and investigators can send their own core investigators or
personnel to these centers. And these have been extremely well
received by the research community.
We have also career development awards, career enhancement
awards for stem cell research specifically issued by several
institutions, which allow an investigator to spend up to 24 months with
$50,000 of direct cost exploring the field of embryonic stem cell
research as well as have training in the uses of stem cells.
And then, requests for applications are directed towards
areas of scientific priorities that the NIH feels need to be
stimulated. So we have stimulated multi-investigator teams. We have
infrastructure, growth and maintenance, research into
biochemical/molecular markers, and so on.
And we are trying now to establish exploratory center
grants that will lead to, then, formal centers that will have for a
primary mission the development of the applications and the basic
science of human embryonic stem cells.
Then, obviously, as you can imagine, there is a tremendous
amount of interest in rapid application in particular disease areas.
So institutes now have also issued very specific RFAs in avenues of
research that are deemed to be potentially fruitful in the short term.
So innovative concepts and approaches to developing
functional tissues and organs from NHLBI, plasticity of human stem
cells in the nervous system, and you can obviously imagine what these
applications area - recovery of cardiac function, the recovery of
neural function, recovery of endocrine function in the case of
diabetes, and obviously basic and applied stem cell for arthritis and
musculoskeletal disease.
The Institute feels that this is a high priority area,
given the fact that musculoskeletal disease and arthritis is emerging
as the number one cause of disability in an aging population. And
then, development and repair of orofacial structures.
I will just go quickly now in terms of some of the more fundamental
research - for example, NIDDK is promoting comprehensive programs
in beta cell biology, again a diabetic target. And then, obviously
looking at the genome anatomy of the hematopoietic stem cells, given
the genomic techniques that are available to us, and so on. So
I don't want to take too much of your time on details, but this
is the strategy that we have implemented.
In addition, we have also stimulated intramural research.
When this field started, you could basically identify one or two labs
at NIH intramural that had an interest and lead in embryonic stem cell
research. Dr. Ron McKay, through mouse embryonic stem cells, was
probably the most prominent.
Today we have nine laboratories in NIH working aggressively
and publishing in these areas. We have a much expanded interest as
cell line availability becomes more straightforward. So we knew that
that was a roadblock that needed to be overcome before anything else
could happen, and that's what we worked on.
In addition, through the identification of roadblocks by
the stem cell task force, one of the things that became very obvious
for us, for all of us in the field, was that unless we had a formal way
of characterizing and identifying the characteristics of each cell
line, it would be very difficult to compare experiments from lab A to
lab B to lab C.
And when we surveyed the field and we surveyed the level of
knowledge needed for characterization cell markers, molecular
characteristics, and so on, we realized that there wasn't a
worldwide agreement, nor was there a U.S. consensus about how to really
make sure that you're dealing with a stem cell, and how do you know
that over a period of time, and how do you compare line A versus line
B.
So we decided to establish an intramural research program
dedicated to the characterization of stem cell lines. We think that
this is an important investment, because it will give us for the first
time the ability to call a stem cell a stem cell in the real scientific
sense of the way - of the word.
So, in summary, what I think you can see between 2002 and 2003 is that
we have built the infrastructure, we have accepted investigator-initiated
awards, we had 21 applications in '02. Now remember, in NIH
parlance FY2002 goes from October 1, 2001, which was a month after
the announcement of the policy to September 30, 2002, and 27 applications
in '03.
We have awarded 25. We have also awarded 66 administrative
supplements. These are scientists who have already accumulated the
knowledge base to work with stem cells, either in adult stem cells or
mouse embryonic stem cells, and we issued a rapid series of
supplemental grants to allow them to work with human embryonic stem
cells.
So we have 66 additional grantees, or groups anyway, that
are able to use human stem cells.
We also had a research symposium in June that showcased
both the research conducted and supported by NIH, but integrated this
with the GM cell symposium that occurred here in Washington on
June 10th and 11th, to look at the entire field and try to understand
where the field was at the time.
On the research horizon, I think what came out of those
meetings is that the priorities today are the following. One is to
define, standardize, human ES cell culture conditions that obviate the
need for either mouse or human feeder cells. This is a priority. We
already have grants from investigators that have been funded.
We have several reports from groups that have been funded
by NIH looking at the characteristics of, what is it that gives a mouse
feeder cell the ability to grow human embryonic stem cells? What's
so special about that versus human feeder cells versus feeder-free
cells?
And there have been recent papers that indicate that you
could - once you understand the molecular drivers of that growth, you
can probably foresee the ability for us to develop, soon I hope,
culture conditions that will obviate the need for any feeder cells.
Then, the second is you can hear many - you can hear through the
scientific community those enabling tools and technologies to further
characterize stem cells as they become specialized cells are needed.
And that goes from specialized antibodies to identify very specific
markers of multiple different lineages.
But it's also a - there is also a requirement from the
scientific community to understand what the genetic events - what the
gene expression patterns are between a multipotent stem cell and the
one that becomes, let's say, a muscle cell or a blood cell.
And that is an area of very, very important research that
is ongoing, and there have been several papers published trying to
identify which genes are really turned on or off as you go from the
stem state to a non-stem state. And that essentially defines the point
number three, which is understanding the molecular pathways that
specify differentiation into these different specialized cells.
And then, obviously, we're not talking about cells just
in culture. They have to survive and function within the host, so that
many, many researchers are now focusing their attention on the critical
factors and conditions that drive the long-term survival of these cells
in the host.
And then, obviously, the one question that requires resolution
before any human clinical trials are even envisioned is the assurance
that we need - and I lwill let my colleague Dr. Mark McClellan talk
about it - to make sure that we can control cell division and prevent
the development of a malignancy or untoward complication.
Now, as we speak about this, you will hear that human
feeder layers are a very important step, and the research already
alluded to this. And the point here is that until recently all human
embryonic stem cells were grown on mouse feeder layers. And new
conditions are being established using human feeder layers.
We know from the Johns Hopkins group there was a recent
paper from the Technion Institute in Israel about developing
matrix-like substances that grow - that can grow without human feeder
cells, these human embryonic stem cells.
There was a publication - not a publication, but at least
an announcement from the Singapore company that you could do that.
There are at least unpublished reports of multiple groups having worked
and working on developing these lines.
Now, this is presented often as a sine qua non of further
research. I'm sure that Dr. McClellan will address the issue of
how you go about qualifying any cell lines that are grown or not grown
on animal or human feeder cells.
Now, but that is still in our mind an issue that requires work,
requires development. It will be much more desirable for us to
have understood the culture conditions without having the variability
associated with either mouse or human feeder cells, even though
that - from the conclusions from FDA and many others — indicate
that it is not a complete obstacle to clinical trials.
But in my mind, it's much more desirable not to have
that factor come into play at all if we can avoid it. But it seems to
be doable, and the research is ongoing.
Now, just quickly some important research results. The
group at the University of Wisconsin has been able to report on
homologous recombination in stem cells. For those of you who are not
familiar with that, it's the ability to essentially introduce
genetic material that will modify the genetic makeup of the cell, and
so that you can control - experimentally anyway - some of the
characteristics of these cells. That is an important step, we think,
in the field.
In terms of application, you have heard about the work from
Dr. Ron McKay primarily, showing a method that can drive the
differentiation towards dopamine-secreting neurons using these in an
animal model and demonstrating, in fact, recovery of function in a
model of Parkinson's disease - very, very promising avenues of
research here.
Then, one of the key areas of research, as I indicated before, was to
identify the key genes, the master genes that control the state
of stemness that we need to understand in terms of being able to
maintain cell cultures in the state that we wish them to be in over
the long- term. And this is a very important advance in the sense
that we are identifying now new genes.
One is nanog - after the mythological Celtic land of
eternal youth - which basically maintains the self-renewing properties
of mouse embryonic stem cells, and he has expressed these as inner cell
mass.
You couple that with other research ongoing in human embryonic
stem cells - Dr. Rowe at the NIH, Dr. Goldman, I think, is doing
similar research - where gene array studies of these cells are coding
down on a subset of genes which seem to be essential to the stemness
state.
So we are very hopeful that within a short period of time
we will be able to at least identify some of the key master genes that
are really at play in this type of cells.
Then, you see advances in terms of not just looking at the
stem cell state, but looking at a differentiated state and
understanding the pathway going from stem to a specific type of cell,
with multiple papers indicating recipes at this point. They are not
well understood.
But clearly, researchers are able to show that through
multiple approaches they can lead a cell to become, for example, a
myocyte that beats, just like a cardiac cell would, an endothelial cell
or a neuron with very specific functional measurements. This is the
most exciting part, if you will, of the research, because it indicates
that there is really proof of concept occurring in multiple subsystems
from the same kind of cells that are being worked on.
Duke University found that you can, in fact, grow a
progenitor - from progenitor cells myocytes. The group in Israel also
has shown that they can differentiate human embryonic stem cells into
beating myocytes. Clearly, both in adult stem cells and human
embryonic stem cells you see early results that seem to indicate that
cardiac function recovery can happen with stem cell therapeutic
approaches. That's very interesting.
Obviously, NIH supports research on many types of stem
cells. I'm focusing my comments on human embryonic stem cells,
obviously. But as you know, adult stem cells have been funded for
many, many years, particularly in the field of cancer and hematology
malignancies.
Just to give you a sense of the relationship, in FY2002, our investment
in human adult stem cell was over $170 million. In FY2002, which
is the very first year of stem cell research on embryonic human
stem cells, our total investment was about $10 million. This year's
investment is probably going to be $17-, $18-, $20 million in the
human embryonic stem cell research, and will be about the same number,
maybe $180 million, in adult stem cell research.
This is not counting animal stem cell research on mouse
embryonic stem cells or other types of stem cells. So as you can see,
the investment is growing. But, again, we hope for advances in all
fields of stem cell research.
We think that given the very early nature of our knowledge,
our understanding, and the limited nature of our understanding, it is
important to promote both areas of research, we think, at this point as
aggressively as we can.
You know about the multipotent adult progenitor cells that
Dr. Verfaillie has developed. It shows capabilities for self-renewal
and differentiation to many specialized cells. I don't want to
take too much time, but we can see glial stem cells that can produce
neurons in culture - very interesting paper from Nunez.
And satellite cells in muscle that have been identified as
adult stem cells that can divide in response to injury. And, clearly,
some early results that indicate that we can turn on these cells,
particularly in patients with muscle-wasting diseases.
At NIH recently there were stem cells identified in baby
teeth that have also quite a bit of potential. So, clearly, a lot of
things are happening. You can see also bone marrow stem cells that are
redifferentiated towards neural stem cells.
There are a lot of questions on the mechanisms by which
these occur. Some people feel that fusion might be the reason, rather
than just the stem redirection. So we'll see about that as we go
forward.
And we're providing also a large amount of information
to the research community on our websites.
I have material here that I could give you also - I
don't know if I'm okay on time - comments about the stem cell
sources and what is really happening in terms of stem cell sources in
the world right now, to just give the Council an idea of how these
things really develop and what happens in terms of research groups
using them.
So this is the paper that I wanted to mention. By the way, before
I go into that area, there's a paper from Hubner in Science
using mouse embryonic stem cells. They were able to generate what
appeared to be oocyte-like cells in vitro.
This is the very first paper on an animal system that
seemed to indicate that you can revert from the pluripotent state to
the totipotent state. It is not confirmed at this point. We don't
really know that the - what they look at and define as structures
resembling blastocysts in the petri dish are really blastocysts,
whether they have the potential or not.
If these experiments can be repeated in human embryonic
stem cells, there will be important implications for the creation of
new cell lines, generation of tissue, and so on. So this is a paper
that I think the Council should pay attention to, because it is quite
surprising actually to see these events in these oocyte-like - in these
culture conditions.
So in terms of cell sources, the first one that was
available was the H1 line from Wisconsin. It has about 300 vials in
inventory. It has shipped already about 105 orders. About 78 of these
were in U.S. institutions, and the rest was overseas.
And then, the cell characteristics are quite well defined,
and these cells seem to - these are the most healthy it looks like,
from the point of view of passages. These cells are in passage 22 and
are available immediately. So this is a very healthy colony that seems
to grow to the right number with a limited number of passages.
H7 is another line. They have just made this one available.
Obviously, it's now commercially available, has slightly different
characteristics. And H9 has - there are about 10 orders that have
been fulfilled with H9. These have all been made available in the
past four or five months, so it's not ? and, again, 10 orders
have been filled in.
The major other source is BresaGen from Athens, Georgia.
It has two lines available. These lines also have interesting
characteristics. You can see they have shipped eight total lines -
five in the U.S., one to the U.K., Israel, and Australia.
In the world of research in stem cells, the countries that
were just mentioned seem to be the most active, because there is a
heterogeneity in the policies of the different countries as you well
know.
From ES Cell International, there are five lines available,
and there were about 33 international shipments and 16 U.S. shipments
from this Australian source. We have a source in Korea. It has one
line. There were 20 shipments made, 17 to Korea, and three to the
U.S., all of which were sent to the NIH for the purpose of that - of
characterization of the lines.
UCSF has now one line commercially available and has 60 vials
in inventory, has shipped 19 - 15 to the U.S. and four to foreign
sources. And I guess those are the reports I wanted to give you.
And I'd be happy to take questions, Dr. Kass.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you very, very much, for a thorough,
illuminating presentation.
Let me remind the Council that Dr. Zerhouni has a 3:00
departure. Let's try to keep the questions brief, and no
speeches. The floor is open. Janet Rowley.
DR. ROWLEY: Well, I certainly speak, I'm sure, for the
rest of the Council. We very much appreciate your taking the time to
come and update us on the current status, and certainly the plans - the
present implementation and the plans for the future I think are ones
that many of us would applaud.
I have a series of questions. One of the first is for the
cell lines not established on feeder layers, this implies that there
will be new ES cell lines developed. And so the question is, these
would then not fall within President Bush's August 9th cutoff
date. And I guess, is that really so?
DR. ZERHOUNI: No. Actually, we did an inventory just
prior to a hearing to just make sure that we had all our facts
together. There were several sources - in other words, institutions or
companies - that had derived cell lines already by August 9th. They
have not exposed all of their lines to human - to mouse feeder cell
lines.
And, in particular, we have specific information on the
lines in Sweden - Gutenberg and the Karolinska - whereby the - as you
saw in the process, there is a process of - where between derivation
and exposure to mouse feeder cell lines you can freeze the lines and
keep them.
So there are at least those, which is about 16 lines, I
believe, that have not been exposed to either mouse or human cell -
human feeder cell lines.
And the reason given to us by the investigator is very
simple. They thought that the field was not mature enough, and the
understanding of the culture conditions was not there. So I think what
they're doing is they are basically doing experiments on
non-approved U.S. cell lines, non-approved by - for federal funding,
and they have reported, for example, experiments where they are trying
to use methods that will require neither human or mouse feeder cell
lines.
