CHAIRMAN KASS: Again, it is a
great pleasure to have Ms. Suzi Leather, the Chair of the Human
Fertilization and Embryology Authority with us. And we look very much
forward to your presentation and discussion. Thank you for being with
us.
MS. LEATHER: Thank you very much
indeed. Chairman and Council Members, it is a very great privilege for
me also to be invited to attend this meeting, and to present to you the
U.K. model of regulating assisted reproductive technologies and human
embryo research.
Thank you very much for this
opportunity and I am sure we are going to learn as the presentation
follows the order of your helpful list of questions broadly.
I must begin by saying that the
Human Fertilization and Embryology Authority which I Chair is an
example of a rather eccentric British institution, a non-departmental
public body. This mean that we report to the U.K. Department of
Health, specifically to the Minister for Public Health.
We have an independent status of
government, and like Baroness Kennedy before, I speak to you today in
my capacity as Chair of the HFEA, and not as a representative of the
British Government.
I also speak as someone who has
not been in place for very long. I took over from my excellent
predecessor, Dame Ruth Deach, only in March of this year.
And before that I was the Deputy
Chair of the Foods Standards Agency, which in some ways is rather
similar, in that we deal with the interspace between public
understanding and perception and science.
So clearly we don't have the
ethical dimension and the feelings dimension as strongly in the food
safety debates as we do in these debates, but there is some that do
cross.
By background, I am not a lawyer,
unlike both of my predecessors. My background is in social sciences,
particularly in political science, and also in social work training. I
have worked mostly for consumer organizations, and focused on health.
Now, Chairman, your first
questions were about the HFEA's mandate and structure. The Human
Fertilization and Embryology Authority, as I am sure you know, was the
first regulatory authority of its kind in the world.
And it was set up following a
very widespread public debate, the most notable feature of which was
the Warnock Committee Report in 1984, which recommended amongst other
things the creation of a new statutory licensing authority to regulate
both the research and those infertility services which the committee
thought should be the subject of control.
And it established the principles
by which we work today. These include respect for human life at all
stages of its development. Respect for the rights of people who seek
treatment and the need for their fully informed consent.
Concern for the welfare of the
resulting child, independent of the interest of the adults involved;
and the recognition of the benefits which can flow from
responsibilities perceived of medical and scientific knowledge.
Established in 1991 by an Act of
Parliament, the HFEA's role is principally to regulate the
creation, storage, and use of human embryos outside the body, both in
treatment and research.
And we also regulate assisted
conception techniques which use their native gametes, and the storage
of gametes. The HFEA's system of regulation is national, covering
clinics and research centers in all four countries of the United
Kingdom.
We make no distinction between
the public and private sector. Constitutionally, as I have said, the
HFEA is a non-departmental public body. This means that it is at a
distance from central governments, being headed by an authority board
rather than by ministers or government employees.
And we have those functions. We
publish a code of practice, which gives guidance to clinics about how
they should conduct their activities. We keep a register about
treatments, about children born, and about donors.
We provide advice and information
to patients, and to donors, and to clinics, and we review developments,
and have also an advisory function. Now, having said that we are
independent, we are not wholly independent.
Our members are appointed by
ministers following open public advertisement of the sort of that
Baroness Kennedy talked about, and we are responsible and accountable
to Parliament through the Secretary of State for Health.
Our membership is very wide
also. We comprise people who are appointed in an individual capacity
rather than as representatives of organizations, but they have
background in clinical and research medicine, nursing, science, the
law, ethics, religion, psychology, social work, regulation, and the
media.
We currently have 21 members, and
no more than half of our members may be from science or medicine. In
addition, neither the Chair nor the Deputy Chair may be other than lay
members.
We have an executive staff of
about 48, plus or minus a few from time to time, and in addition we
have a part-time inspectorate of about 60 clinicians, scientists,
ethicists, counselors, and lay people, and we have about a pool of
about 50 internationally respected peer reviewers who advise us on the
research license approvals.
Our present structure developed
from what was essentially a self-regulatory model, which operated from
1985 to 1991. We currently have an annual budget of 2.7 million
pounds, which is about $4.2 million to cover the research of 122
storage treatment and research centers in the U.K., to cover the
comprehensive data collection and storage function, and the executive
staff to support the authority, as well as our internal committees.
Since inception in 1991, the
context in which the HFEA operates has changed very significantly.
Demand for IVF treatment has more than doubled. About one percent of
births in the United Kingdom are the result of IVF, and we do not I
should say cover gamete inter-fallopian transfers.
So we don't cover GIFT, and
that is not a license in fertility treatment under our system. We also
as you have seen a significant increase in particular in the complexity
of treatments, such as ICSI, PGD, assisted hatching, and now of course
there are new techniques, such as antecloding screening and the use of
frozen eggs coming on stream.
There has also been a very
significant change in public attitudes with very much greater demands
for openness and public involvement. The HGC is one of the expressions
of government's answer to those demands.
And there are also significantly
higher expectations of corporate governance, and rigorous risk-based
regulation across all organizations in the field, but these changes
have certainly had a very remarkable impact in the health sector.
The HFEA is responding to these
changes, and we have recently put a business case to governments to
enlarge the capacity of the organization to support and enhance
regulatory function.
I hope that this should mean
amongst other things that we will be able to move towards a much more
demanding evidence-based, rather than judgment-based, inspection
system, and have a greater capacity to audit treatment information and
provide guidance on best practice, rather than the set of minimum
standards.
Now, this rather complex slide
shows the interrelationship, and I'm sorry, but the white print
doesn't show up very well. It shows the interrelationship between
our licensing activities and some of our policy formation, because we
license clinics, and we audit what happens in clinics, and we inspect
clinics annually.
And from the monitoring of that,
that feeds back into our policy and into our code of practice. So, for
instance, I guess the best example is the number of embryos.
We under our code of practice say
that there should be two embryos transferred, and only in exceptional
circumstances, three, and I believe that is fairly different from some
of the practice in the U.S.
And I personally would be keen to
move as closely as we could to natural practices. Some of the European
countries are looking at that and to single embryo transfer, and
clearing there would be benefits in terms of reducing the burden of
multiple births.
The organization powers and
duties of the HFEA are based on and circumscribed by statute. We
essentially implement the Human Fertilization and Embryology Act of
1990, as amended by a handful of subsequent legislation, such as the
Human Fertilization and Embryology research purposes regulations in
2001, which permits human embryos to be used to derive stem cell lines.
Our foundation is therefore
established by decisions of Parliament primarily when it passed the Act
almost 12 years ago. The main responsibilities of the HFEA under the
Act as I have said are to license and to inspect IVF clinics, and to
license and regulate embryo research, to ensure that only research
which is necessary for, and in keeping with the purposes set down by
Parliament, takes place.
As I have indicated the
HFEA's regulation of infertility treatment applies equally to
private clinics, as well as to the social provision carried out within
the National Health Service.
Similar with research, the
funding source, public or private, is immaterial. Now something about
what we don't do. We do not act as a pressure group. We are not
acting to increase the amount of infertility treatment. That is not
one of our primary roles.
We are not an ombudsman or
ombudsperson. We are not a research or treatment funding organization,
and let me in fact repeat that we don't in fact regulate all
infertility treatment. We don't regulate GIFT, and clearly we
don't regulate what happens in bedrooms.