And they stated very clearly that once they master those
techniques, they will then apply them to the federally fundable cell
lines.
DR. ROWLEY: Okay. The next question is: what kind of
restrictions on intellectual property are attached to the lines? For
example, those from the University of Wisconsin, because I understood
that there were certain very important restrictions. And I know also
that NIH was trying to get some of those modified, and I wondered what
the current status was.
DR. ZERHOUNI: Right. Basically, the restrictions are,
one, the recipients cannot implant the provider cells in the uterus,
mix the cells with an intact embryo, or attempt to make a whole
embryo. The recipients and recipient institutions are free to publish
their research results as they wish. The providers retain ownership of
the original material. So WiCell retains ownership of the original
materials and any unmodified derivatives.
However, the recipient institutions own any new materials
and inventions its researchers create.
DR. ROWLEY: Okay.
DR. ZERHOUNI: Those are the agreements that NIH negotiated
with WiCell, and made those agreements transferrable to NIH-funded
investigators.
The provider of the cells can request a sample of any new materials
for internal research users. So WiCell could request samples from
the university to develop something new for their own research,
and is free to use that for its own internal programs - any newly
patented invention. So WiCell essentially is saying that if somebody
discovers something, they can use that for their own needs internally.
Other restrictions - basically, the main restriction is
that WiCell, for example, granted any PHS-funded nonprofit
investigators the right to use its patented technology, and granted a
royalty-free non-commercial research license to PHS-funded researchers
as long - and this is the real important statement - as long as the
agreements with such third parties were no more onerous than those in
the WiCell agreement.
And WiCell specifically excludes sponsored research where
the research sponsor gives commercial rights to a third party. In
other words, let's say, you know, Dr. Foster receives cells at UT
Southwestern, and then using those cells and whatever discovery he or
she makes, goes to a third party and conveys commercial rights without
WiCell being - having its right respected.
So those are the interesting issues I think that govern
that.
DR. ROWLEY: Can I ask you just one more question, which
there is - in Britain, the MRC is trying to develop a cell bank, and I
just - presumably, it would be parallel with the cell bank that's
being developed at NIH. And is there any collaboration or coordination
of efforts?
DR. ZERHOUNI: Okay. Let's be careful. NIH is not
developing a cell bank. It's developing a cell characterization
unit. In other words, we will develop the reagents, we will have the
lines that we will compare, and we will do a full catalog of all of the
characteristics that researchers tell us are very important. Make the
reagents available, make the antibodies available. We're not going
to be distributors of cell lines as we speak.
The British model is a little different. They have a
commission, obviously, that approves or disapproves requests, and all
lines developed under that policy have to be deposited in the cell
bank.
To my knowledge, to this - I think last week there was an
announcement that the first line had been successfully derived. And,
therefore, those derivers have the obligation to deposit that in the
British bank for wider distribution. So they're assuming, if you
will, the infrastructure role that we granted to the sources here,
they're assuming it within the cell bank.
Any collaborations we communicate constantly. The most
important areas of collaboration, from my standpoint, are we need to
understand the characteristics of cell lines. We need to exchange
information. We need to have a more formal way of understanding what
the field is doing worldwide. And those are the things that we're
doing with the MRC and others.
DR. ROWLEY: Thank you.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Michael Gazzaniga.
DR. GAZZANIGA: I just think it's important to get the
scale down here. So in terms of current embryonic stem cell research,
the investment at NIH is .1 percent of your budget. It's extremely
small. Would you - what would be your guess that - should more cell
lines be made available through a change in the current policy? How
fast do you think that would scale up to be more in line with adult
stem cell vessels?
DR. ZERHOUNI: I don't think the limiting factor is the
cell lines. I really don't. I really think the limiting factor is
human capital and trained human capital that can quickly evaluate a
wide range of research avenues in stem cells.
So I am not of the opinion that the number of stem cells -
you can see the shipments, how many have been requested, and there are
many more available. So I think it's more important to stimulate
the field at the human capital level in my mind, and it will take - as
you know, it takes time. You have to have fellowships. You have to
have centers.
You have to have young post-docs that really get involved in the
field and have new publications and ideas and grants of their own
for that to grow. It's not something you can, you know, drive
top-down, I don't think.
DR. ROWLEY: And just in that vein, your slides showed that
there were three post-doctoral fellowships awarded in FY02, and out of
four applicants. So this highlights, I think, the problem of human
capital.
DR. ZERHOUNI: I think you're right. But we see a lot
of is in the applications that are granted, R01 types or program, what
you see is that post-docs tend to be funded through those grants
directly, without going through a fellowship route. But I think
you're making a good point, and we want to stimulate that.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Bill Hurlbut.
DR. HURLBUT: I want to clarify something. The 16 cell
lines - I think that's what you said that were not grown on mouse
feeder cells - are those part of the original 70 designations?
DR. ZERHOUNI: That's correct. I don't know if
it's 16 or 12. I mean, I can give you the exact information, but
it's about that number.
DR. HURLBUT: These were essentially disaggregated and then
frozen.
DR. ZERHOUNI: Right.
DR. HURLBUT: Doesn't it stand to reason that given the
months preceding this policy there might be thousands of such
disaggregated embryos out there?
DR. ZERHOUNI: Do you mean between August - prior to August
1 - August 2001?
DR. HURLBUT: Everybody saw it coming, right?
DR. ZERHOUNI: I'm sorry?
DR. HURLBUT: Everybody saw it coming, that there might be
such a policy that would say, "No further derivations."
Isn't it possible that there are quite a few cell lines out there?
DR. ZERHOUNI: I wasn't at NIH at the time. But I can
tell you that the NIH staff that worked on that truly canvassed the
world and made sure that whatever lines there was documentation, there
was informed consent, there are some - so it may be that there are
lines out there that have been derived before August 9th, but they may
not fit all of the other characteristics - informed consent, no
inducement, and so on.
I don't know the answer to your question, but I
don't think there are thousands out there that were waiting for the
policy to come out.
DR. HURLBUT: I shouldn't have said thousands. It was
a hyperbole.
But let me ask you two other specific questions. As you
characterize these cells and understand the molecular signals, and so
forth, obviously the hope is that you can derive them without creating
embryos somehow back - pull them down or something. Is there any
special program that NIH is looking at in an effort to bypass the moral
problem? And would it be reasonable to fund such a specialized effort?
DR. ZERHOUNI: I thought you were the program to do that
here.
(Laughter.)
I think Dr. Kass is in charge of that program.
(Laughter.)
No. I don't think there is a particular program that
scientifically could look at the moral or ethical issues. There is no
question that we have in every one of our human subjects and animal
subjects a - you know, a very strong moral and ethical review based on
institutional review boards or the - you know, the typical ethical
considerations that you attach to research.
But I think this one is not something that NIH is looking into,
feeling, and I said that in jest, but I think it's serious.
I think all of the institutions that have looked at this issue would
be the National Academy of Sciences, the Institute of Medicine.
The administration feels that this is a debate that really needs
to happen in forums like this one.
I don't know if I'm answering your question.
DR. HURLBUT: Well, I didn't really mean debate it. I mean,
I think everybody agrees if you could de-differentiate an adult
cell down to an ES cell, a pluripotent cell, without making it totipotent,
that you would have a moral solution to the derivation of ES cells.
And I just wondered if there's - if the science might be ripe
for a special program to seek those avenues and what you might call
morally derived ES cells.
DR. ZERHOUNI: Well, that's the adult stem cell program in
some ways. That's what Dr. Verfaillie is trying to do by using
adult stem cells. And then, going back in history and trying to
de-differentiate them, that's really the - now that I understand
your question, I mean, that is the hope of those investigators.
Cord blood was another source that is used that does not have the
same moral connotation as human embryonic stem cells derived from
embryos.
So yes, actually, if that's - I'm sorry. I
didn't quite understand your question. But absolutely, there are -
as you can see, there is a tremendous amount of activity in adult stem
cells and understanding the differentiation pathways.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I have a couple of questions as well. In
part, you give the impression that we're still at a very early
stage in the road from the bench to the bedside. And you've
indicated at least some of the obstacles that - some of the steps that
would have to be taken and some of the obstacles in the way.
One of the things that you didn't speak about was
research addressed to the immunoprotection problem. And I wonder
whether there are special efforts in that area with respect to stem
cell research.
And, second, notwithstanding the fact that we seem to be at
a very, very early stage in this research, you do indicate that there
is some work going on to look for fairly immediate clinical payoffs,
say in the area of cardiac disease.
I wasn't absolutely clear that that was with human ES
cell - with cells derived from human sources or not. But how do you
square the sense that on the one hand we are at a very, very early
stage, and on the other hand the field might be ripe already for
certain kinds of clinical trials. What message should we take away on
that particular point?
DR. ZERHOUNI: I think I may not have - I may not have been
clear, but what I refer to as "host cell interactions" imply
immunological responses. We need to understand those. We need to
clearly make sure that either the transplant is not destroyed, nor is
the transplant left to grow in an uncontrolled fashion.
So I didn't mean to ignore those issues. They are
there, and they need to be addressed.
Now, science, as you can imagine, advances by leaps and
bounds, and investigators have passion and sometimes believe there is a
shortcut or not a shortcut. So that the two areas of research that I
think are driven to applications are those that, through what I call,
you know, recipes or lucky strikes or understanding of pathways,
whatever it is, try to find an application, a path to application, in a
proof of concept fashion, usually in animal systems.
And that's really what researchers tend to do. In
other words, you try to build from the solid ground you're at, and
then you go out and build an island, and then you fill in the blanks.
The fill in the blanks are still in the basic region that I
described. Even if you showed today that there was a recovery of
cardiac function through some pathway, you still will have to do the
demonstration that you understand the host cell interaction, you
understand immune response, you understand all of the safety
considerations, and so on.
So I don't mean - in my view, they are not incompatible with each
other. At least the characterizations I gave are very compatible.
What happens typically in biomedical research, you have
multiple avenues, and that's the strength I think is to let people
demonstrate that. Your question about, is it in humans - adult stem
cells have been reported to have been used in humans in Italy, in
Brazil, from bone marrow sources. So adult sources that have then been
implanted in the heart, it is not clear, really, that it is the
implantation of those adult stem cells that has accomplished the
result.
We've had embryonic stem cells injected in rat hearts
that have been infarcted that showed recovery. But those are proof of
concept experiments.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you.
Bill May.
DR. MAY: At one point you talked about arcing back from
pluripotent to totipotent. Is a reversal from pluripotent to
totipotent in effect the creation of a new cell line?
DR. ZERHOUNI: That's a very, very difficult question
for me to answer, because there's one experiment that showed that,
at least on the surface in a mouse model, that you had structures that
seemed to form not only a totipotent cell but an oocyte-like
structure. So that - a blastocyst-like structure.
So the question is: are you creating a new cell line, or
are you creating a new organism - is not clear in that. But this is a
very early area of research at this point.
DR. MAY: It does bear on the August 11th cutoff date I
guess, doesn't it?
DR. ZERHOUNI: It could.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Michael, and then Janet.
DR. GAZZANIGA: Just a followup, because I think your point
on the human capital is important. Sort of in the labs in various
biomedical institutions, there's an unwillingness on the part of
many young investigators to go into this field because of the
uncertainty of its political scientific status.
And so there's an interaction here where if it was
clear that this program is going to move forward, it was clear that
there are going to be more lines developed, because certainly more
lines are going to be needed for a variety of biomedical issues, that
the human capital aspect of it might be solved very quickly.
Certainly, that is what happens in all other fields which
are not constrained by the sort of - these sort of political moral
issues. But if there's a new technique, gene expression work - as
you know, overnight it remade the field, the DNA chips, and so forth.
So if it was clear what the policy would be in the future,
wouldn't your guess be that the human capital part would be solved
rather quickly?
DR. ZERHOUNI: Again, that's a question that goes from
a premise that there is an issue. Clearly, when you look at the
increase in publications and names on publications, you see a lot of
new entrants. I wasn't at the first meeting at NIH two years ago
about these issues, but the symposium that we had in June, 600 people
all supported in some fashion or another. How you compare that to
another field, I don't know.
The other anecdotal piece of information is I visited a few
sites, and they don't report a dearth of post-doc candidates for
their programs. Once they're established, you see - if you go to
Jamie Thomson, he has a tremendous amount of required - or demand for
trainees to come into his program as post-docs.
And so once you have an established program, it seems like
you are able to attract people. If you go to an institution where
there's no leader, no established program - I knew from my
experience at Hopkins, John Gearhart, he had his pick. I mean, he
could choose whoever wanted to come. So I think it's the program
that drives the young investigators to enter the field - program with
funding, with available resources.
Is the fact that cell lines are under the policy a driver
of going and not going into the field? I don't have the answer to
that. But obviously, since this is an issue of federal funding,
private funding is also available, an avenue that is not prohibited, as
you know. And the biotech industry - there was a recent report that
shows that there is still quite a bit of activity in the biotech - and
growing activity in the biotech industry for stem cell research.
So I'm not sure that from the standpoint of human
capital that there is a monofactor here that you can identify, saying,
"Well, this will prevent for sure the growth of human
capital." I can't answer that question in the affirmative.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Last question before we let Dr. Zerhouni
go. Jim Wilson.
PROF. WILSON: Do you have any estimate - it would have to
be crude, I assume - as to how much money private sources are putting
into stem cell research?
DR. ZERHOUNI: Actually, there's a paper that was
published just recently, and I can give you a copy of it. And this is
not an NIH study, but I understand that there is spending of $200
million per year in stem cell research, embryonic stem cell research,
and 1,000 FTEs, full-time equivalents doing research worldwide.
About 60 percent of those are in the United States, about
15 in Europe, and 27 percent in the rest of the world, primarily
Australia, Singapore, Korea, Japan. I have that reference if you want
it.
PROF. WILSON: Thank you.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Actually, if you can take one more, Janet
had been on the list - if you'll make it brief.
DR. ROWLEY: I just want to make a question and a comment.
The comment is actually related to Kay Hubner's paper in Science,
and I think that it is important to recognize that this is work
that was done in the mouse. And we've had a great deal of difficulty
in terms of translating success in the mouse and other animals into
humans, so this is going to take some time.
The question is you mentioned that there is a program at
NIH now for characterizing these cells, and I wondered what institute
it was housed in.
DR. ZERHOUNI: The Institute - NINDS, neurological
diseases, under - actually, it's associated with Ron McKay's
laboratory, because we feel he has the best expertise in that area.
DR. ROWLEY: Thank you.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Dr. Zerhouni, thank you very, very much for
a wonderful presentation and very frank discussion. We really
appreciate your presence. Thank you.
(Applause.)
CHAIRMAN KASS: As we learned from Dr. Zerhouni, we are at
a relatively early stage in our journey from basic stem cell research
to therapeutic benefits. And as one looks ahead down this road, we see
in advance the important role that the FDA is going to play in
verifying the efficacy and the safety of any eventual stem-based - stem
cell based therapies.
In recent months, the FDA issued its guidance regarding
xenotransplantation, the introduction into human beings of materials of
animal origin or derived from materials having contact with animal
tissues.
Almost immediately, there were press reports, many of them
grossly off the mark, about what this guidance might mean for the
possibility of future clinical trials using material derived from the
Presidential cell lines.
To help us separate fact from fiction, and, more
importantly, to help us understand how the oversight and regulatory
activities of the FDA might eventually figure in the area of stem cell
based therapies, we're very fortunate to have with us Dr. Mark
McClellan, who is the Commissioner of the Food and Drug Administration.
Dr. McClellan, many thanks to you for taking the time to
help us understand this important aspect of the road that we are on
that will take us from the bench to the bedside. Welcome.
DR. McCLELLAN: Thank you, Dr. Kass. And all of you on
this distinguished Council, thank you for inviting me here today to
discuss the role of the FDA in helping to make new safe and effective
xenotransplantation treatments available, including potentially
valuable stem cell treatments.
FDA's job is to protect and advance the public health,
and one of our primary responsibilities involves helping safe and
effective products reach patients and consumers quickly.
Our Center for Biologics Evaluation and Research, which
I'm sure many of you are familiar with - goes by the acronym CBER -
has the lead in FDA for regulating xenotransplantation, including
emerging cellular therapies. FDA regulates cellular therapies under
broad authority from the Public Health Service Act and the Federal
Food, Drug, and Cosmetic Act.
Under this authority, FDA has taken many steps to foster
the development of safe and effective stem cell therapies, while
assuring appropriate protections for human subjects involved in the
research.
As you know, xenotransplantation is a set of procedures
that includes the transplantation or implantation into a person of live
cells from non-human animal sources, including human cells that have
had ex vivo contact with live non-human animal cells or tissues.
And as you just heard from Dr. Zerhouni, recent evidence
suggests that transplantation of cells and tissues may one day provide
many important therapeutic benefits for diseases such as
neurodegenerative disorders, diabetes, many other conditions involving
organ dysfunctions and cellular dysfunctions. Because the potential
health benefits may be considerable, it's appropriate that there
are many clinical research and development studies going on now to
better characterize the risk and benefits of these potentially
important treatments.
Xenotransplantation products, under the Food, Drug, and
Cosmetic Act are treated in accordance with our statutory provisions
governing premarket development. And so they are subject to FDA review
and approval. Investigators of such products should obtain FDA review
of proposed xenotransplantation clinical trials before proceeding.
In addition to providing necessary assurances of protection
for human research subjects, FDA takes many steps in its regulatory
oversight to help researchers and product developers avoid mistakes and
translate good research ideas into safe and effective treatments as
efficiently as possible.
And in an area as complex and with as many practical
uncertainties as stem cell research, this regulatory guidance can be
extremely helpful for obtaining the most public health benefit from
basic science insights. For example, applied research conducted at
CBER has been instrumental in improving our understanding of safety
issues associated with xenotransplantation.
CBER is engaged in a range of scientific investigation of
safety issues, including on known and emerging infectious agents,
immunological issues, transfer and differentiation issues, and others
that will need to be overcome for the safe and effective use of
xenotransplantation products.
The results of these studies have helped CBER in its safety
assessment, including assessment of risk and the development of better
diagnostic methods and standards to assess risks. CBER researchers are
continuing to develop assays appropriate for safety monitoring and are
working with sponsors and collaborating with other government
scientists in the development of these assays.
In addition, to improve our regulatory policies related to
xenotransplantation, CBER working groups are analyzing data and events
and developing and proposing strategies for appropriate studies, for
risk assessment, for prevention, for communication, and agency response
or regulatory action, such as requests for more data from sponsors or
for particular product assays and the course of clinical investigation,
or, when necessary, the placement of clinical holds on clinical
investigations.
We discuss all of these proposals and strategies with our
advisory committees when needed or at public meetings as appropriate to
make sure we've got full opportunities for public comment on the
most effective way to regulate these important but complex new areas of
medical technology.
CBER has also developed a mechanism for the systematic and
regular evaluation of the scientific and clinical literature relevant
to xenotransplantation as well as careful scientific evaluation of the
submissions that we get in our xenotransplantation product files.
If you put all of that together, that not only the research
studies but what we see in terms of the studies, the details of the
studies that are ongoing now, not just the published studies but the
ongoing work, this amounts to the most extensive data available on the
practical application of stem cell technologies.
We have a xenotransplantation product review or working
group, which consists of the review staff responsible for the review of
xenotransplantation submissions, the clinical product and pharmacology
and toxicology reviewers, as well as our veterinary staff.
They all meet regularly to discuss application of the principles
that are in our relevant regulations and guidances to review and
discuss current scientific and medical data and literature relevant
to xenotransplantation, to review and discuss the current status
of xenotransplantation applications that are before the agency,
to discuss, the unique issues that these products may present and
to highlight areas of concern where further expert advice and solicitation
of public opinion, and outside expertise may be needed.
This working group structure gives us an approach - gives us a
consistent and up-to-date review approach for xenotransplantation
applications, and it helps us recognize patterns or trends or common
problems that may be associated with xenotransplantation products,
and, again, a highly - a new and high emerging research area. And
it should be communicated to xenotransplantation product developers
and other interested parties in a timely way.
Our data evaluation and management process is linked to
this regulatory process, and it's applied during regulatory
decisionmaking and product and policy design at the agency. We have
augmented our own experience with cell therapies by sponsoring and
participating in a large number of open public meeting and workshops,
both domestic and international, that focus in whole or in part on
cellular therapies.
These activities are essential for both sharing information
and receiving public input on relevant issues. To make sure that our
insights and our assistance reach those involved in planning stem cell
trials effectively, FDA has also been proactive in educational
partnerships, workshops, and guidance development.
And this work collectively includes discussing preclinical
pharmacology and toxicology studies, and good clinical practices, and
product characterization studies - all difficult issues that need to be
addressed effectively in these emerging sciences.
All of this work is intended to support our goal of helping
clinical research and development of stem cell therapies proceed as
efficiently as possible. And our extensive experience with cell
therapy clinical trials, and the processes for obtaining effective
outside expertise, has helped a wide variety of clinical studies
involving xenotransplantation of stem cells proceed with public
confidence about safety and without avoidable costs or complications
for the subjects involved.
With respect to the details of our oversight of clinical
xenotransplantation studies, as in other areas, FDA allows INDs -
investigational new drug applications - for these trials to proceed as
long as they don't pose unreasonable risks to the human subjects.
Reflecting both the flexibility of our risk-based
regulatory framework and the energy of this important new research
area, well over 1,000 separate INDs for all forms of cell therapies
have been implemented over the past decade. Hundreds of subjects,
hundreds of human subjects, have received experimental products
comprised of animal cells or human cells that have had contact with
animal cells since the early 1990s under FDA oversight.
Hundreds of additional human subjects have been treated
with a human skin cell product called Epicell that was grown on mouse
feeder cell layers. FDA discussed this Epicell product at a public
advisory meeting in January 2000, and we agreed with the advisory
committee's conclusion that the safety data concerning the use of
the well characterized mouse feeder cells in this case was sufficient
to allow clinical trials to proceed generally.
And that is, the lesson here is that when murine cells can
be characterized as in this Epicell product, then as a general
regulatory matter there is no overarching need for monitoring and
surveillance with respect to this particular safety concern.
FDA is continuing to support the development of safe and
effective cellular therapies, and we work directly with sponsors to
help ensure that all promising therapies can be clinically evaluated in
an ethically sound, scientifically rigorous, and efficient manner.
The agency evaluates each individual product on its own merits.
FDA's regulations, our guidances, and our policies, provide
useful information on safety and product development issues to help
sponsors interested in development of cellular products.
CBER's regulatory guidance and regulations are
continuing to evolve, and this is appropriate to ensure that the
continued advancement of a very dynamic and growing field is matched by
continuing advancement in our regulatory guidances to support it.
The hundreds of patients that have been treated in clinical
trials in which non-human animal cells have been implanted or infused
directly, or in which human cells that have had ex vivo contact with
animal cells have been administered, have been treated using protocols
that meet FDA safety standards.
For Phase I or early clinical trials, the most important
aspect of safety is the demonstration of the products not contaminated
with adventitious infectious agents, including viruses, bacteria,
fungi, and so forth. This safety criterion needs to be met, and it has
been met by most FDA-regulated products, including biological products,
before they can be used in the clinic.
For all cellular products, including human cells, non-human
cells, animal cells, or human cells that have been exposed to such
cells, which often can't be tested for sterility prior to
administration because they can't always be stored, FDA has pursued
a flexible approach that does not compromise patient safety. In
particular, FDA has allowed sponsors to administer the cells based on
the results of interim, in-process, bacterial and fungal sterility
testing in which the absence of infectious agents is demonstrated.
The sponsors then perform sterility tests on the final
product, though results are frequently not available until after the
products have been administered. A positive sterility test on the
final product is quite rare if the interim tests have been negative.
But if the result is positive on the final test, the results of these
sterility tests are used to inform subsequent patient treatment.
To address potential viral contaminants, FDA requests that
prescreening of components that could introduce viral infections
occur. For example, before using porcine tests in humans, sponsors
have been asked to demonstrate that the pig tissue that they use
doesn't produce infectious porcine endogenous retrovirus.
In the case of Epicell that I mentioned a few minutes ago,
the manufacturer was able to use standard techniques to show that the
transmission of murine viruses to the co-cultured human cells
shouldn't be a problem. As a safety net, the recipients of animal
cells or human cells exposed to non-human animal cells are monitored
for unexpected infectious diseases.
When human cells are transferred from one human to other
humans, whether or not animal cells enter the equation, FDA asks that
the human cells, and, if possible, the donors of those cells be
thoroughly tested for known viruses. So we've overseen treatment
of thousands of patients with human cells or with animal cells, or with
human cells that have been exposed to animal cells, in which the
transmission of infection has been tightly controlled.
Human embryonic stem cells are just one type of living
human cells among the many somatic cellular therapies that FDA
regulates. Most of the issues that will be involved in the production
of human embryonic stem cells for clinical use are shared with these
other cell therapies. Of course, there has been a high level of
interest, as I've heard in my time here today, in the research
involving particular human embryonic stem cell lines that are listed in
the NIH registry.
Just about all of these cell lines - all of these cell
lines have been in ex vivo contact with live, non-human animal cells or
tissues. And the exposure of such human cells to animal cells, though,
represents only one of a large number of issues to be considered in
evaluating the development and use of human embryonic stem cells.
Among the many further technical challenges to be addressed
are the manufacture and testing of the human embryonic stem cell
products, preclinical testing of human embryonic stem cells in animals
to show potential clinical benefit as well as potential toxicities,
appropriate clinical trial design issues, and appropriate followup of
human subjects treated with human embryonic stem cells.
And our regulations and our guidance has to address that
whole panoply of issues. Recognizing the potential importance of new
cellular therapies that may be derived from these cells, FDA extended
an invitation to each of the derivers of the NIH registry cell lines to
meet and discuss critical issues pertaining to the derivation of these
lines to help us assure safety in the clinical studies.
We discussed FDA expectations of safety, and we gained
insights from the derivers on how they can best meet those
expectations. We also gathered information from the derivers of the
HES cell lines regarding specific methods of preparation and
propagation of the cells to add to our understanding of the
manufacturing of these novel cell lines.
FDA is in the process of publishing a series of guidance
documents through a notice and comment process to assist sponsors and
investigators interested in conducting clinical trials in the field of
xenotransplantation.
These documents are providing reasonably detailed and
timely pragmatic guidance to sponsors regarding xenotransplantation
product safety and clinical trial development, including specific
recommendations for how FDA believes that studies can be conducted
efficiently and with adequate safety assurances.
The guidances that we published so far include a guidance
for industry for human somatic cell therapy and gene therapy published
in 1998, a guidance for reviewers on instructions and templates for
chemistry, manufacturing, and control of human somatic stem cell
investigational therapies, published in the past year.
And, in addition, earlier this year we published a new
xenotransplantation guidance for industry entitled "Source Animal
Product Preclinical and Clinical Issues Concerning the Use of
Xenotransplantation Products in Humans." All of these guidances
are available online at FDA. We also recently just this past month
published a draft guidance for our reviewers to go along with this
xenotransplantation guidance for industry.
These guidances provide information to sponsors interested
in developing products that include animal cells or exposure to animal
cells. All of the human stem cell lines, as I mentioned earlier, are
subject to this guidance.
And the goal here is to provide a comprehensive approach
for the regulation of xenotransplantation that efficiently addresses
the potential public health and safety issues associated with
xenotransplantation, and at the same time to provide guidance to
sponsors, manufacturers, and investigators regarding
xenotransplantation product safety and how to conduct clinical trial
design and monitoring.
One of the many issues that's addressed in the guidance
is the development of human embryonic stem cells that have had ex vivo
contact with mouse cells in clinical trials. In our guidance, we note
that this guidance is relevant to all of the stem cell lines, all of
the human embryonic stem cell lines that have used mouse feeder cell
layers, and so fit into - this fits into the definition of
xenotransplantation used in our guidance and in our broader public
health service guidances.
FDA has had a number of meetings, as I said, with the
derivers of these stem cell lines, and what the guidance focuses on is
that certain precautions are required to maintain the safe use of any
xenotransplantation product. In the case of the existing embryonic
stem cell lines, the precautions include appropriate testing of cells
in mice if the mouse feeder cell layers continue to be used for
adventitious agents.
This testing is manageable and is readily available and
achievable using current technologies. So our xenotransplantation
guidance provides some specific, useful steps that sponsors can and
should take to address safety concerns. A sponsor who wishes to
investigate a stem cell product derived from existing human embryonic
stem cell lines in a clinical trial may need to demonstrate to FDA that
the stem cell line is free from infectious agents, including the murine
infectious agents.
Given the current technologies available as described in
the guidance, this should be feasible without undue burden. The same
recommendations apply to other xenotransplantation products that
contain human cells with a history of co-culture with non-human animal
cells.
So overall we are very committed at FDA to evaluating each
specific product that comes into us on a case-by-case basis. We try to
augment this with guidance to make it as straightforward as possible.
And this is important, because in a world where most clinical trials
and most products that enter clinical development fail to show benefit,
each new individual proposed clinical study might still provide a
crucial step forward.
There are multitudes of patients who have yet to benefit
from the biotechnology revolution, and as a public health agency we are
committed to making sure that every experimental product to be tested
in humans is as safe as possible, with the ultimate goal of getting
safe and effective products as quickly as possible.
I want to thank you all for listening to me today, giving
an overview of FDA's regulatory and guidance activities in this
important area of emerging science, and I'd be pleased to answer
any questions that you all might have.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you very much.
Dan Foster, are you on the way to - no, I'm sorry.