In your questions to me,
Chairman, you asked whether the HFEA has any formal responsibility to
advance British competitiveness in biotechnology. It does not.
And indeed as a regulator, I
would emphasize the importance of maintaining an evenhanded stance with
regard to particular companies and research groups operating within the
United Kingdom.
Furthermore, the HFEA is not
involved in funding as I have said either treatment or research, or
indeed in directing resources of any kind in this way, although we do
have an important role to play with medical funders, such as the MRC,
and we are currently talking to them on setting up good research
projects and looking at the outcomes of infertility treatment.
Now, this is some of the recent
public consultations that we have done, and we are about to launch in
fact on Tuesday of next week a sex selection consultation.
We have be invited by government
to do so, and we last consulted the public about this in 1993, and it
will be interesting to see whether there has indeed been a shift in
public attitudes. Certainly only yesterday there were reports in our
media of family couples coming ot the States to make the use of
MicroSort techniques, because they wanted to determine the sex of their
next child.
But at the moment the position in
the U.K. is that sex selection is only permitted to enable couples to
avoid serious sex link disease and not for social purposes.
One of the purposes of regulation
I feel is to maintain public confidence in the area regulated, and I
believe that we have a responsibility to act openly, and to consult the
public as widely as we can, and to inform public debates about the
activities, benefits, and costs of reproductive technologies.
As well as to carry this debate
forward through public education. But I do emphasize that this derives
from our responsibility for informing the public and not from any
interest in the furtherance of science or the promotion of U.K.
biotechnology.
If we do carry out our tasks
openly and intelligently, I hope nevertheless that the public debate
will be an important contribution to the future of these technologies.
Let me turn now to your questions
about the guiding principles and ethical basis of our work. As I have
said the HFEA was set up to implement an act of Parliament. That
legislation was itself a result of concern about the human embryo, and
the possibilities that arose as a consequence of the creation of
embryos in the laboratory.
The Warnock committees'
approach, which was subsequently endorsed by Parliament, and embodied
in the legislation setting up the HFEA, was to focus not on the
definition of the status of the embryo, but rather on how it should be
treated.
In the Committee's view, the
developmental potential of the early embryo made it deserving of
respect, but not of being regarded as a human person. Following the
committee's report, certain absolute prohibitions were codified in
the legislation.
For example, research on embryos
up to 14 days is permitted, but only for specific purposes as defined
by Parliament, and only with the approval of a research license from
the HFEA.
In public debate about the
creation of embryos outside the body, this gives rise to three main
concerns. Is it right, and is it safe, and where might it lead.
Public opinion on these questions
is varied, and in the United Kingdom, as in the U.S., there are some
people who are opposed to IVF and the use of embryos in any research.
However, in the U.K., the
experience of over 10 years of regulation has provided reassurance that
the activities of researchers and clinicians can be controlled in such
a way that it allows the benefits of these technologies to be explored
and enjoyed responsibility.
And certainly the debate in 2000
and 2001 surrounding the derivation and use of embryonic stem cells
showed that concern had moved on from anxieties that characterized the
debates in the 1980s over the regulation of IVF and the acceptable use
of embryos in research.
However, the HFEA must I think do
more to come back to one of your questions, Chairman, and must do more
than merely reflect public opinion on these matters.
In particular, when there was a
question of licensing the implementation of new techniques, these must
be judged first against the parameters set down by Parliament, i.e.,
there is a role in interpreting the lawmakers.
And then in light of the
principles that underlie them to which I have already alluded, in these
matters the HFEA fulfills I think an essential function, in that we are
an expert body appointed to address questions that are sometimes
technically difficult, and always ethically complex, and in which the
public is not necessarily interested, or the implications of which it
does not see necessarily straight away.
So while we consult widely, and
often in collaboration with other bodies, and sometimes with the HGC,
it is not possible or I think appropriate to consult on every new
development.
Or indeed to develop or to decide
some of the sensitive issues as it were by plebiscite. Typically the
HFEA's process involves a movement from consideration of principles
to the consideration of consequences or utility.
Only when legal, technical, and
ethical questions may ask can it be done, may it be done, ought to be
done, have been fully considered does the HFEA then reach the point at
which in turning to more concrete and practical questions we have to
balance the potential benefits that technologies might provide with any
risks associated with them, both in terms of public health, and in
terms of public morality.
The decisions which the Authority
makes are frequently the subject of a great deal of media interest. An
area of current focus is embryo screening.
Consistent with the outcome of a
large scale public consultation, the HFEA permits the implantation
genetic diagnosis in cases where there was a serious significant risk
of a child inheriting a serious genetic disease.
Now, precisely what this means is
a matter of judgment. There is no positive list of diseases or disease
categories. Instead, seriousness is judged in the context of each
clinical situation, with reference to the abortion guidelines from the
U.K. Royal College of Obstetricians and Gynecologists.
In other words, if a condition is
so serious that two doctors would allow a doctor to terminate her
pregnancy if the fetus had it, then pre-implantation and genetic
diagnosis may be allowed so that the woman can begin her pregnancy,
confident that the fetus she will carry is unaffected.
However, the possibilities
available through pre-implantation genetic testing are not restricted
of course to the avoidance of disease, and this was clearly the concern
of the architects of the legislation.
Decisions concerning the
selection of genetic characteristics have themselves raised questions
in the public mind about the circumstances and the extent to which
couples should be allowed to select for or against characteristics.
Increasingly the HFEA is faced
with decisions involving the use of assisted reproductive techniques in
non-infertility settings. Two important decisions have been made by us
this year.
In February the HFEA allowed a
couple undergoing IVF with PGD to select an embryo, which as well as
being free from a serious disease, is also selected to enable cord
blood from the resulting baby to be used to treat an older sibling
suffering from beta fallacemia, and this is sometimes referred to as
the Hashmead case.
In reaching its public policy,
the HFEA established a number of criteria under which it would see the
use of such a technique being acceptable. I apologize for the small
print, but I think these are quite important.
So firstly the condition of the
affected child should be severe or life threatening or of a sufficient
seriousness to justify the use of PGD. The embryos conceived during
the course of this treatment should themselves be at risk from the
condition by which the existing child is affected and that is a very
crucial clause, and it relates to another case that I am going to talk
about in a minute.
All other possibilities of
treatment and sources of tissue for the affected child should have been
explored. The technique should not be available where the intended
recipient is a parent, and the intention should be to take only cord
blood for purposes of the treatment, and not other tissues or organs.
PROF. SANDEL: Does that include
bone marrow?
MS. LEATHER: No. In another
subsequent case which did not meet the criteria, specifically of
embryos conceived in the course of this treatment should themselves be
at risk by which the existing child is affected, the Authority has not
allowed HLA matching, and this case is sometimes called the
Whittaker case.
These were two pretty important
decisions by the HFEA,a nd they both received an enormous amount of
media coverage. Our reasoning for making this distinction involved the
acceptance of three premises.
Firstly, the principle that
persons should not be regarded merely as means to other people ends,
and the need to respect the interests of any child being created as
separate from the interests of anyone else, even a seriously ill older
sibling.
Second, a recognition that embryo
biopsy is a procedure which has not been subject to lengthy clinical
trials. The risks associated with it are therefore yet unquantified,
but must be balanced against any benefits accruing to a person which
develops from the biopsied embryo, and this point came up in your
discussions yesterday.