Let me start and, first of all, thank you, really, for a
very comprehensive and helpful account. And I emphasize that because
I'm going to ask a sort of flat-footed and dumb couple of
questions. If I wanted to say, Dr. McClellan, the take-home lesson, if
I wanted to sort of put it in a nutshell, would be xenotransplantation
involving stem cells in contact with murine cells, we have experience
with that, and we are careful.
We know what to do, and it's - while it's something
to be paid attention to, it's not an insurmountable obstacle or one
that deserves extra special attention.
DR. McCLELLAN: We've certainly had experience,
successful experience, in thousands of patients in documenting the
safety of cells that have been exposed to animal feeder cells, mouse
feeder cells, and the like.
The other take-home lesson that I think is important is
that while this is a very important emerging area of technology, this
is a quite complex cellular therapy that presents many new safety
issues as well as effectiveness issues that have to be evaluated.
And we've got multiple parallel efforts to try to
assess and help manage and address the different risks that are
involved in stem cell therapy treatments, so that we can hopefully as a
result get more rapid development of stem cell therapies that really
work, and that can be used widely.
But as is the case with all of the biologicals, especially
complex new technologies like this, ultimately it's nature that
determines whether the products are really going to benefit the needy
if we can - and we need to unlock, through a whole - evaluation of a
whole host of complex safety and effectiveness issues, whether they can
- whether those benefits can be demonstrably given to patients. And
we're still very early on in that process.
And the mouse feeder cell issues are one area where we have
a regulatory process in place to address it, but there are many other
safety and effectiveness concerns that remain to be addressed, and that
we're working hard to help product developers address effectively.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you. And let me just very quickly -
am I right in thinking that cells grown on human feeder cell layers
would be subjected to - have to be subjected to the same kinds of -
DR. McCLELLAN: Yes, they do. They are incorporated in our
same xenotransplantation guidance, and they are subject to the same
kind of evaluation of potential exposure to adventitious infectious
agents. They need to go through the same kind of testing procedures
and the like.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you.
Questions or comments? Dr. GÓomez-Lobo.
DR. GÓMEZ-LOBO: This is a question out of total
ignorance. I have great confidence in FDA. In fact, I think it's
a great institution and -
DR. McCLELLAN: I do, too.
DR. GÓMEZ-LOBO: Well, I'm glad you do. But here's
my question. I'm also convinced that human knowledge is very
limited, and you speak with great confidence about identifying bacteria
and viruses, etcetera. Could it be the case that at a nano level there
might be problems, say, with some of these products that we cannot yet
detect?
In other words, what I'm thinking about is, what's
the next step when we go into, say, gene therapy and that kind of
thing? Is FDA going to be able to detect any problems with that?
Should we be cautious, or should we just trust FDA and just rush
forward? In other words, it's a very general, sort of prudential
question that I'm raising.
DR. McCLELLAN: Yes, that is a good general question. FDA
is not usually accused of making people rush forward, but glad to hear
that's -
(Laughter.)
- the perception in at least some corridors.
These are very challenging new technologies, and
there's a great scientific concept out there and a great
potential. And that's something that generates a lot of media
interest, and the like, and holds out a lot of hope. I think, you
know, with some reason that we are going to be able to bring new
benefits, important new benefits, to many millions of patients that
don't have effective treatments available today.
But as with so many other areas of emerging technologies,
moving from ideas that seem to work well even at the proof of concept
stage, to treatments that demonstrably can be shown reliably to be safe
and effective in patients is very difficult. And we are early in that
process now for these complex biological treatments.
I have talked a lot about some of the issues related to
transmission of infectious diseases related to feeder cells, because
that's gotten a lot of the attention. But you're absolutely
right that there are a host of other important safety issues and
effectiveness issues that also need to be much better understood before
these treatments can be used reliably and confidently by the public to
improve the health of the public.
And that's what this investigational process is really
all about. That's why we have a comprehensive guidance for the
INDs involving stem cell therapies and many other types of therapies as
well, so that we can conduct those studies in a way that's - that
relies on the best-available knowledge as to whether we're
presenting patients with unreasonable risk.
We can do it in a controlled setting, so that we can learn
from the latest studies and add to the state of knowledge that exists
from what goes before. And then we can modify our research protocols
and guidances and research activities accordingly.
But this is a difficult process. You know, a lot of people
talk about the fact that it takes over a decade for going from - for
something as simple as a small molecule drug, just a simple chemical,
from the time that it's first identified and people first suspect
that it's going to have a benefit in patients. It can take well
over a decade to go from that proof of concept to a product being
commercially available to the public.
It's a long, complicated process. And these complex
biological treatments and cellular therapies are far more complex and
have far more potential interactions and consequences that are not well
understood than a simple small molecule drug.
So this is an ongoing process, a careful one, and I
don't think we're rushing headlong into this. But at the same
time, I want to make sure that our regulatory staff is apprised of all
of the latest science, is working closely with researchers and others
involved in product development, to make sure that we're making the
most of the available knowledge, both for the sake of the patients that
are involved in these clinical studies and for the sake of creating the
knowledge base we need to get safe and effective treatments to patients
as quickly as possible.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Rebecca Dresser.
PROF. DRESSER: Thank you very much for your overview. I
guess a comment and a question. I do think it's interesting there
has been so much in the press about this particular issue as a
potential safety issue as I think you've observed, compared to
other safety issues that this technology might present such as tumor
risk and, you know, the ability to channel the cells into the -
DR. McCLELLAN: Pluripotency.
PROF. DRESSER: - appropriate tissue, and all of those
things. So it seems that in some ways you and your colleagues are
being forced to address this issue, at least publicly, with more
attention than these other issues. And I'm glad to hear that
you're thinking about these other issues.
But I guess just to play devil's advocate, isn't
there a risk with xenotransplants that there is an undetected animal
virus, an undetectable virus we don't even know about, that could
be present and transmitted if the cells are grown on animal feeder
layer, that wouldn't be a risk if you had, you know, the absence of
a feeder layer or a human feeder layer? And so wouldn't it be nice
if you could avoid that risk?
DR. McCLELLAN: It's certainly possible that there are
completely unknown, you know, animal viruses that could potentially be
transmitted to humans.
We just haven't ever seen them observed, and that's
why an important part of our guidances here is followup on the patients
who are involved in these studies, so that as we learn more over time
we'll be able to identify any problems that might subsequently
emerge in the patients that have been brave enough to participate in
these early studies, and to make sure that we can let the patients know
if there is new technology that becomes available that ought to
influence their subsequent treatment.
But there are - you know, those kinds of hypotheticals
exist in each and every one of these many complicated aspects of stem
cell therapy. There are the potential for human cells to harbor
completely unknown illnesses that might also be transmitted.
It might even be easier to transmit to humans than in
animals, and even for cells that are harvested and used in treatment
without the use of any kind of feeder layers. There are still a host
of other issues, as you identified, that could present important safety
concerns.
We do have to make our regulatory decisions and allow
studies to go forward under uncertainty. You know, these issues are
never going to be fully resolved, and I think that the best job we can
do is try to make sure we're apprised of all of the latest science,
all of the, you know, concerns that might impact on potential risks and
benefits for patients involved in the studies, and then do as careful
of a job as possible in making sure that the best and latest knowledge
is applied as we move forward in this important area of emerging
science.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you. Permit me one very quick
question. You've indicated how your experience with
xenotransplantation in other areas gives you some confidence that you
might not have received with this aspect of it.
Is there any precedent and experience for dealing with the
specific kind of risk of teratoma or tumors that are associated with -
well, possibly it could be associated with, say, residual,
undifferentiated stem cells that might accompany a population that have
been differentiated?
DR. McCLELLAN: That's certainly something that
we're monitoring for here. And some of the - and in many of the
earlier human stem cell - I mean, human cellular studies that - or
cellular studies more generally, they were differentiated cells
involved.
And so it raised different kinds of issues than a
pluripotent or an undifferentiated stem cell might. It's
definitely something that's on people's minds, and we're
watching carefully. We don't know of any specific evidence of
important problems there yet that we haven't accounted for, but we
are monitoring it carefully.
I think that's one reason we pay so much attention in
these protocols to understanding and tracking the exact conditions
under which the cells were derived, because that can potentially have
an impact on how they might differentiate and act in - after
implantation subsequently. It's just an area where we have to
watch closely, because it's not very well understood.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Well, Dr. McClellan, thank you very much
for being with us, for your presentation, and for your very good work.
DR. McCLELLAN: Thank you.
CHAIRMAN KASS: We're adjourned for 15 minutes.
(Applause.)
(Whereupon, the proceedings in the foregoing matter went off
the record at 3:35 p.m. and went back on the record at 3:55 p.m.)
SESSION 4: STEM CELLS: MOVING RESEARCH
FROM THE BENCH TOWARD THE BEDSIDE: THE ROLE OF NONGOVERNMENTAL ACTIVITY
CHAIRMAN KASS: Could we get started, please?
Our fourth session of the day is on stem cells, moving
research from the bench to the bedside, the role of non-governmental
activity.
Progress in stem cell research proceeds not only with
government support, important though such support surely is. Biotech
companies are vigorously active in the field both with embryonic and
non-embryonic cells, and disease related and other philanthropic
foundations are actively supporting such research.
Our monitoring of stem cell research would not be complete
without some review of what is going on under these auspices. This
afternoon we are fortunate to have with us representatives from two
leading biotech companies very active in stem cell research and from
two leading private philanthropic research foundations who will tell us
something about the strategies they are pursuing to develop stem cell
based experimental therapies, how close they are to developing such
therapies, and what obstacles currently stand in the way.
As they have all been asked to avoid commercial pitches,
criticisms of competitors, or advocacy for or against legislation
currently pending before Congress, I would ask Council members to
refrain from prodding them to do otherwise or to ask them for
investment tips or other privileged information.
(Laughter.)
CHAIRMAN KASS: Our guests in order of presentation are
Dr. Thomas Okarma, who is the President and CEO of Geron Corporation,
a company that emphasizes embryonic stem cell research and formerly
supported the work, among others, of John Gearhart and James Thomson,
and that has solid patent positions in this field.
Second, Dr. Theo Palmer, who is an assistant professor in
the Department of Neurosurgery at Stanford, a stem cell researcher
working on nervous system applications, and today representing the
Michael J. Fox Foundation for Parkinson Research on whose scientific
advisory board he serves.
Third, William Pursley, President and CEO of Osiris
Therapeutics, Inc., a company in the forefront especially of
mesenchymal stem cell research, with many strong patents in this area
and exploring clinical applications for cardiac therapy,
immunomodulation, among others.
Finally Dr. Robert Goldstein, who is the Chief Scientific
Officer of the Juvenile Diabetes Research Foundation International, an
organization with extensive activities, including a recently announced
program of training grants to draw top young researchers into the stem
cell field.
Gentlemen, thank you very much for taking time from your
busy lives to travel here and to give us the benefit of your knowledge.
We'll start with Dr. Okarma.
DR. OKARMA: Thank you, Dr. Kass, for the opportunity to
spend some time with you today. It's a visit that's probably
overdue.
You asked me to address three topics: our progress in the
development of products based on embryonic stem cells; our thoughts
about immune tolerance and immune rejection of the transplanted cells;
and, lastly, impacts of various policies on our progress in the private
sector in 15 minutes. So I will be terse and not do justice to either
question, but try to give you an overall picture.
By way of background and the take-home point, clearly human
embryonic stem cells are a special case, and this Council has certainly
debated the issue of the moral status element of that specialness. But
I would argue that there are two other elements to its specialness.
First, the biology which is unique amongst all the cells in
the universe and its promise for medical therapeutics.
And thirdly and not well understood, this paradigm is in
the industrial sector, not in the academic sector, and that has some
very important implications to the development of this technology, and
I'll try to make those points as I go through.
Geron, as you may know, has been at the forefront of human embryonic
stem cell research since 1995 when we first entered the field.
We funded the work done in Jamie Thomson's lab, John Gearhart's
lab, and Dr. Pedersen's lab at UC-San Francisco, and as such,
we're the movers technically, technologically and proprietarily
in this entire field.
We have spent over $70 million on this technology, most of it
since 1999 after the cells were derived. That's a number against
which the NIH disbursements pale by both absolute and relative terms,
and there are some reasons for that that I will touch on.
So let me move first then into our development plans and
our developmental progress. First, let me talk a bit about some of the
infrastructure basic science components that we've established.
You've heard a lot of discussion about how these cells
are grown on mouse feeder cells. We've established a scalable way
to grow these cells not only off of feeder cells, but now with a fully
qualified set of reagents. These can be scaled virtually limitlessly.
We've established ways to scalably produce seven
different differentiated cell types from each of the lines that we
have. So one line now makes seven different kinds of cells that
we'll describe in a moment.
We have verified the stability of the embryonic stem cell
line in culture. Some of the lines have been grown continuously for
over three years, more than 600 population doublings, and there's a
manuscript in press now describing four lines studied over that period
of time that demonstrates that the karyotype, surface marker,
differentiation potential, and gene expression level, the stability of
these undifferentiated cell lines grown under our culture conditions.
We have had a preliminary meeting with FDA, and we have now
qualified two of our cell lines for human use. They have passed every
assay the FDA has asked us to submit them to, even though they are
appropriately classified as xenogeneic. I will return to that later.
In collaboration with Celera, we've established an
annotated genomic database of undifferentiated embryonic stem cells.
One hundred fifty thousand EST sequences have been sequenced, and the
physical clones are deposited in Menlo Park.
This is fully annotated. We can query this database. We
understand what the gene expression pattern of stemness really is and
what genes are up and down-regulated as these cells differentiate.
That has been a crucial foundation for our ability to learn how to
produce differentiated cell types.
And lastly, we, too, have developed methods to genetically
modify these cells.
Now, the cells that we have learned how to make are
characterized by their normalcy. Virtually every cell that we have
made, without exception, expresses completely normal cell biology. So
the islet cells we have derived express insulin, and they express
insulin in a dose-dependent fashion as a function of glucose
concentration in the media.
The oligodendrocytes we have made myelinate spinal cord
cells in animals.
The dopaminergic neurons we have made secrete dopamine.
The cardiomyocytes that we have made express all of the
molecular markers consistent with their being human cardiomyocytes.
They respond in appropriate dose response fashion to cardioactive
drugs.
The bone cells that we have made in Roslin have
absolutely normal biology. The techniques to look at the bone
formation these cells make in vitro by X-ray diffraction are
absolutely spot-on normal.
We are close, but have not yet derived chondrocytes. That
is also a project funded at the Roslin Institute.
And lastly, bone marrow cells, hematopoietic progenitors,
which again are absolutely normal in their cell biology, producing all
three cell lines normally.
Now, some of these cells have progressed into animal
studies, and I'll detail those in a moment. The first take-home
point to make is that we have never ever seen in any single animal the
formation of a tumor. That is because we only put in differentiated
cells.
The issue about growing the cells in the undifferentiated
state is to keep them from differentiating. So when we remove them
from the undifferentiated culture conditions, these cells want to
differentiate, and we have molecular markers to prove that they are
differentiated.