Thirdly, the view that where such
a procedure is being undertaken, and the interests of the future child,
an additional step which does not involve additional anticipated harm,
but which may confer a sufficient lateral benefit, maybe be permitted.
Thus, if the benefits essentially
accrue only to another person then we thought that it was unethical to
allow the creation of a person whose interests have been compromised in
this way.
Both decisions as I have said
provoked widespread controversy, and I'm sure will be the subject
of continuing discussion and review. The underlying issue, which is
how far U.K. society wishes to go in making use of these techniques for
purposes other than the simply avoidance of serious disease, is
unresolved at this time.
PROF. SANDEL: Could you just
explain how Condition B was not resolved in the case that you turned
down so we can understand it?
MS. LEATHER: I'm sorry, the
case we turned down?
PROF. SANDEL: Yes.
MS. LEATHER: The child that we
created did not themselves stand a chance, any more of a chance of you
or I inheriting -- well, not in inheriting, but in suffering from the
disease that its sibling had.
PROF. SANDEL: And you knew that
because of the genetic testing?
MS. LEATHER: The sibling had
black fananemia and was not judged to be a genetic illness. So
subsequent siblings it was felt would not stand any more chance of
having that disease than anybody else.
So if you were going to allow HLA
typing in order simply to have a match for an older sibling, that that
was ethically unacceptable we felt.
PROF. SANDEL: Was it in the
first case --
MS. LEATHER: In the first case,
beta fallacemia, a second child themselves would have been at risk of
that disease. So they themselves benefitted from pre-implementation
genetic diagnosis. We felt that therefore at the same time that you
could choose an embryo at the same time that you were doing an embryo
biopsy to avoid that child having beta fanacemia, you could choose an
embryo which tissue matched the older sibling.
PROF. SANDEL: Thank you.
MS. LEATHER: It is difficult to
explain these differences, which are very fine judgments, and clearly
fall with the families concerned that are hugely painful.
And it is difficult to explain
them, and even here it is very difficult to explain them to the media,
but nevertheless it did seem to us to be a very important ethical
decision and one that we should at this time protect.
And can I come to the sex
selection consultation now? This is an area as I have said that we are
consulting. Now, once it is a matter of policy, sex selection using
pre-implantation genetic diagnosis, is only permitted in the United
Kingdom for medical reasons.
And sperm sorting follows by
artificial insemination, where this uses fresh sperm of a woman's
partner, is not controlled currently. And the consultation which we
are going to publish next week has followed a year long review, which
has included the commissioning of independent reports on the scientific
and ethical aspects of the treatment, as well as market research into
the nature of public understanding and discussions of this subject.
And we are going to address three
main areas. Firstly, should the use of sperm sorting be regulated in
the United Kingdom. Secondly, should sperm sorting be available for
medical indications, bearing in mind the current uncertainly as to its
reliability and long term side effects.
And thirdly should sex selection
in general been available for any non-medical reasons. Let me turn
now, Chairman, to your questions on our processes and actions, and in
particular embryo research.
We make a distinction in the U.K.
between publicly and privately funded system conception centers, nor
between research which is funded by public bodies, which as the Medical
Research Council. and private organizations, such as pharmaceutical
companies.
All activities which involve the
storage of human gametes, the creation outside the body, the use and
treatment, and research of human embryos up to 14 days, are subject to
our license and inspection procedures.
The approval process for research
licenses is rigorous. The HFEA has first to be confident that the
proposed use of any embryos is necessary for the purpose of the
research, and the activities conducted in the course of the research
are in keeping with Parliament's accepted purposes.
The 1990 Act defines these
purposes, firstly, as promoting advances in the treatment of
infertility, and increasing the knowledge about the causes of
congenital disease, and increasing knowledge about the causes of
congenital disease, increasing knowledge about the courses of
miscarriage, developing more effective techniques of contraception, or
developing methods for detecting the presence of gene or chromosome
abnormalities in embryos before implantation.
But these purposes were generally
to do with infertility is explained by the way in which human embryo
research developed in the U.K. in pursuit of more effective means of
overcoming infertility.
So the historical reason for the
HFEA's remit covering both treatment and research, and in the
context that it was a short step for techniques to move from
development to implantation, and quite often as connections, of course,
between people who are involved in research, and people who are
involved in treatment.
In January of 2001, following
large majorities in both Houses of Parliament, which were on three
votes, and so people weren't voting along particular party lines,
but individual consequence on the issue, three additional research
purposes were added.
Firstly, increasing knowledge
about the development of embryos, and increasing knowledge about
serious disease, or enabling such knowledge to be applied in developing
treatments for serious disease.
The addition of these purposes
confirmed the HFEA as the appropriate body to license and regulate
embryo research, a confidence that was then endorsed by the House of
Lords on that committee later that year.
However, with the introduction of
these new purposes, the HFEA is realizing more than ever before a need
to collaborate closely with other organizations and bodies with an
interest in the development and use of knowledge techniques in cell
lines originating in embryo research, specifically with the Medical
Research Council.
In addition to thinking about the
requirements for embryo research, in addition to passing the first
hurdles which I have described, which are the necessity and appropriate
purposes test, all research applications have to have the approval of
a properly constituted ethics research committee.
And the research is then subject
to our peer review process. The research facilities are inspected, and
the proposed license holder for the project and many of their team will
be interviewed before a final report is considered by an HFEA licensed
committee.
Applicants wishing to undertake
research to drive stem cells from embryos are further required to do
the following. Firstly, to justify why embryonic stem cells are to be
used, rather than other types of stem cells.
Secondly, to provide detailed
information on what happens to the stem cells throughout the project;
and to place a sample of all cell lines in the MRC stem cell bank.
Chairman, you asked me also about
human cloning. The U.K. has taken the lead in positively outlawing
human reproductive cloning. The Human Reproductive Cloning Act of 2001
makes it an offense under criminal law to place a cloned human embryo
into a woman.
And any clinician found guilty of
doing so in the U.K. would be liable to a prison term of up to 10
years, and also to a fine. Somatic cell nuclear transfer, sometimes
called therapeutic cloning, or I think in your last report, cloning for
biomedical research, on the other hand, is permitted under the law.
Indeed, one of the intentions of
the Research Purposes Regulation of 2001 was to permit the deprivation
of stem cell lines from embryos created by cell nuclear
transplantation.
And so together these two pieces
of legislation positioned the U.K. in your ban plus regulation
category. The HFEA is therefore allowed to issue licenses for
therapeutic cloning. However, it has yet to do so.
Furthermore, the HFEA has
announced that it will not issue any such licenses until the House of
Lords, acting as the final Court of Appeal in litigation brought by the
Pro Life Alliance, puts beyond doubt the question of whether human
embryos created by cell nuclear transplantation are in fact embryos
within the terms of the regulatory legislation.
Your final set of questions,
Chairman, were most difficult. You asked me to make some general
reflections, and I think to make some suggestions for your country,
which I really don't think is in a sense my business to do.
But certainly the benefit of
hindsight is attractive. Looking back, a notable feature I think of
the legislation which established the HFEA has been its remarkable
durability.
The HFEA Act has continued to
provide a workable framework and prove robust enough to cope with the
proliferation of scientific developments and treatment possibilities --
ICSI, pre-implementation, and genetic diagnosis, antecloding screening,
assisted hatching.
There have, however, been some
drawbacks in the legislation. In a very practical sense, we have been
hampered by the very stringent definition of confidentiality under the
Act.