We also have cytotoxic technology capable of detecting one
out of ten million cells that are undifferentiated should we need to
apply that later on in scale-up.
So which cells are in animal models? Well, first the
hematopoietic cells are in Canada, and we've demonstrated now
engraftment of these human embryonic stem cell derived hematopoietic
cells in the appropriate nude mouse model, which repopulates the
animal's peripheral blood. That has important implications not
only for an alternative source of cells for bone marrow
transplantation, but for the second question regarding immune
rejection.
We've made dopaminergic cells which are engrafting
robustly in animal models of Parkinson's disease. This is a huge
tissue engineering challenge where these cells must penetrate to the
cortex of the animal to completely correct the Parkinsonian defect.
We have not yet demonstrated significant behavioral
improvement in the animals. We are still working on that, but the
cells engraft robustly and, again, without tumors.
The cell type that is most advanced is the oligodendrocyte,
and there will be a very exciting manuscript later this year from our
collaborator at UC-Irvine, Hans Keirsted, in which we have transplanted
the human oligodendrocytes into a model of spinal cord injury and not
only show statistically significant functional improvement of the
animal, but we have shown at the histologic level that the animal cells
are remyelinated by the cells that we have injected.
Lastly, we are now in animal studies in three different
labs with cardiomyocytes injected into animal models of heart failure
and myocardial infarction. Again, no tumors; again, the cells engraft,
and we have histologic evidence that these cells begin now to
communicate with the animal cell in situ in the heart.
So the work is early. There is much more to do, but we are quite
pleased with the progress that we've made thus far and would
predict that the oligodendrocyte will be the first cell to enter
the clinical environment, and that an IND, if all goes well, could
be submitted in late '04 or early '05, which is quite a
bit ahead of most people's expectations.
At this point our second cell type into the clinic would
probably be cardiomyocytes, based on the data set we have today.
As part of that first question, you asked about obstacles. There
are clearly many, many technical and scale-up obstacles that we
yet have to traverse, but those we think are fungible. Our major
problem is funding. We have done two reductions in force in the
company since a year ago. We are one third of our former size.
The political uncertainty of this field not only turns off
investors, but also turns off the other source of funding for biotech,
which are pharmaceutical partners, who at this point in time are
completely uninterested in this field.
Turning to the issue of immune rejection, first, there are
a number of very exciting, new immunosuppressive drugs in clinical
development. So I think the field of immune suppression through
pharmacology will dramatically advance, and we hope to take advantage
of that.
Secondly, it's now known that pure effector cell
transplants, in other words, not organs that are contaminated by the
donor's immune system, are much less immunogenic in animal models
and in a few cases in human than is an entire organ transplant, again,
auguring well for the size of the problem of immune tolerance.
Thirdly, there is some very exciting work that we are doing
not yet published, so I can only hint at it, that establishes the human
embryonic stem cell as being unusually unique in its immunologic
properties. It has inherited some of the immunosuppressive properties
that are existent in the blastocyst.
Why is it that the mothers never immunologically reject
what is an allograft, the blastocyst? Well, there are specific reasons
for that, and those reasons are, in fact, inherent in the
undifferentiated embryonic stem cell.
But in terms of our strategy, notwithstanding the prior
points of how to control immune rejection, we have one that makes a lot
of sense, and that is hematopoietic chimerism. We know from the bone
marrow transplantation work that if a patient who gets a bone marrow
donation from me will be completely tolerant to receiving a kidney
allograft or a heart allograft from me. The prior bone marrow
transplant has tolerized the patient to the antigens in my tissues.
We also know now from work done at Stanford that patients
who are status post whole organ transplant patients can be completely
weaned off of immunosuppressive drugs by giving them a mini bone marrow
transplant taken from a donor with the same tissue type as the prior
kidney donor.
This is the strategy we plan to use out of the box in our clinical program,
having now established that we can derive hematopoietic progenitors
from one of the lines. A dose of those cells should tolerize the
patient to any effector cell transplanted into that individual derived
from the same stem cell line. So that is my answer to Question
2.
Lastly, you asked me to address issues of policy that
affect our ability to develop the programs. Certainly the fact that
this is primarily an industrial paradigm helps with regard to FDA.
I've worked with Kathryn Zoon and Phil Noguchi since the
mid-'80s in my prior company in cell therapies. Many of the points
to consider that are now published came from our mutual collaboration
in the early work in the '80s and '90s in cell transplantation.
The pathway to regulatory testing and commercialization
with this technology is clear. There are some idiosyncracies, it is
true, but we understand the pathway, and we have thus far been very
pleased with our early interactions with the agency.
The NIH has a different issue: to recognize the primary
role in this field that has been played by industry. That is not their
fault. They were prohibited by law from funding this arena. That is
how we got into it. That is how we got ahead of everyone.
But that has some special implications. For us, as I
manage Geron, we have two platforms: the stem cells that we're
talking about today and a cancer program based on telomerase. And the
management and depth of technology in both of those platforms is hugely
different with, I think, important consequences both for patients and
for policy makers.
On the cancer side, we have sent the telomerase gene to hundreds of
laboratories all around the world. We have many, many collaborators.
Many people have worked independently of us on telomerase. So as
we move into the clinic with our anti-cancer platform, our scientific
understanding of how to use telomerase as a vaccine, how to develop
drugs that inhibit telomerase, how to use the promoter of telomerase
to drive oncolytic viruses is very, very deep.
That reduces risks to patients and increases the likelihood
that our first entré into the clinics will be successful, as we are, in
fact, seeing with our telomerase vaccine program in the clinic at Duke.
That is to be contrasted with our program in embryonic stem
cells, where we have a small number of collaborators, the bulk of which
are frankly either in California funded by us and the State of
California, or in other countries, the U.K. and in Canada.
So there's no question that when we think we are ready to
move into the clinic expeditiously and cautiously, having checked
all of the appropriate boxes the FDA wants us to check, we will
still be skating on relative thin ice in terms of the science behind
the product that we are testing in people.
So the narrower science base in embryonic stem cell
research increases risk of technical failure and exposes patients to
greater risk from the experiment.
The second point under policy I would make sort of
illustrates a problem that's about to happen. We've heard a
lot about the issue of are the old existing lines okay. What about new
lines? Will they be different? Will they be better?
Well, the existing lines, as you've heard today, can be
used in human clinical trials, but they will not last forever, we
don't think. There's no reason to assume that. And these
current lines, all of them, were derived on mouse embryonic layers and,
as such, are appropriately classified as xenogeneic transplants with
increased risk to patients and a much increased burden on the sponsor
to follow these patients for life after they receive these cells.
That's appropriate.
So the FDA is urging us appropriately to derive new lines
that not only have not seen mouse feeders, but whose entire pedigree is
from reagents that are qualified for human use and that the entire
process of derivation be under GMP, good manufacturing practices.
We will be successful in doing this. We will generate such
a line very quickly, very soon, and then the implication of the current
policy, however, is that arguably this would be the best line to use
and to qualify and to share, but because it was derived after 2001 in
August, the NIH will be prohibited from studying it.
And what are the implications for when we take that cell
line into the clinic? Will we be unable to share that cell line either
from a funding or a technology perspective with the NIH?
So those are my brief comments on the three questions. We
are unquestionably the leader in the field because of circumstances
that enabled us the freedom to operate, and in some ways, particularly
with regard to FDA and scale-up and GMP, that's good for the field.
But in terms of getting this technology embedded rapidly in the most
sophisticated biomedical community in the world, we are amiss.
Thank you.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you very much.
I think we should hear from all four people together and
then have questions.
Dr. Palmer, please.
DR. PALMER: Thank you, Chairman Kass, members of the
Council.
I'm here on behalf of the Michael J. Fox Foundation,
and I was asked by the foundation and by the Council to give a little
bit of an overview of the foundation's efforts in targeting
Parkinson's disease. So I'll talk to you a little bit about
Parkinson's disease, or PD, and then also the role of stem cells in
our portfolio; finally, a little bit about what we've learned in
three years of trying to use stem cells in this very targeted
application.
The foundation is relatively new. As you know, it started
in late winter of 2000. The goal of the foundation is to match funding
to scientists who are pursuing every avenue of research to find a cure
for Parkinson's disease.
Our secondary goal and my primary goal as an advisory board
member is to make sure that this funding reaches the investigator with
speed, and one of the things that we've found that has really
speeded the research is to short circuit some of the delay in an
investigator coming up with a good idea and then getting the funding to
that research.
So we're targeting Parkinson's disease, and our
efforts in stem cells are quite narrow compared to many of the
applications that you'll hear today. But Parkinson's disease
is the accelerated loss of a dopamine neuron in the adult brain. These
neurons control movement, and the loss of the neuron does not allow the
brain to initiate movement.
So one of the strategies, of course, is to replace those
neurons with a stem cell derived dopamine neuron population. This is
part of our research effort.
The other part, and in fact, a larger part, is to
understand the disease itself and then prevent or augment the remaining
system, prevent degeneration.
So the brain doesn't replace these neurons, and the
stem cell biology really comes into play when you've got a patient
who's missing a substantial portion and is now dysfunctional in
terms of their ability to move.
It's a slow disease. It progresses over years, often
decades. There's a declining quality of life, and the disease is
lethal. It affects more than a million people in the U.S. alone, and
there's no cure.
In the context of PD, stem cell technology has promised two
significant advances that are not available in any other context or
form. A single culture can create enough dopamine neurons to cure the
entire population of PD patients if we can get the technology to work.
This may not necessarily be true in practice, and we heard one reason
why this might not be true, if there are limits to the ability to
expand the culture. But a second reason and perhaps one that's
not very well explored by the Council is the ability to use ES cell
lines as a tool for research and particularly as a way of making
authentic human dopamine neuron for drug screening or high throughput
assays of some sort or another.
Now, this is a very important point I'll come back to
later.
I'd like to go over the portfolio of the Fox Foundation
and just give you a picture of the research that's being funded in
PD by a private sponsor of research. To date the foundation has funded
28 million in Parkinson's related research overall. This is since
our inception in late 2000.
Twenty percent of that fund has gone to stem cell research
of one sort or another, and it's a carefully chosen array of stem
cell strategies in mouse, non-human primate, and human embryonic stem
cell systems.
At the time the grants were funded, so beginning in 2000,
very few investigators had either the ability or access to human lines,
and by default rather than by design, at this point except for one
study, all of the studies that we fund use approved lines.
Now, this will change in the near future, and we anticipate
in the next rounds that we may see a significant increase in the
request for funding on non-approved lines. And in part, we feel this
is driven by the FDA and the requirement for lack of adventitious
agents and just the ease at getting a cell line product through the
approval process if it has been isolated without the use of the animal
cell lines or animal products that were not characterized.
So we have seen in the past several years a significant
increase in requests for stem cell funding in the review of our funding
portfolio and our upcoming funding efforts so that we're attracting
new scientists, people who have not really used stem cell technology in
their research into the area of Parkinson's disease.
So as a tool, it's an attractive tool for a scientist
who knows Parkinson's as a model, but now wants to expand their
repertoire to use a tool that seems to have much higher promise than
the current strategies they're using. So we're seeing an
increase in new researchers in the field.
In our annual fast track funding, this is an independent, investigator-initiated
pilot study where investigators send in unsolicited proposals.
In 2001, we had roughly 200 applications in Parkinson's in general.
Ten of these were stem cell applications. The total request at
that point was just a little over a million dollars.
In 2002, we had a similar number of total applications, and
our requests went up. We had 12 requests. Two and a half million
dollars would have funded all of those stem cell requests.
And in our pending round in 2003, we have over 200 total
applications that we're anticipating, and more than 20 of these are
stem cell related. And over time, we're seeing a significant
increase in both the application of stem cells to cell replacement in
Parkinson's, but more interestingly, a recognition of their utility
as an in vitro source of authentic human neurons, where people
can study drug effects or the genetics of Parkinson's disease
itself. And these are studies that are not necessarily targeted at
replacement, but more at understanding the disease and then coming up
with a non-stem cell basis for treatment.
So the foundation's experience has given us some
insights into what a moratorium would mean in terms of research on stem
cells and also what the current policy on federal funding is. We have
a diverse portfolio. We have studies on embryonic stem cells as well
as fetal stem cells and adult stem cells. Many of these projects were
funded early in our round because the advisory board felt that stem
cell strategies had very high merit, and one of our first efforts was
in creating cell lines that could be used for transplantation.
So we have now and unusual point of view where we can
actually compare the preliminary results from a variety of efforts.
After two years of focused research, we can see that if this was a foot
race and we were comparing adult stem cells to fetal stem cells,
there's no competition. There really is no race involved at all.
We have data generated from our funded research that shows
that the adult tissues are not presently a robust source of cells,
particularly when it comes to creating dopamine neurons in our focused
effort to treat Parkinson's disease.
Optimists would say that there's still potential, and
there is still potential in leveraging the adult stem cell to our goals
as a Parkinson's research foundation.
But to contrast the progress made in the same time frame
with embryonic stem cells, it's a fragile hope at best to say that
in the immediate future the adult cells hold the promise that we had
hoped two or three years ago that we would see in the research.
So it is now clearly demonstrated in vitro, and when
we started this was still an unknown, but now quite well established in
several of our funded laboratories that the human embryonic stem cells
can make authentic dopamine neurons. What's left now is the
practical application of making this work in a transplant, and these
are ongoing studies.
So I mentioned a moment ago the proliferative potential provides
a means to treat many individuals from a single isolate. Unfortunately
our research experience is now encompassing a number of cell transplant
strategies. The farthest along of these is fetal tissue transplantation
where you harvest from the fetal tissue an authentic dopamine neuron
and transplant that into a Parkinson's patient.
One of the key observations now that we have had blinded
clinical trials tell us that there may be additional problems that were
unforeseen, a key point is the presence of a fairly robust immune
response in many of these patients, and this is something that cannot
really be ignored.
I have to take my hat off right now and put on my own
personal hat so that I'm no longer a foundation representative
here. I work in adult stem cell biology, and it's my hope that we
can make endogenous neural progenitors do the job of an embryonic stem
cell, but in studying the behavior of newborn neurons from endogenous
precursors, we have just run into a very serious impediment that
involves the immune system.
The immune system, if activated in the context of a
developing neuron, essentially shuts off this early progenitor's
ability to make a functioning neuron, and if we're looking at cell
transplantation as a way to cure Parkinson's disease and the cell
transplants are not well matched to the host or if there isn't a
strategy for making the host tolerant, then having just a few lines is
going to be a very serious impediment to applying the existing lines to
clinical research.
So getting back to the foundation portfolio, there is another
benefit to looking at additional lines of ES cells. Putting cell
replacement aside and now looking at the technology that stem cells
in the culture dish provides, there's a body of research that
has been going on for nearly 20 years or more, and that's the
technology of transgenic animals and, more recently, the use of
embryonic stem cells in creating mice that carry very discrete genetic
mutations.