This was incorporated in order to
protect patients, donor, and off-spring confidentiality, but it has
imposed in fact significant practical constraints on the HFEA.
It means, for instance, that the
HFEA has been unable to engage outside contractors to improve its IT
systems, and it suffered from a qualification on its accounts due to
the fact that these can't be independently verified.
So these are not necessarily
issues for you, but they are certainly issues that have made a bit of a
difference to us.
In terms of recommendations, it
is difficult I think to read across very closely from the U.K. to the
U.S. The different histories and traditions, not least the fact that
the U.K. does not have a written constitution, or a Federal structure,
but does have an established church, and I think a less publicized
civil service, makes generalizing from one setting to another
particularly precarious.
Additionally as I have said, our
regulatory history over the past 10 years or so has given public debate
a different complexion, and I think it is fair to say that public
opinion in the U.K. is less polarized on these issues than it is here.
That said, let me suggest some
issues for debate. Firstly, the core question I think for us for
regulation of assisted reproduction technologies is to what extent is
this so different an area of health care that it justifies and requires
a distinct regulator restructure.
And in the U.K. in 1990, it was
certainly judged to require just that. There were a number of factors
which justified setting up the HFEA, and not least of course ethical
sensitivity about embryo research and infertility treatment.
In addition, access to
infertility treatment has never been generally available under our
National Health Service. So rather like cosmetic surgery, most
providers were in fact in the private sector, and so it required a
system which operated across both public and private provision.
From the U.K. perspective, I can
certainly point to many benefits of regulation in the area of assisted
reproduction. A reliable and publicized standard of service provision
for patients, and public confidence that these standards will be
maintained, compulsory data collection in the interests of public
health.
And consistency, transparency,
and independence of decision making in line with clear moral standards
in what is an ethically difficult area. But having said all of this,
it is important to remember I think that each national jurisdiction
will have to reach its own conclusions on the acceptability of forms of
assisted conception and embryo research.
And to implement those within or
under the rubrics of its own political system. There may be some uses
of reproductive technology which are so offensive to moral sense and
natural justice that they merit international condemnation and
prohibition.
Human reproductive cloning, and
cloning to produce children, and eugenic selection of racial
characteristics may fall into this category. But for others, I think,
it is a case of determining what the moral consensus in each culture
can approve in the interests of medical benefits and scientific
advance.
The U.K. experience has been that
it is possible to reach consensus, or at least an accommodation in this
area. But the road to legislation was a difficult one, and in another
context it might prove more difficult still.
Consequently, in the research
context, very real issues arise with regard to the exploitation of
biotechnology discoveries made in other jurisdictions, and for those
wishing to import biological material which originates in other
countries for research.
In the first case, given that
biotechnological inventions have the potential to provide significant
health benefits, and to alleviate profound suffering, possibly for
great numbers of people, one must ask I think how should one approach
the use and practice of biotechnological discoveries, and the knowledge
that these may have been generated in ways which would be ethically and
legally unacceptable in a domestic setting.
This is unlikely to be a question
that can be resolved in the abstract, but nevertheless certain
parameters may be established. In the U.K., they are either codified
or implicit in the HFEA Act.
In the second case, and perhaps
more immediately, the question which must be addressed is to what
extent may research be allowed to progress on imported biological
material derived in a way that might not be acceptable locally.
This is a question which has
already risen in Europe with individual jurisdictions, and having to
find particular solutions to this problem. In conclusion, Chairman, I
would say that rather than simply lock the gateway to embryo research,
the British approach has been to appoint a gatekeeper.
The role and actions of this
gatekeeper will no doubt be the subject of infinite -- and I hope --
healthy debate, and I think it is particularly helpful to have
international debate.
I am not saying we should be
having an exchange of ideas about what is morally appropriate, right
and wrong, but we are actually faced with a situation where citizens
from the U.K. can say we can do it, and citizens in the U.S. say why
should I have to pay the airfare to get there. Thank you for inviting
me.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you very
much for a very lucid and forthcoming, and very responsible
presentation. May I ask just a few questions from the Chair?
Yours is really the only existing
regulatory body. There are lots of advisory commissions, and there are
other places that have statutes that prohibit certain sorts of things,
but this is a group that not only sits down regulations, and monitors,
and inspects.
And I guess my question is have
you had experience in finding things in which people are not playing by
the rules, and what has happened, (a).
And I guess a corollary to that
is what is the response of the regulated to what they perceive to be
unreasonable restrictions on practices that in fact could benefit
people's health.
In this country, we would have a
very hard time, I think, imposing these kinds of restrictions, and
having a monitoring system where there are penalties for
non-compliance. Has there been non-compliance, and what has happened,
and how do people react?
MS. LEATHER: Okay. Well,
firstly, I think there are some cultural differences in attitudes to
regulation between the U.K. and the U.S. I think that in contrast
perhaps to the U.S. that the U.K. -- and Helena can agree with me or
not on this, that we quite like a bit of regulation. It makes us feel
safe.
And indeed the Warnock Committee
report talked about this and establishing the 14 day boundary. That is
a 14 day boundary of what is in biological terms a process, and so in a
sense it is artificial to draw it to any one place.
But they were mindful of the need
to do that in order to establish public confidence, and that approach
has shown itself to be extremely successful, and we do want the whole
field safe for this. There is an important degree of acceptance of
moral consensus that that was the right boundary.
Now, you asked about the action
of the regulators. Well, I guess that most organizations -- and I
would include mine -- don't necessarily welcome the people that
regulate us. I mean, it is just a human response.
I think that most clinics see the
benefit of having a regulations structure because it clearly tells them
what they should and shouldn't do, and what they can and can't
do. It has the power or we have the power to close clinics if we find
that they really are doing things which they shouldn't be doing.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Have you ever?
MS. LEATHER: Yes, we have closed
clinics. And that also gives patients a degree of confidence, and I
think that it is interesting that quite a lot of people from other
European countries come to the U.K. to have treatment.
And I guess that one of the
reasons that they do that is not only that they have very good
information published by -- independent information published on the
success rates, but also they know that the practices in clinics is well
regulated.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Let me ask
also --
MS. LEATHER: Do people welcome
being put out of business? No, absolutely not, but I should say that
this is extremely rare, and we do annual inspections and inspection
teams go in, and they comprise different people.
So clinicians, scientists, and
nurses, counselors, and people with an expertise, and they will look at
the practices in the clinics, and say this isn't okay, or this is,
and change it. And we can make additions upon licenses, and give
people a certain amount of time to change practice.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Let me also
ask about commerce in gametes, and the like, and I know that you have a
policy on this, but I think it would be good for the record if you
would comment on that.
As you know, in this country
there are on the internet advertisements for oocytes, depending upon
one's accomplishments, and now up to $50,000. And even many of the
hospitals are now -- many institutions are charging now up to $7,500
for oocytes, and there is now competition for this in this country.
What is the British policy and
are people obeying?
MS. LEATHER: In the whole we
have tried to remove human tissue from the marketplace as far as
possible. So, we don't, for instance, pay blood donors. And the
same approach, and we have taken the same approach with regards to
gametes and embryos.
So you can get your expenses,
plus a little bit more, but it is a very, very small amount of money
for donating sperm and eggs. And we import, and we allow the
importation of sperm and eggs really on the same basis, and so we are
not happy with the idea that somebody should be a donor because they
were offered a great deal of money.
That said, there is of course
international trade as it were in gametes, and we are -- we do face a
shortage, and we have always faced a shortage of eggs, but we are not
facing quite a serious shortage of sperm.
And it may be that we may have to
review this policy. But also since 1991, the approach has been that
you shouldn't donate your characteristics so openly as you have
here.
So we have a kind of -- I suppose
that consumers in the U.K. are rather blinder than your consumers, in
terms of what they may be getting. We do go to great lengths to screen
for health reasons for sperm, for instance, but we don't say here
is somebody who has a Ph.D. in physics. Do you want this one rather
than someone who is a farmer.
CHAIRMAN KASS: But there is
this policy, but if individuals wanted to offer their gametes to
market, it is legal in Britain, or is it not?
MS. LEATHER: It is not legal for
the clinics to do that, no. You can't pay somebody a great deal of
money. What you can do is to donate eggs and get cheaper treatment.
We have allowed that to happen.
So you may say what is the
ethical difference to that, and that itself has been accepted, but it
does set up certain problems I think for some women, because it means
that somebody might have tried to have either treatment that has not
been successful, and they donated some of their eggs, and they have a
feeling that there is somewhere else a woman who has conceived using
her eggs. These are difficult problems.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you.
Michael Sandel.
PROF. SANDEL: I thought this was
a very instructive presentation, and it brings out very -- it seems to
me that the U.K. has struck a very sensible balance in this system, and
in this whole domain that we are still struggling towards, and it has
alluded us so far.
And what your presentation I
thought brought out very powerfully was the connection between the two
differences between the U.S. and the U.K. You mentioned that public
opinion in the U.K. is less polarized on these issues than in the
United States. And you also mentioned that there is more of a
tradition of government regulation, and its acceptance in the U.K., and
what struck me thinking about how you have arrived at this balance is
how connected those two things are.
It seems to me that in the United
States one of the reasons public opinion is so polarized on these
questions is precisely because there is such hostility at least in some
questions at least to government regulation because of the belief in
unfettered markets.
And that every choice, that every
decision about embryo research or stem cell research is all or
nothing. So that on the one hand, IVF clinics are completely
unregulated. Tattoo parlors or barber shops are required to more
licensing requirements than fertility clinics in the United States. We
don't regulate them at all.
So in principle, provided that it
is done with private funds, you could have not only sex selection, but
all kinds of trait selection, buying and selling, because we are such
believers in completely unfettered markets. We don't regulate even
IVF clinics.
And then when it comes to
discussing possibly life sustaining new technologies or forms of
research, we say, well, there would be a slippery slope here, because
it is against the background of an unfettered market and no regulation.
And no authority like yours to
actually enforce regulations on the clinics, and so if we accept a life
sustaining form of research here, well, it could lead to a parade of
horribles. The slippery slope argument.
And what your -- and so it is
either all or nothing. Either we must ban it, because if we permit it
in this purely unfettered market, then there is no way of stopping the
parade of horribles, the slippery slope.
And what your regulatory body
provides is a way to make the slope less slippery, and a way to -- and
that in turn permits the debate the public debate, about whether or not
to avail ourselves of this or that technology, or medical research.
It makes it possible for that
debate to proceed with less polarization, because it is not an all or
nothing affair. The slippery slope looms less large because of an
institution like yours.
MS. LEATHER: I think that is an
extraordinary insightful comment, and in fact when the debates were
being had in Parliament at the end of 2000 and 2001, people made
precisely that comment. We would have found it very difficult I think
as you did to accept therapeutic cloning if we hadn't had over a
decade of experience of responsible regulation that on the whole has
worked well.
No regulation is ever perfect,
and there are always going to be things that it doesn't know about,
but on the whole it has worked extremely well, and it is perceived as
having done so.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Gil
Meilanender and Rebecca, and Alfonso.
PROF. MEILAENDER: I have two
questions, and they are just factual ones, and they are entirely
unrelated I believe, but they just occurred to me at different
moments. One is that when you were discussing PGD and it can be done,
and if there is a possibility of a serious genetic disease, and you
said there was no list.
That in a sense it is a
determination made case by case, I guess, is what you said. But I just
wondered if you could narrow that for me. So that, for instance, would
something like cystic fibrosis constitute a serious genetic disease,
even though someone can live quite a lot time with it, for instance?
Would a propensity to
schizophrenia or something constitute a serious genetic disease? If
you could just sort of narrow it for me at all, just in terms of what
your own experience of cases tells, that would be interesting to me.
And then second, and an entirely
different kind of question, but you have 21 members I think you said on
the HFEA right now. And I am wondering if any of those 21 members
opposed, say, to embryo research, or would this way of dealing with the
question in a non-polarized setting effectively exclude from kind of
important roles in public deliberation people who held certain kinds of
views? So those are my two questions.
MS. LEATHER: Okay. Thank you
very much indeed. You have asked me to do precisely in a sense what we
have struggled to avoid, which is to start a list. In my view, yes,
cystic fibrosis is such a serious life threatening disease, and we have
accepted it for pre-implantation genetic diagnosis.
Schizophrenia has not obviously
come up yet, and were it to come up -- and I can only answer this in a
personal capacity at this stage. I was once a mental health manager,
which meant that we reviewed section orders for people who were
detained under mental health legislation, because I chaired the NHS
trust which provided mental health services.
My experience of people suffering
from certainly extreme forms of schizophrenia is that that is very deep
human suffering, and not only for that person, but for other people who
love and who are related to them.
So I would also regard that as
being in the category as it were. Your question about should we have
people who are opposed to it.
PROF. MEILAENDER: The question
is do you.
MS. LEATHER: No, we don't.
This does come up as an issue, and I think that the government has felt
in a sense of what would be the purpose of having somebody there. It
is not as if we are not continually reminded that there are many people
who hold very firm views against what we do.
And I believe that those views
should be respected, but they are out with the moral consensus in the
U.K. at the moment, and I don't think we need them continually on
the committee saying that I am opposed to all of this, and I am opposed
to all of this, because I think that would stop the decision making
that we have to do.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Rebecca.
Rebecca Dresser.
PROF. DRESSER: Thank you very
much for these two presentations showing us that at least it can be
done in some way. I had some questions about the -- I guess it is a
subcommittee or a separate committee that reviews the research
proposals, the embryo research proposals. Is that correct?
MS. LEATHER: A license
committee, yes. It is not in fact -- we can have license committees to
look at research proposals made up of Authority members, and in the
same way as we have license committees for treatment made up of
Authority members.
PROF. DRESSER: I was wondering,
as I understand that it does peer reviews, and so does it also include
non-scientists? And in reading our staff's description of your
system, and I guess on one of your slides you had some criteria, such
as the potential importance of the research, and whether the use of
human embryos is justified.
And I wondered if there is also
consideration of whether there are -- and perhaps this is part of the
last principle, alternative approaches to getting the same information,
and a justification for the embryos are the only alternative.
So I wondered if there are people
on there to make value judgments apart from scientists, and this ties
in a little bit with the previous question. And I guess it
wouldn't necessarily be that -- I mean, one position would be that
you could have some people who are very skeptical of using these, and
would oppose them at all times.
And then another would be that
there would be a range of opinions, and so there might be some people
who would say only in the very, very compelling case would it be
justified. And then there would be others that might take a more
liberal position.