Now, one of the strategies that we as a foundation trying
to cure Parkinson's disease contemplate is the value of having
embryonic stem cells that actually carry the genetic profile of a
Parkinson's patient, and although we're not talking today
necessarily about nuclear transfer technologies, this clearly pops into
mind as a strategy for making an in vitro authentic dopamine
neuron population that is identical to a class of patients that are
presenting a certain disease phenotype.
So the disease is diverse. It presents early and progresses rapidly
or it can present very late in life when a tottering gait is really
commonplace in that age bracket and, therefore, it's not as
big of an effect.
But this variability is really as variable as human life
itself, and so having 11 or 12 lines from normal individuals does not
allow us to access to that technology, and the creation of drugs that
would more readily target a type of dopamine neuron depletion or a
disease context.
So the targeted manipulation of genes in an embryonic stem
cell is another aspect of this that is now just entering science, and
the ability to introduce genes into human ES cells or to target
mutations to an individual cell population obviously gives you a
potential way around this, but this is a technology that's novel.
Nuclear transfer technology would circumvent that. It
gives us the baseline from which to understand how to create ES cells
through a non-embryonic process, but there has to be a way to get from
Point A to Point B, and this is where the additional lines and the
exploration of new technologies comes into play.
I'd like to finalize or just summarize here with an
overview of current research concerns. In the near term, human ES
cells are already undergoing efficacy trials in preclinical models. So
human ES cells, as we heard earlier, are in animals, and there's
great hope that we'll see that they're at least as effective,
if not more so, if the immune complications can be overcome than the
fetal tissue transplants that are so commonplace now.
To move forward with these lines, there are several
limitations with current policy that seem to inhibit our progress as a
foundation that's trying to promote cure or intervention in stem
cells. The first is what I've targeted mostly in my presentation,
and that's the heterogeneity of these current cell lines and
limited numbers.
So if you start with a few lines and the cell lines are
heterogeneous, some will make, in our experience, a lot of dopamine
neurons, and others really seem to be impeded in their ability to
respond to the same cues provided in the same dish.
So in this preliminary data that we see presented in summarizing
our funded work, we're observing that one line will work beautifully
well in a paradigm. Another line is basically eliminated from the
study because it has an inability to make enough dopamine neurons
to be useful.
So heterogeneity in the performance of an individual line
may limit what can be done with the existing lines, and of course, the
absence of genetic diversity within the existing lines, the absence of
a representation of disease genotype is limiting in what can be done at
the research bench in understanding the disease process, and of course,
heterogeneity in HLA matching may be a very serious concern, and it
will require additional complexity and treatment if we don't have a
matched donor and host or fairly stringent strategies for tolerizing
the host to the incoming cells.
Finally, I think there is this question that's been
touched upon quite broadly today, and that's the presence of
adventitious agents in the existing lines and whether or not the
foundation's research can transition quickly to clinic really
depends on how well an existing line can meet FDA requirements.
And I've heard that this is possible, but it also
places an extreme burden of follow-up on a funded project that makes it
difficult for a private foundation to fund.
So in the absence of federal funding, is private support
really up to the task? And I think really to summarize this, the
private foundation's focus is to pilot research, to find very good
strategies or promising strategies, and that's where our funding
really runs out. The NIH has typically stepped in at that point, after
the pilot study stage, and proceeded with the larger experiments, the
validation, the expansion.
If the foundation funds unapproved lines, that has nowhere
to go at this point. So there is a serious concern that though we may
be able to use private funding to our benefit, that there will be a
stall or serious delay in getting this to clinic.
So these burdens loom particularly large to us as a foundation
as the Baby Boomers age, and the number of Parkinson's patients
increases. The social and economic costs go well beyond just the
Parkinson's community, and I think the economic costs in terms
of the cost of clinical care is just one part of it. The economic
cost in delayed development of drugs because we cannot use in the
public sector privately funded ES lines for drug screening or nuclear
transfer lines for screening, lines that carry a disease phenotype.
I think this is an economic burden that our society has to
face and one that should be very carefully weighed in the Council's
discussion.
I think the foundation very much appreciates the ability
and the invitation here to give our experiences, and we understand that
you have a very difficult task ahead of you as counsel to the
President, and we thank you for this opportunity.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you very much, Dr. Palmer.
Mr. Pursley, please.
MR. PURSLEY: Yes. Thank you.
Thank you for having Osiris here. We've been involved
in mesenchymal stem cell, adult stem cell research for about 11 years
now. Our technology came out of Arnie Kaplan's lab and was
acquired from Case Western at that time, and we've been solely
focused in that area since on several applications.
Our development strategy is very straightforward. It's
tissue engraftment and regeneration without immune suppression.
Let me back up a moment, too, to set the record straight.
In some of the earlier media documents, it has me as a Ph.D. I'm
not a scientist or a physician. I'm a businessman, and if my
technical explanations aren't satisfactory, most of what I'm
going to report on is published or we believe will be published in
acceptable peer review journals, and in fact, correct me if I'm
wrong. This panel should have been provided privately an embargoed
manuscript that will be submitted.
Okay. Our technology is the universal application, and
I'll explain that term in a moment, of adult MSCs, or mesenchymal
stem cells, with no in vitro manipulation. In other words, if
you will, these very smart cells do what they do in vivo. We
simply put them in there and let them go, so to speak. And I'll
define that in some of our programs.
What I mean by universal application, we started out as an
autologous cell company and later found out that we can provide from
any donor, unrelated, HLA unmatched, any donor these cells to any
recipient without immune rejection.
And in fact, what you'll see in our first program, we found
them to be immune selective, T cell-suppressive in some instances.
So we are now working on what would be literally an off-the-shelf
product for whatever the indication may be.
The process we use under anappropriate IRB protocol, again, we
take an unrelated, unmatched, volunteer adult donor. We take a
bone marrow aspirate, a whole marrow aspirate from the iliac crest,
bring that back to our manufacturing, and then we will culture and
expand that currently to about 1,000 doses from one donor.
We are going through an expansion now that's not a
change in process. It's an expansion of process. We will
ultimately get that to about 10,000 doses per single donor.
A very nice advantage of this is that we don't have to
expand cells indefinitely. We can go back to new donors. Currently
one donor can provide bone marrow six times in their lifetime. These
are usually younger people because the younger you are, the more MSCs
you have.
We will then cryopreserve the finished product in liquid
nitrogen, and at that point it is ready to go to clinic for use. We
also now have done stability and potency testing to have that stored at
a lesser temperature over X period of time in certain containers so
that it's easier for the hospitals to use.
The safety of these cells in the universal application has
been proven now. Allogenic MSCs have been given to 56 human beings.
Thousands of various animals models have been used, rats, mice, goats,
dogs, pigs, and baboons.
This has been done in conjunction with the NIH, Hopkins,
Cedar-Sinai, Texas Heart, et cetera. And at this point, over several
years now, there has been no possibly or probably related serious
adverse events associated with MSCs. This includes no infusion or
direct administrative toxicity. There's no ectopic tissue
formation. In other words, they aren't differentiating in
cartilage in the heart, on the knee, et cetera, and there is no tumor
formation at this time.
And, in fact, we have two lead programs in Phase 2, which
by definition from the agency standards, the FDA, means we have met
their safety standards for biologic in order to move into Phase 2. So
we are very happy to report we see and now the agency sees these cells
as safe, allowing us to move into Phase 2.
Now, the precise mechanism of action regarding this
universal application is not known. All we do know is apparently there
are certain cell surface characteristics of the MSC that do not elicit
an immune response, and in fact, as I said, as you'll see in our
first indication, are actually immune suppressive.
As far as how close are we to developing therapies, our
first two programs are in Phase 2. The first is peripheral blood stem
cell transplant support for patients with hematologic malignancies, and
again, forgive me if you're very familiar with this pathology, but
basically if you have a leukemia, a myeloma, a lymphoma, et cetera, a
blood cancer, you receive total body irradiation and/or chemotherapy,
with the goal of obliterating the bone marrow because that's the
source of the cancered blood.
These patients then need to receive a transplant. They
receive a peripheral blood transplant of hematopoietic stem cells so
they can produce enough platelets to clot and white cells to fight
infection and red blood cells for volume, and gain a natural state of
hematopoiesis.
And those cells usually come from a sibling or a parent.
The problem is for these patients who have no choice but to go through
this, ten percent and up to 20 percent can actually die from this
procedure, with the vast majority of graft versus host disease, and
that means the hematopoietic stem cells are rejecting the recipient.
And so what we did in a Phase 1, in a multi-center Phase 1,
is provide MSCs, mesenchymal stem cells approximately four hours prior
to the transplantation with, first of all, in a Phase 1, the primary
goal for a biologic is always safety, and you look for secondary
efficacy trends, which are great if you reach them, and we did in a
very big way.
What we did is reduce significantly graft versus host
disease. So we believe there was a T cell suppressive effect in
working with the patient or with the hematopoietic stem cells not to
reject the patient, if you will.
Now, the reason we say selective T cells suppressive, these
Phase 1 patients are now out three years. They have also had a
significant reduction in return of the cancer, which means we did not
suppress the T cells fighting GVL, graft versus leukemia.
This was a very big concern. If these are immune
suppressive, are we going to hurt the patient's own ability to
fight the cancer coming back? And what we've seen at three years
out is this is not only not the case. They have a less incidence of
return of the cancer.
So with those data we are in Phase 2. This is an IV
preparation. The status is we should have Phase 2 data reportable in
time Q3 of '04.
If that goes well, we will go into a Phase 3, and this
should be available to the hematologic malignancy population if things
go as planned, and Murphy has a way of raising his head in this
business and always will, but even with some of those considerations,
we would hope to be commercially available to humans by 2007 with this.
Just after that program, a very similar situation but a
different mechanism of action, which is the amazing thing about these
cells. That was a T cell suppression effect to reduced GVHD. In a
similar sense there are infants to adolescents primarily who don't
have matched donors who will receive cord blood transplants, and their
problem is not GVHD because there are so few hematopoietic stem cells
in the cord blood transplants. Their problem is establishing a
natural hematopoiesis.
So some of these kids will lay in the hospital an average
of about 90 days. It's fairly replete in the literature, and they
aren't released from the hospital until they produce enough
platelets to get out, and so they can sit for 90 days in a subacute
state with bleeds and infections, et cetera.
This is a tiny population. It's an orphan indication,
but there's nothing that can be done for these, and in a Phase 1
study with an admittedly retrospective comparison to that database.
All of these kids are in a single database in the U.S.
Our primary goal was to decrease the time to platelet
engraftment, to get these kids out of the hospital and establish a
natural hematopoiesis, and the kids that received MSCs got out in an
average of about 38 days compared to retrospective control, historical
control of 90.
And so that program is in Phase 2, and we hope it would be
available also to humans in the '07 time frame.
The very large and much more talked about program, our
cardiac program for acute MI, will be in humans this December in
conjunction with Boston Scientific. Most of this preclinical work was
done in swine models at Cedar-Sinai and Hopkins, and the primary goal
here is for these cells to reshape the baseline morphology, the heart,
and regain the baseline function of the heart pre-MI.
It is fantastic preclinical data, and I say that with
humility after looking at preclinical data for 24 years in this
business. After you see so many pig hearts grow back and get back to
normal function, you start to believe it.
And the IND has been filed, and the FDA will allow us to go
into clinic at the NIH and Duke this December.
The idea here, too, in this indication, something we just
found out in '99 in rats, this will be an IV administration. It is
not a direct injection or catheter application to the heart.
Apparently these very smart cells - and I can call them that because
I'm not a scientist - find their way to an inflammatory site.
And an acute MI is a very strong inflammatory event, and an
inflammatory cascade that probably lasts in a strong manner for seven
or eight days. And basically these are given IV. They swim to the
heart. They regenerate the infarcted area of the heart, which the
heart doesn't then respond with a compensatory thickening like
normal, and that happens in about four to six weeks, and in about six
months the heart gets very close back to pre-MI function.
And if that gets in the clinic in December as planned, and
it should, these are going to be much larger trials because of acute
MI. We would like to think that this product could be available to the
public commercially in 2009 or 2010.
The next product which we have an IND filed for and will be
in humans before the end of '04 is meniscal repair in the knee.
This is the most common knee injury at least in this country.
There's about 850,000 meniscal tears, from the Weekend Warriors.
This will be a high regulatory bar. It should be. These are healthy
young people normally, and so the safety is going to be critical.
Preclinical work has been done in 72 goats, and basically what
we do is do a partial to full meniscectomy as is done with the patients.
There's nothing you can do for this today but take out part
or all of the meniscectomy to ease the pain. After whole or partial
meniscectomy, it is replete in the literature that one goes on to
develop osteoarthritis.
And what we do is give about 150 million cells directly
into the knee, and it grows back the meniscus in about six weeks time,
and hopefully then it will obviate any progression to osteoarthritis,
and we hope to be in the clinic with that as well in, again, '04
and, again, should be commercially available to humans in a similar
time as the acute MI product in '09 or '10.
The last advanced program, also in concert with Boston Scientific,
is maybe the largest unmet definitive therapy in terms of societal
cost, and that's congestive heart failure or, maybe more appropriately,
chronic ischemia leading to congestive heart failure. At Texas
Heart, in the canine model, we put an amaroid occluder in place
in these dogs to mimic chronic ischemia. Basically you do that
for about 30 days until you create an ischemic model.
About 30 days later you give the MSCs. The ejection
fraction in the amaroid occluded non-treated dogs, once it drops below
17 percent, they die. The ejection fraction in the treated dogs with
the occluded, LAD still in place, the occlusion remaining in place,
goes back to normal function in about six months.
So basically we've restored the heart morphology and
the baseline heart function pre-ischemic model with the amaroid
occluder in place, and there is possibly some form of angiogenesis
going on here.
So those are the advanced programs, and in all of these
programs and all of the animal models to this date, there have been no
serious adverse events associated with MSCs, again, neither infusional
toxicity, ectopic foci, or tumor formation.
Finally, we have many, many orthopedic models in a
preclinical area where we will or will not use a scaffolding or a
matrix for these cells in some of those applications.
And finally, we are involved in grants from DARPA and NIST
looking at wound healing and CNS repair, respectively.
As far as what obstacles stand in the way, the usual. One is
enough money, especially in today's very tight private equity
market, and it's probably going to stay that way until the IPO
lid comes off.
Cell biology talent. We will be forever understanding what
goes on with these, which leads to another point I'll get to in a
moment.
And then one, to put into an equal bag where we can all take an
equal share of guilt, and that's politics, corporate greed,
and academic ego, which is a bane always in the development of any
of these, and I don't say this lightly. Again, as a personal
comment after being involved in this 24 years and being fortunate
enough to be at Genentech when they grew up and then at Genzyme
when they grew up and at TKT with maybe the most elegant protein
technology I've ever seen. Have never seen anything like this.
The hardest thing about managing this company is keeping it
focused. There is no application that can't be brought up that we
can deny the possibility of the use of these cells or cells like this.