And so I was interested in that
part, and then I just had one related question. It says in our
documents that you have received 135 applications for research
licenses, and of these 115 were granted.
I was curious whether you know
anything about the ones that were turned down and why, and then --
MS. LEATHER: Okay. Thanks very
much.
PROF. DRESSER: Should I ask one
more or wait until you --
MS. LEATHER: Let me deal with
those first. The question about the justiciability in a sense of using
embryonic stem cells rather than other stem cells. We are using that
justiciability, not in the moral sense. We have determined that has
been decided by Parliament.
But what we mean is this
scientifically justified, and one of the benefits of having the stem
cell bank, which we will have in the U.K., is that we will know exactly
what are the stem cell lines that are being created.
So it will be much easier for us
in reviewing potential research licenses to say that this hasn't
been done or this has been done. If it has already been done, it is
already there, and we don't need to do science twice, of use more
embryos unnecessarily.
The peer reviews that you talked
about, they are scientists. We do not or don't have lay peer
reviewers, but we do have lay members of the license committee, and
also low research ethics committees under the U.K. system also have lay
members when properly constituted. What was your other question?
PROF. DRESSER: The ones that
were turned down, the licenses?
MS. LEATHER: My guess is that
those researchers were trying to do something that either wasn't
licensable under the legislation, or we weren't satisfied that they
were the proper research group to do it. But if you would like me to
get back to you with further information, I can.
PROF. DRESSER: That might be
interesting.
MS. LEATHER: Okay.
PROF. DRESSER: The one other
question that I had was that in our notes it said that the 2001 law
included a prohibition on altering the genetic structure of any cell
while it forms part of an embryo.
MS. LEATHER: Yes.
PROF. DRESSER: And I wondered,
and maybe you could both comment on that, but does that mean a
prohibition on germ line interventions, or what was that all about?
MS. LEATHER: That means that you
can't do cell nuclear replacement on a blastomere. So we have
permitted it to be used in an egg, although as I have said in fact we
are waiting on the House of Lords' decision on whether embryos so
created, because they actually have not been created as a process of
fertilization, are in fact embryos within the terms of the Act as they
are already under the earlier legislation.
PROF. DRESSER: So our
understanding of this is that it just applies to the somatic cell
nuclear transfer organisms, whether they are embryos or not. I
wondered if there are any developments in the U.K. about germ line
interventions in humans that might be helpful for us to know about?
Has that been an issue on the table recently
Because we have some people here
in this country who are beginning to say that maybe we should start
thinking about this.
MS. LEATHER: Okay. I am not
aware of that, but again I will get back to you if that is different.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Alfonso.
DR. GÓMEZ-LOBO: Thank you for
the very clear presentation. I think I have more comments than
questions at this point, and in regard to Gill's second question, I
tend to see quite clearly that given that the mandate for the authority
for the HFEA is under the terms of the Act of Parliament, it seems
rational to say that only those persons who are in agreement should be
part of it.
I don't know, but it seems to
me a coherent reply. Now, that said, I would like to say that my own
opinion is that I hope we do not here in the United States adopt the
same procedure. And by procedure I mean the whole process.
I am starting from the widely
shared assumption I guess that morality is or should be above the law.
That the fact that the something has been enacted doesn't mean
necessarily that it is morally right, no matter how much consensus
exists.
That is the problem with ethics
always, and unfortunately it is not a matter of democracy. It is not a
matter of the majority of votes. It is a matter of reason, and
that's why I wanted to exclude any argument to the effect that some
of this would be based on religious beliefs, and therefore it is not
part of the public debate.
I hope that everything else is
well founded on reason, and not on theology. Now, what worries me a
lot is the fact that many of these ideas that we are enshrining in the
law were developed starting from the Warnock Report.
And for those of you who have not
read the report, I would like to stress one aspect of it, and it is
that philosophically that really it works with two ethical principles.
One is the principle of utilitarianism, which of course as we all know
justifies actions by reference to the consequences, the good
consequences.
And that is why utilitarians talk
a lot about balancing, and other traditions don't talk about
balancing. They only talk about balancing when it is morally
legitimate actions.
You know, should I go to this
movie, or to the movie, but if there is action, which by its very
nature is unethical, then of course there is no room for balancing that
action against any good that might come of it.
Now, that strain in the Warnock
report is tempered by an appeal to moral sentiments, which is very much
a British tradition coming from Hume, and while the contemporary
versions of that are so-called emotivism, but there the question is
only whether certain kinds of actions are going to emotionally affect
people.
People are going to say, oh, this
is terrible, and I feel that this is terrible and I shouldn't do
it. But I don't see a real deep meditation based for instance on
the -- well, on other ways of doing moral philosophy.
Now, I don't want to go into
a lecture here, but my own preference in the United States would be to
have that deep ranging debate because the perils of utilitarianism are
really very great indeed.
Practically anything could be
justified by reference to good ends. I can think of severe
restrictions of civil rights in the United States in order to fight
terrorism.
I lived through a very well known
application of utilitarian principles during the military dictatorships
in Argentina and Chile, where the justification of torture was always
that, oh, this is going to benefit so many people, and in so many ways.
Now, of course, there is an
important difference there, several kinds, but again it is this pattern
of thought that it seems to me that we should be very well aware.
And the question is, well, are
there any cases in which wonderful ends simply do not justify means.
So that is a problem that I have here. Now, of course, all of this
depends on the 14 days decision. And the Warnock report, of course,
admits that it is totally artificial.
I mean, there is no doubt about
that. There is a human embryo developing according to a genetic
program, and it is making progress in the direction that is well known
to embryologists and to myself, and therefore, it just doesn't seem
rational to me to say, oh, here we have a cut-off point.
Everyone agrees I think that the
cut-off point is something of a convenience, and I'm sorry that
Mike Gazzaniga is not here, and something as he said that I feel
comfortable with.
Well, it is not a matter of
whether we feel comfortable with or not. It is what is there, and what
is this organism, and what are its properties, and what is its nature.
How is it different from other
organisms, and of course all of that is something that has to be looked
at before we take the step of saying that there is no need to respect
dignity before 14 days, and there is a need to respect dignity after 14
days, although there, there is the morally questionable provision in
the law if I read it correctly, and it is that the embryo should be
destroyed, or should not be allowed to go beyond the 14 days.
I suppose that an embryo could be
frozen at that point, right? But again --
MS. LEATHER: I'm sorry, but
the 14 days doesn't include the freezing time, but you can't
freeze something on day 13 and then do a lot more work on it later.
BARONESS KENNEDY: I believe that
wasn't what was being suggested.
DR. GÓMEZ-LOBO: No, it was. It
was. It=s just, you know my ignorance, but from a moral point of view
it=s along the same lines. So, my encouragement to the United States,
and I feel a deep moral responsibility, being a U.S. citizen and being
a member of this council, is that all of these philosophical issues
that are going to inform the law should be a matter of great concern
and a deep debate. And again, we, I think, as a counsel should try to
work on that. Now, baroness Kennedy says we=ll never agree. I don=t
know. I=m a socratic, and I would not foreclose a discussion before
it=s even started. Well, it has already started. I just trust that
there has to be, there has to be, a rational way of discussing these
things. I was reminded, for instance, of the remark by Bill Hurlbut in
Nature magazine this past July. There was an article that=s quite
illustrative of what goes on in the human embryo before the 14 days. So
I would say the science doesn=t allow us to decide this of course, but
the science, the new insights into embryology, into how important those
few hours or days are, those are clues, those are part of the evidence
I think that we have to take into account when we advise the republic
on what we should do in these matters. Not the kingdom, but the
republic.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you. I have frank
and the two Bills. And we will B okay.
PROF. FUKUYAMA: I have a couple
of questions about the politics of the HFEA. The Human Fertilisation
Embryology Act was put forward under a conservative government, but you
said party discipline didn=t apply so it was a free vote. And there
was a very large majority in both parties in favor. Could you just
talk a little bit about the politics of that? I mean was there, for
example, particularly strong opposition from the British IVF industry
to being regulated in an area where it had been left up to
self-regulation, and just how did it fall out between the different
political positions, ideological positions?
And then the second question is a
procedural one about who has the authority to appoint the 21 members?
And if there is .. I mean, presumably, there's not been a lot of ..
well, actually, this is a question. I mean in cases where there's
division among those 21 members, what are your procedures for coming to
a decision?
MS. LEATHER: Thanks very much.
The question of self-regulation, were the clinics opposed to it? No,
they weren't, and in fact there was this self-regulatory model. So
I think what the clinics wanted and what the researchers wanted was
certainty about what the country as a whole thought was okay. And you
colleague talked of it as just a sort of pragmatic decision and it was
just to do with outcomes, and it wasn't. I mean the debate was
also about right and wrong, and it continues to be.
But it wasn't .. the votes
that were taken were free votes, and within all the parties there is a
range of views about the ethics of this. I don't think it's
fair to say that one party is particularly more divided than another,
really. There's a range of views everywhere.
PROF. SANDEL: On the free vote,
when Frank was talking about the free vote, I think he was referring to
the vote on expanding the research purposes. You said that was a free
vote ..
MS. LEATHER: Yes.
PROF. SANDEL: .. not the vote to
set up the authority in the first place.
MS. LEATHER: That was free, yes,
yes. All these procedures have been passed on free votes.
You asked about who appoints to
the authority. They are ministerial appointments, and some people come
and go, but they don't .. there's no automatic change if the
administration changes, nothing like that. How do we vote? Do we
vote? We try and achieve a consensus, and that is not always
possible. So, for instance, we have recently had a debate about
whether we should get rid of donor anonymity, and most of us felt that
in fact we shouldn't say to people who have been created as a
result of IVF that they had less right to know their genetic origins
than everybody else. So we thought, and our advice to government, is
that prospectively we should get rid of donor anonymity but not
respectively, that there should be a voluntary register considered for
donor information, retrospectively. But some people disagreed with
that. Some people felt that it was wrong to get rid of donor anonymity
because of the effect, for instance, on the supply of sperm that the
Chairman referred to earlier.
PROF. FUKUYAMA: But do you
actually have internal procedural rules? Let's say in the future
you got a really polarized issue. Could 11 members vote against ten
members to make a decision?
MS. LEATHER: I think as a Chair
in that case I would say we are undecided about this, and if we are so
undecided about this, it seems pretty difficult to proceed to change.
BARONESS KENNEDY: Can I just
comment on that?
MS. LEATHER: A bit like the
position you're in, perhaps, sir.
BARONESS KENNEDY: I'm just
going to comment on that. On the recent decision that was made by the
HFEA on the Hashmi case and the other cases that were mentioned where
pre-genetic diagnosis was allowed for a subsequent child. There was
quite a lot of controversy over that, and there was a feeling that that
sort of matter should, because it's so controversial, should back
before a committee of the House of Commons. I mean there was some
debate about whether that was a course that should be taken. Now, the
decisions were made and they were made with sufficient unanimity, but
if there were the sort of tightness that you're describing of seven
to six, I think that there would be a feeling that it would not be
something that should be left to the HFEA.
MS. LEATHER: I mean that vote,
that decision was taken against a background of public consultation, so
we were guided partly by what the public response to that had been. If
there were issues that were very new about which the public had never
had an opportunity to debate, then I think Helena's point is even
more strongly made.
DR. GÓMEZ-LOBO: Yes. Very
briefly, it's a clarification. I don't doubt for a second that
the question of right and wrong is raised. The question is how
it's answered. If it's answered by reference to consequences,
then, you know, we're clearly in utilitarian context.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Bill May, then Bill
Hurlbut.
PROF. MAY: I'm not clever
enough to put my ruminations in the form of question, but I do want to
return the discussion to the question of regulation. Oftentimes our
difficulties with regulation are explained in terms of the fact
we're not an island, we're a continent. There's another
way of explaining that where we say, "You're at fault,"
because this country emerged in the setting of rebellion against King
George III, and we tend to think of the government still as a kind of
foreign power, not an instrument of national purpose, which tends to
make us suspicious of regulatory agencies, especially on the part of
the national government. And it carries through in our suspicion of
bureaucrats, a sign of which is either we starve regulatory agencies,
we don't provide enough regulators in the SEC or the IRS and so
forth so that the private economy operates as it will, or we hem in our
bureaucrats massively with regulations. That's the other response
of suspicion to bureaucrats. So bureaucracy happily metastasizes at
the hands of its sworn enemies. It's a huge irony in American
life.
Meanwhile, we're given to a
kind of mysticism of the marketplace which tends to make us overlook
the bureaucratic complexities of corporations at play in the
marketplace. In Dallas, I was very impressed by Ken Anderson, the
President of the Parkland Hospital. Given the complexity of the
economics of our health care system, he said he needs 300 people to
handle accounts to yield the payoffs on bills and so forth, which in
fact the Vancouver City Hospital handles with only six people.
It's a very interesting, high degree of suspicion as it relates to
the government and bureaucrats but incredible tolerance of the
emergence of the bureaucracy in the setting of the private economy.
That is not in the form of a question but an introspective comment
generated by your presence here.
(Laughter.)
CHAIRMAN KASS: So noted. Bill
Hurlbut. We're going to move toward break and then to lunch. Bill
Hurlbut and then Paul.
DR. HURLBUT: I want to return to
the complex issue of what you called selection for characteristics as
part of a larger consideration. In deciding about sex selection
techniques, let's speak of pre-implantation genetic diagnosis, is
your concern there with the dangers of characteristics per se and
gender biasing and so forth or are you also concerned about using that
kind of a technique itself? I mean what is exactly going on in the
mind? I mean why not do it, actually?
MS. LEATHER: Why not select for
social reasons?
DR. HURLBUT: Yes.
MS. LEATHER: Well, people have a
number of problems with this or a number of issues, and I suppose the
most important and perhaps the most difficult to express is the feeling
that if people select the sex of their child, there's something
about wanting to do that decision which undermines the essential
quality of parent love, which is unconditionality. And I think there
is a feeling, and certainly our focus work that debated this came up
with this as an issue. Was it actually okay to want to do that, to
want something particular about your child? And would you be
disappointed if it didn't go right?
DR. HURLBUT: Well, for some
people, some social groups and some families, it could be a matter of
balancing first, which does not weigh quite as heavily as just simply
wanting a specific characteristic maybe. But also for some social
groups a very serious matter, use that word "serious"
concerns. To them it's extending the definition of disease into
social realities. I mean you probably .. I don't know what you do
with growth hormone, but you know what I'm talking about, some
cosmetic surgeries are acceptable for social reasons, disfiguring
repairs and so forth.