Bill Krivits up at Minnesota has given these to kids with lysosomal
storage diseases and they are not transduced. They just start secreting
the enzyme they're missing.
The immune modulation possibility now that we found out
almost serendipitously with our first program, that's a whole new
area of arthritis, et cetera. It literally is limited by our
imagination, and it's bigger than any of those entities I mentioned
by far. It is the closest thing - and I'm sorry for the drama - of
a human health care miracle that I've seen in a quarter century.
And I just hope somehow those entities can synergize to
bring this as quickly as possible and as safely as possible to the
millions and millions of people.
As far as approaches to overcome immune reaction, we
don't have any. We have found that there is no immune reaction
against these cells, and not only that. We have found them to be
immune suppressive selectively in appropriate situations.
As far as the federal policy impact, depending on what your
patent portfolio is, that drives your answer on this. Right now we
think from the Patent Office's perspective it's a very good
thing. We have had senior scientists that have stuck with this from
the beginning because they believe with this their inventions have been
protected, and it is allowed to go on in a protected manner to develop
those.
As far as the NIH, again, anything that can be done by that
institution to further synergize itself with commercial endeavors
without feeling it is bastardizing its academic purity, and exactly
what that means and how that is getting done we don't have an
answer, and I don't know who does, but it certainly could help all
efforts.
And the FDA, first of all, I want to say, again, in a long
experience over several technologies, they have been a very good
partner with us in this, and we appreciate that. We're a tiny
company. We need a lot of guidance, and it hasn't been an
adversarial situation. It has been a partnership situation, and
anything to continue to increase that.
We are in the good fortune of being by far the most
advanced company in the world in adult stem cell research, and so it
has got to be in partnership with the FDA that we understand how these
are to be regulated because I think that will set the bar for how it is
done from this point on.
I think one of the things that will be looked at, and we have
to understand where we draw the line to accept, is especially in
the technology where everything is happening in vivo, basically
from a cell that's the same ex vivo. Without all of
the black box answers for mechanism of action, why, how, where,
how long known is how that will be weighed against the actual clinical
outcomes of safety and efficacy and how that regulatory guide pole
is looked at is critical.
Thank you very much.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you very much.
Dr. Goldstein, please.
DR. GOLDSTEIN: Chairman Kass and members of the President's
Council on Bioethics, thank you very much for inviting me to testify
today.
I'm the Chief Scientific Officer for the Juvenile
Diabetes Research Foundation.
JDRF was founded in 1970 by parents of children with
juvenile diabetes to find a cure for diabetes and its complications
through the support of research, and this year we expect to fund
approximately $90 million worth of research.
Since its inception JDRF has funded diabetes research all
over the world, and it turns out it's the world's leading
nonprofit, non-governmental funder of diabetes research.
At your July 25th meeting, you heard from Charles Queenan,
a JDRF volunteer, who spoke about the advances in islet cell
transplantation that are showing dramatic results in people with Type I
diabetes. I'd like to briefly summarize.
As of April 2003, more than 250 patients worldwide had
received islets infusions using the so-called Edmondton protocol.
About half of these patients received islets alone. The other half
received islets in conjunction with or after a kidney transplant.
Most patients have enjoyed insulin independence, reduced
hypoglycemic episodes, and improved quality of life.
Despite this success, there are too few insulin producing
cells available from organ donors that at its max could help perhaps
five, six, 700 people a year. JDRF, therefore, believes that embryonic
stem cell research could lead to the discovery of new ways to develop
additional and unlimited supplies of insulin producing beta cells with
the hope that everyone with the disease can be treated and cured.
With this background, I want to cover some of the
activities that JDRF is engaged in over the past several years in the
United States and abroad to help advance the embryonic stem cell
research agenda.
In the spring of 2000, we announced our intention to
support embryonic stem cell research. We began to build a research
portfolio that promoted human and animal stem cell research.
To insure the ethical conduct of this research we formed a
stem cell oversight committee consisting of leading researchers, policy
makers, ethicists, and lay volunteers who were charged with providing a
second level of review in addition to the usual scientific peer review
for all human stem cell research applications that we received and
considered.
We recognize that stem cell research may require innovative
and novel public/private partnerships, and we included in our request
or solicitation the notation that we would support the derivation of
human embryonic stem cell lines.
The scientific principles that form the basis for stem cell
research funding program is as follows. We recognize the need to
support research using human stem cells from all sources and that very
basic research is the necessary precursor for the development of cell
based therapies; that adult stem cell research is a complementary
approach. We have long supported efforts in both adult stem cell
research, as well as more recently human embryonic stem cell research.
JDRF believes in providing a collaborative environment that
will encourage or maximize the opportunity and promise of this
research, and we work to insure easy and public dissemination of
embryonic stem cell lines without major restrictions as to the usage,
and we're committed to sharing information and data as they become
available.
We also participate in forums for public dialogue and
dissemination information.
JDRF embryonic stem cell research activities today include everything
that I mentioned, cells from all sources. This year we have applied
approximately $6 million in support of stem cell research with out-year
commitments of about $16 million over the next four years. Of the
$6 million this year, about three million is for research to direct
the differentiation into glucose-responsive, insulin- producing
cells using human embryonic stem cells as starting material. About
two million is for research using human stem cells from other sources,
and one million for animal work.
About one third of JDRF's funding for human embryonic
stem cell research supports work done in the United States. The rest
supports research outside the United States where in many cases
investigators work in more favorable environments, often with special
government programs that provide extra resources for human embryonic
stem cell research efforts, for example, Sweden, the United Kingdom,
Australia, and Singapore.
We initially received very few applications from U.S. based
investigators, perhaps related to concerns over policies and
restrictions. We have received consistent feedback from U.S.
investigators that they are wary of entering this field even with
private funding due to the limitations imposed by the federal policy.
They, in addition, mentioned a limited number of federally
approved lines, the lack of genetic diversity among the lines,
insufficient characterization, variability in the developmental
capacities of the lines, difficulties in distribution, as well as the
ubiquitous presence of the mass feeder layers which we've been
discussing which make the development of clinically useful cell
therapies not impossible, but more difficult as has been mentioned.
These barriers we feel need to be removed to increase the
value of using the approved stem cell lines for research and then for
the development of therapies. We acknowledge and recognize the efforts
of the NIH, particularly the NIH stem cell task force, and we are
working closely with NIH on this.
But I think that it's our international partnerships
that are pertinent to the conversation this afternoon.
JDRF's international efforts have continued and been
expanded in the area of stem cell research both through independent
funding of investigators, as well as through partnerships directly with
other governments. We have established a series of co-funding
partnerships with government research agencies in the United Kingdom,
Sweden, Canada, Australia, France and Singapore, and we have ongoing
discussions with others.
In some of these partnerships, local foundations within
those countries also provide support.
In addition, in many of those countries, we have provided
funding for very basic embryonic stem cell research that was not
necessarily connected to diabetes in any particular way since the
research was at the earliest stage.
Because of our extensive international work and leadership, JDRF
was invited in January 2003 to be a founding member of the International
Stem Cell Forum established by the Medical Research Council of the
United Kingdom under the leadership of Professor Sir George Radda.
This group currently includes representatives from
government agencies in the United Kingdom, Australia, Canada, Finland,
France, Germany, Israel, Japan, Singapore, Sweden, and the Netherlands,
as well as the NIH.
The objectives of the forum are to encourage collaborative
research across nations, boundaries, and disciplines; to encourage
sharing of resources and data; to fully capitalize on the existing
available human stem cell lines; to identify key research gaps and
address these by capitalizing on national strength; and to identify
funding schemes that actually facilitate transnational collaborations.
In specific terms, this group has agreed to develop a set
of criteria that could be adopted globally for optimizing the
derivation characterization and maintenance of human stem cell lines
from all sources; identify a small number of international laboratories
that would commit to using the agreed criteria to characterize existing
human embryonic stem cell lines; and to identify opportunities for
sharing resources, cell lines, data protocols, and guidance documents
on an international basis; to coordinate or make an attempt to
coordinate national stem cell banking activities.
This group has already convened a working group to
characterize stem cell lines with a series of recommendations.
The United Kingdom has one of the more progressive
environments for stem cell research as a consequence of the British
government providing strong political, regulatory, and funding support
in this area. The recent establishment of the U.K. Stem Cell Bank is
one example. This will provide access to existing and new quality
controlled adult, fetal, and embryonic stem cell lines. It will have a
good manufacturing practice arm for research leading to clinical
applications.
Academic researchers and companies from the U.K. and
elsewhere will be eligible to deposit and to access lines according to
a code of practice developed by interested parties.
This bank will serve as an outstanding example of how to
foster and enhance the research needed to develop therapies from stem
cells of all kinds.
Other countries are working toward the development of
similar resources, and it is envisioned that the International Stem
Cell Forum may serve to coordinate such activities in order to enhance
the exchange of information and to provide complementary efforts in
this burgeoning field of research.
Examples of activities under consideration include the
establishment of a registry posted on an international Web site that
would provide appropriate scientific information about lines not listed
in the current NIH registry; characterization of non-NIH registry
lines, and comparison with NIH lines; in addition, joint training
programs to assist new investigators.
Organizing and coordinating these international research
activities in order to better serve research efforts everywhere
provides a model that is highly likely to bring results to the clinic
much sooner.
Well, this summarizes research activities to date. I do
not want to provide the impression that these international activities,
for example, can replace the resources which the federal government and
United States could provide for this research.
The limitations imposed by the current policy raise
questions and provoke uncertainties about the future of human
embryonic stem cell research in the United States. We think that one
result is fewer scientists working, fewer graduate students, postdocs,
et cetera, and universities who have less than an active willingness to
invest in facilities, a comment that was made earlier in the afternoon.
These resources could make a significant difference to research progress
in the development of insulin producing beta cells for the cure
of diabetes, and in this area, they need to establish and nurture
collaborations between the world's experts in beta cell biology
and the world's experts in stem cell biology so they can collectively
conduct the necessary research. It remains a critical event.
Expanded federal embryonic stem cell policy would make an
important difference in helping promote this research.
Much of the current knowledge of beta cell development
comes from studies using mass embryonic stem cells that is not always
easily translatable into human work. Several protocols, however, have
been reported that direct mass embryonic stem cells to becoming
functioning islet cells. Early studies in human embryonic stem cells
suggest that they could be coached, though at the moment inefficiently
to insulin secreting cells, and this work has gone a little more slowly
than we would like.
We do continue to support research on the differentiation
of adult precursor cells into beta cells, but that's a severely
limited field in terms of how successful it has been.
Progress to date does underscore the need for continued
investment in research in this area, including the creation of an
environment in the United States that encourages and supports
scientific discovery.
The potential for this research to have a positive impact
on the maybe 100 million Americans who suffer from a wide variety of
diseases and injuries who might benefit is just too great to be
ignored.
Thank you for your invitation, your time, and your
consideration.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you, Dr. Goldstein.
Thank all of your for your fine presentations.
Let me just throw the floor open. Let me, so that everybody knows where
we are, we started late. We were originally scheduled to go to
5:15. Let's go to at least 5:25 and get people's questions
out so that we take advantage of our guests who traveled so far
to be with us.
So, please, Jim Wilson.
PROF. WILSON: Several of you referred to the political
uncertainty of stem cell research in the United States, and in the
course of making these remarks, you listed many possibilities. I would
like to know from you as briefly as possible what you think is the
chief political uncertainty.
Is it money? Is it stem cell lines? Is it the number of
researchers or what? What is the political uncertainty that you're
concerned about?
DR. OKARMA: Well, the quick answer is all of the above
that you just mentioned. If I were to prioritize them, it is the pure
political process of taking scientific inquiry out of the hands and
hearts of the scientists and into the halls of Congress.
Can the environment worsen with a different administration
or with the same administration? These are exactly the things that our
investors tell us that they are concerned about.
But the fact that there is a very thin infrastructure to
complement what we are doing at Geron, what other folks that you've
heard are doing here makes the risk higher to achieve a commercialable
and safe and effective product. They are intimately intertwined.
PROF. WILSON: That is true, but Congress has always, since
1938, placed under legislation by its action important therapeutic
regimes that might affect the safety or health of other people. Is
this supposed to be exempt from that?
DR. OKARMA: I'd like to hear an example of that that
compares to the -
PROF. WILSON: Well, the FDA constantly regulates.
DR. OKARMA: That's not political; that's not
congressional. This is different.
PROF. WILSON: Oh, there's a difference between the FDA
and Congress? You'll have to explain that to me.
DR. OKARMA: I think there certainly is.
PROF. WILSON: Anyone else have a response?
DR. GOLDSTEIN: The universities during the past two years-plus,
since the administration's policy, have had a variety of information
coming. As Dr. Zerhouni told you, it has only been since his arrival
that the stem cell task force was created. So some time was lost.
The most simplest example that I can give you is the
confusion over the application of federal policy to indirect cost of
university researchers, and it has only been in the past four to six
months where people have accepted the notion that they can do federally
funded research next door to privately funded research without getting
in trouble.
The clarification of that was painfully slow, and people
just didn't hop on the bandwagon immediately.
The second part, I think, has to do with what investigators
tell us, is it takes me six to eight months to work through my research
office to get a material transfer agreement to get one cell line at
$5,000. I'm hardly likely to be interested in studying two, three,
or more at that pace and would prefer some more economical and more
free distribution of more well characterized material.
So that inherent slowness is not exactly a terrific
ingredient for promoting and expediting research in a new area.
It's one reason why the international community, for example, has
taken a very strong position to complement the NIH activity and make
materials, information available on a more free exchange environment.
And you know, it's in a time when budgets for funding
research worldwide seem to be down. I would point out that the U.K.,
Japan have put special extra money at this topic because they view it
as an opportunity. That coincident with decreases in their regular
research budgets.
So people see this as a major opportunity.
PROF. WILSON: Thank you.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Alfonso.
DR. FOSTER: Jim, were you through?
PROF. WILSON: Yes.
DR. FOSTER: Dr. Okarma, I wanted to ask one question that
I wasn't sure about. You emphasized the oligodendrocyte as one of
your chief cells that was moving on. You said you were working on this
in spinal cord injury, but I presume this would be some myelinating
agent in something like MS or multiple sclerosis or something as well.
I don't know that, but the question would be if you put in a
differentiated cell and let's say you have a balance between, you
know, some autoimmune disease that's demyelinating and an
oligodendrocyte that's myelinating, the question I was going to ask
is that apparently a lot of times there's a block in the
oligodendrocyte capacity to myelinate because there's a block in
the movement from the pre-oligodendrocyte to the oligodendrocyte by,
you know, a jagged notch interaction or something like that.
So I guess the question I'm asking: is this
differentiated cell going to be - we've talked about the problem of
immune rejection and things like that - but is there another problem in
certain diseases of differentiated cells that they might not work
because of the primary disease that's present?