What I'm getting at here is
is there something about the .. I understand you preempt even sperm
selection, but is there something about the investigation of an embryo
that is even more troubling in that context? No.
MS. LEATHER: I'm not quite
sure I understand what you're saying.
DR. HURLBUT: Well,
pre-implantation genetic diagnosis for what you're calling not
serious things, why not do it? I mean it's .. what I'm trying
to get at is the status of the embryo, according to your principles, is
one that is due respect but not due inviolability, right? Because
otherwise you couldn't justify certain practices like so-called
therapeutic cloning. Do you see what I'm getting at?
MS. LEATHER: Yes. In discussing
the difference between the Hashmi case and the Whitaker case, perhaps I
didn't make it quite clear, but one of the things that worried the
authority was the idea of using somebody as a means to someone
else's ends and, additionally, to exposing them to an
unquantifiable risk where that person wasn't going to benefit. By
definition, somebody else was going to benefit.
DR. HURLBUT: Okay. What I'm
getting at here is even pre-implantation genetic diagnosis for a
serious disorder involves a risk to the normal embryo, right? Because
yesterday one of our speakers told us there was a 50 percent decrease
in successful implantation after this investigation of a given embryo.
Does that .. I'm just asking for your rumination of this, because
I'm trying to figure out in my own mind about it, is that real?
MS. LEATHER: I think goes back
really to the fact that we have .. it's not as if we've ended
the debate on the embryo up to 14 days; it's still there in the
public mind as an important issue. But it's not the focus of
debate. It really is not the focus of debate. We've now moved
through that and we are concerned more about what are the
characteristics we should allow people to choose for and against.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I think we'll move
on. Paul and then we're going to break.
DR. MCHUGH: I also want to thank
you for that helpful discussion and presentation, Ms. Leather, and I
want to come back, really, to also the very important point that
Michael made at our beginnings; that is, whatever is going to happen
here in the United States occurs in this remarkable context of the
free-heeling approaches that we've taken to these matters before.
In fact, for me this is a very telling issue in relationship to the
ultimate development of our regulations related to SCNT and its
products. I'm happy to hear that the House of Lords is struggling
to decide whether the term "embryo" should be applied to
that. We've gone so far in this Council, or at least I've gone
so far in this Council, as to try to impose a new word under that
product to differentiate it from a zygote with only modest success. So
the Lords in their decision-making, in their discussions would be fun
for me to listen to.
But I have two very practical ..
PROF. FUKUYAMA: They'd take
you more seriously.
DR. MCHUGH: Britain, you think
they would? I doubt it. This brings me to two very practical
questions, and it relates to our interest in what regulations would do
and what openness would do in relationship to SCNT even for the best
benefits that we're all very interested in. And one of them is
does your system now, your regulatory system, make it possible for
there to be careful thought about what use over denucleated ova would
be put to in the scientific context of the research so that we
wouldn't develop an open market for searching for thousands and
thousands of eggs and turning many, many women into egg factories?
That's a very important concern to me, and that issue would be
helpful to hear how you have thought about that and where that has
come.
And then the other simple thing,
again, like everybody here at the table, we admire the way the British
are willing to queue up and stay in line .. I just had a fight down in
the front about people not being in a queue or me not being in a
queue. It was a very amusing American scene.
(Laughter.)
But when you were developing your
regulatory bodies and your regulatory processes, was there any
hinderance or hold back of investigations that were going on while the
regulations were being put in place or was there simply a parallel
process, research was going on will-nilly and the regulations were
either catching up with it or not? Those are my two questions.
MS. LEATHER: Okay. I'll try
an answer as best I can. Before the HFEA was set up there was research
and treatment going on. That's different from what's happened
since it's been set up. Since it's been set up all research
and treatment is regulated, okay? So I think that clears that one up.
DR. MCHUGH: Was there a
hesitation period during the process of setting up the regulations
where you said, "Hold on now, you guys. Don't do anything
until you hear from us." Was there?
MS. LEATHER: You're not
allowed to do it unless it's been licensed.
BARONESS KENNEDY: No, but there
was a period .. before the HFEA came into the being ..
DR. MCHUGH: Yes.
BARONESS KENNEDY: .. there was a
period when people were asked again, it wasn't a formal moratorium
but they were asked to hold back on what they were doing ..
DR. MCHUGH: I see.
BARONESS KENNEDY: .. while this
was being debated and so on. And people in Britain, as you have
suggested, are willing to do that. There's a sort of way in which
generally people are prepared to ..
DR. MCHUGH: So the scientific
community was willing to accept this voluntary moratorium. It came
forward and said, "We accept this for ourselves voluntarily while
you, whether a week or a month or years, you set up your things."
That happened?
MS. LEATHER: Yes. What the
scientific community wanted was long-term security ..
DR. MCHUGH: Yes, yes.
MS. LEATHER: .. about what it
was and wasn't allowed to do.
DR. MCHUGH: And it was willing
to pay the price ..
BARONESS KENNEDY: The scientific
community in fact were the initiators. They came into the domain and
said, "We're doing this work. We want to know how the public
feels about this. Where are the parameters on this?" That was
how ..
DR. MCHUGH: I love to hear
this. I hope the scientific community in the United States is
listening and bringing forward something other than signatures.
MS. LEATHER: I think your other
question was about consent and donation and we've set down specific
guidelines for the consent issues involved in donating embryos and
gametes which will be used in deriving stem cell lines, because the
issues for donors I think are rather different. The House of Lords
drew attention to the immortal, as it were, nature, the unceasing
nature of stem cell lines. That has to be explained very carefully to
donors as it has to be explained that although other people may benefit
financially, eventually from the knowledge and possibly from products
derived from applying stem cell line knowledge they as donors won't
be part of that. So we've already drawn that up.
DR. MCHUGH: So, therefore, you
explain to the donors, the voluntary donors, that what is going to
happen or what the implications of this contribution are is. I want to
know whether it worked also from the other direction; that is, that
well-trained scientists and well-developed laboratories and things of
that sort were considered before eggs were being harvested from women.
Here in the United States, for example, in the NIH, one of the issues
in deciding about a research grant is to look at the institution
that's making this application and deciding whether those
laboratories or those people are skilled enough or are effective enough
or have the resources to do what they claim to do in this research.
And many research projects, even though that they are well designed by
the author, are turned down because it said as yet this institution has
not developed the expertise to do this, and we don't want to waste
the resources or the money on the other things on that. And I'm
just wondering whether they considered .. whether your place you are
considering such things before you let donors come forward and give
this important tissue away.
MS. LEATHER: Indeed, we do
consider that, and it would not be permissible for people to use eggs
or sperm or embryos donated for research but not knowingly donated for
stem cell research for stem cell research.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you very much.
Let me make a procedural suggestion to members of Councils. I think we
should conclude this session and thank both of our visitors for really
wonderful presentations and the wonderful spirit of forthright and
responsive conversation. You stimulated us a lot and we have things to
learn, and I do hope that we can remain in contact with you in the
months and years ahead as we go forward.
This was the original scheduled
time for a break for 15 minutes before we reconvened. There are
members of Council who would like to leave early, who have planes to
catch, and although it would be nice to rise and say farewell to our
guests, if we would liberate them from the table but the rest of us
stay, I think we .. my hope is that we can conduct our business in this
session with dispatch and people will not have to leave before the
decision is taken. Is that agreeable?
So that is Council members will
simply stay and let me just thank you both.
(Applause.)