DR. OKARMA: That's precisely correct, and we have yet
done no work on systemic autoimmune based demyelinating diseases,
although to your point, they could potentially be subject to - we have
only worked on oligodendrocyte precursors in acute spinal cord injury.
DR. FOSTER: Thank you very much.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Alfonso Gómez-Lobo.
DR. GÓMEZ-LOBO: I don't know who this question is
going to go to. Probably Dr. Okarma.
I understand my charge here in this Council primarily as a
duty to worry about bioethics. I mean this is a Council on Bioethics,
and that's the way I see my social role in this context.
And one of the things that worries me is that in these
presentations, in these wonderful presentations you have made, I
don't see that dimension. For instance, it's one thing for
there to be political problems and perhaps concentrated on Congress,
but I think that there's the larger context of the whole nation and
there's the larger context of our lives and of the respect we owe
to each other, et cetera.
And then the question arises: shouldn't we see a
problem in the fact that a blastocyst that we know could be implanted
and continue its journey towards being like one of us, if that's
destroyed to extract the embryonic stem cells, whether we should not
worry at all about that? Is that a reason why some people may have
serious doubts not about the benefits, but about the means to obtain
these benefits?
DR. OKARMA: Well, first, sir, I was specifically asked not
to address those concerns, but let me assure you that they are very
prominent in the culture of our company. Approximately six months
after I arrived at Geron in December of '97, I formed an ethics
advisory board to discuss precisely those issues both for my own
uncertainties, to more vigorously and rigorously dissect the issues as
viewed by different Western religious traditions, as well as secular
perspectives, and to expose the workers in the company to this body and
have them ask their own questions of it, which has helped us enormously
and has informed us about the issues of moral status and has comforted
us in our position that this is not an ends justifies the means
argument, but that the special circumstances, the scalability, the
biological diversity, the normalness of the cells that we're able
to manufacture from a single stem cell line made from a single embryo
destined for destruction tilts the moral seesaw in our direction.
And we are intellectually and emotionally convinced of that
point.
DR. GÓMEZ-LOBO: May I?
CHAIRMAN KASS: Do you want to respond?
DR. GÓMEZ-LOBO: Fair enough. Now, that's a
straightforward utilitarian argument, and someone may say that, you
know, even one adult could be sacrificed for many. So there are
serious problems with that argument.
Let me leave it at that.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Does someone else want to respond to the
question as put before I call on someone else?
Dr. Goldstein.
DR. GOLDSTEIN: I would like to make a general comment
that we took the issue so seriously that we added an additional
layer of oversight, and the charge to the committee was to provide
and consider and revisit issues as they come up.
We assumed this was going to be a dynamic field, and this
committee developed guidelines. It watches over and it considers many
aspects that we don't consider with typical research grants, with
typical research grants that the IRB approves and you have all of the
signatures on.
So I think it has been taken in extremely serious ways. I
don't have a specific response about, yes, this is the correct or
incorrect or that kind of thing, but we made this effort because we saw
this as an issue, and we decided we needed a serious way to deal with
it.
And this committee reports directly to our board.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Janet, Janet Rowley.
DR. ROWLEY: I'd like further discussion in two areas,
and I suspect that maybe it's both Dr. Okarma and Dr. Palmer who
might respond to this.
First, I was surprised at your discussion of your funding
problems at Geron and the fact that you're only a third of the size
of a year ago because implicit in much of what has been written and
discussed earlier this morning, the assumption was that the federal
funding wasn't going to be important because private funding was so
robust and we could sit back and let the private sector take care of
it.
And you've raised some question about that more rosy
view.
I have another question though about the role of
nonapproved cell lines. So in a sense, both of you are counting on
these nonapproved cell lines because they will obviate the need for
feeder cell layers and things of that sort. But how do you view these
being used in the future or being of benefit or are they only going to
be of use outside of the United States and not be available for use for
American citizens?
DR. OKARMA: Well, first, let me clarify the premise of
your question. There's no uncertainty that the current lines in
Menlo Park that we have qualified for human use can go forward into
early stage human trials. They are robust. They are clean. They
differentiate repeatedly in the directions that we want them to go.
But they are xenogeneic, and they will eventually die off,
we think. We have no evidence for that yet, but we think it's the
conservative and appropriate assumption to make, that these cells,
despite their telomerase expression will not be immortal, as is a tumor
cell.
So for those two reasons, their natural life span and the
desire to improve by taking advantage of what we've learned from
the existing derivation protocols and improving them, putting those
derivation procedures under GMP with completely qualified and pedigreed
reagents so that even the antibody used to purify the growth factor has
never seen a murine antibody; that's what we're talking about
about GMP cell lines.
And that is a normal progression within the entire field of
cell therapy, and we think we are ahead of everyone in the restricted
arena of embryonic stem cells. So stay tuned for that announcement.
The issue, as you correctly point out, is that those cells
by definition of the current government policy will not be available
for study by U.S. government funded entities, and there's no
question, as you correctly imply, that the international community will
be very anxious to get their hands on those cell lines.
DR. PALMER: I'd like to add then to that the idea of
heterogeneity. If you're a publicly funded entity and would like
to explore the utility of these cells and you find that only a few will
perform the way that you are interested in and then only a few of those
will work in a portion of the patients that you are interested in
treating, then the new lines become absolutely critical; that you could
not cure Parkinson's. You could treat a few people. If the cell
lines run out, then you're done.
So it is a critical aspect of expanding the research to a
level where it's self-sustaining.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Bill Hurlbut. I'm sorry. Excuse me.
Michael and then Bill.
PROF. SANDEL: This is a question for Dr. Palmer, and it
goes back to something that Paul McHugh said in this morning's
discussion. He was giving an interpretation, a sympathetic
interpretation, of the President's current policy allowing the use
of private funds but not public funds for new embryonic stem cell lines
and limiting public funding to the preexisting.
And the way that Paul interpreted that was as a challenge
to scientists to say, "All right. Within this limited area, show
us what you can do. Show us that there's not just speculative
promise, but that there's genuine progress. Show us. Let the
burden be on you scientists to show us not only that, but also that
redeeming that progress depends on going beyond the 12 approved stem
lines that are currently available for distribution, and show us also
that redeeming that genuine progress requires federal funding for more
than the existing approved cell lines."
Now, much as I heard your comment, you were speaking in
that spirit, addressing that kind of challenge with respect very
concretely to Parkinson's, but I wonder if you could just, taking
that challenge directly of Paul, address to him in a summary way the
answer.
As I understood your testimony just now, you in effect
think you already now have the answer for Paul, and then I'd be
interested to hear Paul's response.
DR. PALMER: Let me speak about data that I have seen, but
it's still proprietary and confidential in a general sense. In
funding stem cell research, about half of our stem cell effort is in
embryonic stem cells, and the remainder divided between adult stem
cells and fetal stem cells.
Within the embryonic stem cell projects, several of these
proposals, their specific aim was to contrast and compare cell lines
that were available to them, and what we have seen in the data that
they present is that there is beyond a shadow of a doubt huge potential
to create authentic dopamine neurons from human ES cells.
That's good. The problem is that within the limited
number of cell lines that they have tested that potential is hugely
variable. These are cell lines that are theoretically pluripotent, and
they should be equivalent embryonic lines. If you look at a picture of
them in the dish, they look strikingly different from line to line,
which has the stamp of their history, which cell lines they have been
exposed to, which sera they had applied to them, which growth factors
were used in their preparation in isolation.
And this history of experience from these ES cells then
imprints them to behave a certain way when their context is suddenly if
they're asked to produce a dopamine neuron.
So the heterogeneity tells me as a scientist that we have a
problem, that some of these lines may work some of the time for some of
the applications, but they will not all work for all applications.
And this is a very strong argument for expanding the
variety and the heterogeneity of the lines that we currently have
access to. Eleven or 12 is not enough.
DR. McHUGH: Yes, thank you very much, Michael, for asking
that question because it was rather what I wanted to ask. But I have
two responses to that.
First of all, the heterogeneity that you mentioned may or
may not be so compelling as to not allow you to find, after all, these
are immortal cells, and if you get one or two or three lines from the
12 and the expansion of things that are going, you may well be able to
tell us that you're already achieving with what we have in front of
us adequate things for the future. That's the first thing.
But more importantly to me, anyway, was what you said about
the issues of the autoimmune problem and how you thought that the
autoimmune problem was going to be the telling one as you have seen the
cells die in the process when they're exposed in this way in a
foreign turf and you looked forward to the opportunity perhaps of using
somatic cell nuclear transplantation to develop dopamine cells that
were, in fact, from the person themselves.
And I wanted to say that I, of course, have spoken in this conference
that I think that that is going to be the way in which embryonic
cells ultimately will - as one of the ways that will get to this
source of cells in ways that we will have to look more closely at
its ethical basis and I see as distinct from the ethical source
that comes from the zygote and the embryonic stem cells that the
President was talking about in his August 9 speech.
So, Michael, now to return to you, I just think that
we've seen today from these wonderful four presenters just the
kinds of things that I would like to see to enhance our conversation to
get us to a place where we will talk about the direction science will
go and the promise that it will take.
And let's just finish off by a very small question that
I wanted to ask you, Dr. Palmer, since I've got the floor, and that
was aspects of the biology of Parkinsonism itself and the concern that
I have that perhaps the disorder - are you sure that the disorder will
not in itself being directed against dopamine cells, might not kill off
the stem cells that are being produced and kill them more quickly than
even the endogenous cells?
So where is the understanding of the pathogenesis of
Parkinsonism in relationship to this transplantation treatment?
DR. PALMER: Let me turn this around maybe and expand your
horizon in thinking about ES cells, embryonic stem cells, and again
stepping one more step into the nuclear transfer arena or into the area
where you can engineer, genetically modify a traditional embryonic stem
cell.
So there is no guarantee that making a pure population of
dopamine neurons will cure Parkinson's disease. There is very good
evidence that under some circumstances dopamine neurons from fetal
tissue do help in Parkinson's disease, and what we would be
striving for is a population that is renewable that would not require
the use of fetuses for curing individuals.
So in that sense, there is a gold standard that is working
relatively well, but has problems to overcome to which ES cell
strategies can aspire to, and that does work. And so I am optimistic
that the stem cell strategy will also work, if not better, if we can
eliminate the aspects of the fetal tissue transplant that may be giving
us trouble in that particular clinical paradigm.
Now, flip-flopping this a little bit, you brought up the
idea that Parkinson's disease is a disease, and putting healthy
cells into the diseased brain may be a bad idea and may not make it
work. How would you understand the complexities of that disease?
The way one might approach this is to use ES cells that
harbor all of that genetic complexity of that disease and model it in a
tissue culture dish. Try your drug screening strategies. See if you
can't find mechanisms that are not possible to even understand in a
whole organism by recreating the system in the dish.
This is the real power of ES cell technology.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Bill - sorry. Paul, did you want to just
every quickly?
DR. McHUGH: No. Thank you very much for that.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Bill Hurlbut, the last question and then
we'll stop.
DR. HURLBUT: Well, thank you for your presentations and
the very exciting prospects of going forward with the existing cell
lines and the others that you suggest. The future looks like it has
real possibilities.
What I want to explore for a second is beyond the
therapeutic potential. You've mentioned amazing possibilities for
scientific research and drug testing and so forth. So even if this
technology doesn't end up making its way into the clinics, it
obviously is going to be very, very important for the whole future of
biomedical science.
So what I want to ask you is this. Given this amazing
foundational, early stage of this new medicine, kind of a whole new
wing on the mansion of medicine, and yet given the conflict that is
going on within our culture where, depending on who you believe, which
survey you believe, maybe half the population has problems about the
moral grounding of this future of medicine, here's my question.
I was speaking with a pediatrician recently, and she told
me that it's not uncommon to have parents whose children are going
to be vaccinated ask her was this vaccine grown on fetal tissues.
So the problem is that even if the individual patient
doesn't choose to employ the therapy that they have an ethical
problem with, the whole foundation of medicine is going to be built on
this technology, and so it's not just a vaccine that somebody can
say, "Well, I don't want it." It's just sort of like
everything will be built on this, right?
And beyond the question of whether or not the President
could change his policies, there is the Dickey amendment, and I think
we heard this morning that to a very large extent his decision was an
interpretation of the Dickey amendment itself.
So given half the population roughly has ethical problems,
given that this is going to be the future foundation of medicine, are
there ways in the kind of research you're doing; do you see any
hopeful ways that we can do this in a way that bypasses the moral
problems?
And as a part of that question, I'd like to ask you:
how important do you think cloning for biomedical research is,
so-called therapeutic cloning?
And recently the work of Gurdon at Cambridge suggested that maybe
you can find the cytoplasmic factors that can down-regulate or reprogram
the nucleus of a somatic cell. Do you see any hopeful ways out
of this?
And are there ways we could fund this current research such
that the moral impasse would be temporary if we could just get it
launched with a good deal of support?
DR. PALMER: I do agree with the sentiment entirely. So
the real issue is how. Let's take two hypotheticals.
One is that the U.S. is restricted in its ability to pursue
these technologies on ethical grounds, on moral grounds, yet other
countries are not. The moral question becomes can you then use the
information and technology that was developed offshore morally. And
that's something that would have to be discussed.
We would be far behind in our technologies, in our drug
development, in our ability to provide health care to our
constituents. If we had the ability to temporarily recognize the value
of the lines of research with the full intent that we need to
understand what these cytoplasmic factors are, nuclear transfer
technology is the prototype. It is the first working example of taking
a genome, which is totipotent. So a cell's genome has all of the
information that you need to make an individual.
My cheek cell, if it has all of its genes, is totipotent,
given the right cytoplasmic factors to program it. How will you
circumvent this moral problem unless there is a decision or an
understanding that the morality is a combination of concepts and
beliefs?
This is a very difficult question, and I don't envy
your task as Council. If you were to take a fertilized egg and
reprogram a nucleus, create an embryo out of that to make stem cells,
that's not so technically different than just simply programming
the nucleus to go through all of those steps to create stem cells, and
it's one of an intellectual process coming to grips with a moral
stance, a belief. It's going to be difficult to separate those
two, I think.
So technically I think there's great hope to program
the genome in a way that would lead to an embryonic stem cell
that's pluripotent. The prototype of that is nuclear transfer
technology, and that is the technology that's going to give you
those steps to get from Point A to Point B without creating the embryo.
DR. HURLBUT: Within the constraints of existing policy, do
you think we could if we funded it properly find a way to do that?
DR. PALMER: It could happen tomorrow or it could be
years. It will happen offshore regardless.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thanks to our four panelists for your
presentations, your forthcomingness. Thanks to the Council members for
enduring a long, but very interesting day.
We meet again tomorrow morning at 8:30, and we meet again
at 6:30 for convivial repast.
The meeting is adjourned.
(Whereupon, at 5:40 p.m., the meeting in the
above-entitled matter was adjourned, to reconvene at 8:30 a.m.,
Friday, September 5, 2003.)
|