Friday, March 7, 2003
Session 6: Biotechnology and Public Policy:
Professional Self-Regulation
George J. Annas, J.D., M.P.H.,
Edward R. Utley Professor & Chair,
Department of Health Law, Bioethics & Human Rights,
Boston University School of Public Health, and
Professor, Boston University School of Medicine and School of Law
CHAIRMAN KASS: I'd like to get started and in
ten seconds call on George Annas for his response, and afterwards
we'll consider the two presentations together, and people who were
still in the queue for comment before, I still have your names and
you will not be forgotten.
I did want to mention to everyone present that the council's Web
site has been redesigned since the last meeting, and I'd like to
call your attention especially to a feature of which we are particularly
proud: selection of readings from our bookshelf, supervised by Rachel
Wildavsky, which now has three sets of readings up there in the
spirit of "Toward a Richer Bioethics," in addition of
the one on "Among the Generations." We have something
on scientific aspirations, and something on the pursuit of perfection.
There are things coming along on vulnerability and things on "Many
Stages, One Life." So please keep your eye open for what's
coming there.
George Annas, thank you very much for joining us. The floor is
yours.
MR. ANNAS: Thank you, Mr. Chairman.
I don't look at this so much as a response as another view, let's
say, of self-regulation.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Please.
MR. ANNAS: All right. I'm a regulator, and I'm
very comfortable regulating things. I've spent my life with physicians.
So I'm comfortable trying to regulate physicians, as well.
I do believe most of them need regulation, and often they are
very happy to be involved in it, but, on the other hand, as we know
from the current debate on medical malpractice, they're not particularly
fond of physicians or with lawyers -- I'm sorry -- and not particularly
fond of private lawsuits.
So when you look at the area of how to regulate any industry or
activity, you have choices of the market, the market in private
lawsuits, professional self-regulation if you're a professional,
or some form of government regulation, or even as I'm going to suggest
at the end, a hybrid, government-private type of regulation similar
to that which we have in organ donation and organ transplantation
in the United States.
So first, just a bit of my own biases. I started my career part
time on the Board of Registration of Medicine in Massachusetts.
I spent six years on that board regulating physicians as its vice
chairman and chairman of its complaint committee and enjoyed that
quite a lot.
Then I was the chair of the Massachusetts Organ Transplant Task
Force whose job was to try to produce regulations to introduce liver
and heart transplantation into Massachusetts. As many of you know,
the most expensive and probably the -- they think they're the best
as well. We all think they're the best -- medical system in the
world, the most expensive medical system in the world.
And we made it much more expensive by making sure not just one
hospital, but four hospitals did liver transplantation in the first
year it was introduced.
I am, as you've mentioned, Mr. Chairman, past member of the ethics
committee of ASRM and happy to take responsibility for the many
documents that came out while I was on the committee. Rebecca has
told you those were all consensus documents, and in my years on
the committee, our chairman was one of the most distinguished people
in the contemporary history of bioethics, Dr. Ken Ryan, who died
recently.
But Dr. Ryan was an unbelievable chairman. I mean, he was as knowledgeable
as you can be about the field and also knowledgeable about regulation.
He was, as many of you recall, the chairman of the first national
commission for the protection of subjects of biomedical and behavioral
research.
That commission met from 1973 to 1981, and its regulations were
essentially all but one adopted and put in the Federal Register
and form the basis of the current common rule for all human experimentation
that is governed by those regs. in the United States.
And Dr. Ryan ran a terrific committee, and I think the deliberations
of that committee speak for themselves.
And there are some problems with self-regulation that the committee,
which is, I think, as good as you can do, by the way; I'm not going
to critique any members of the committee or any of the motivation
of having such a committee, but I'm going to critique the reality
of how you put a committee like that into existence and what happens
to its rules.
There are a number of critiques of professional self-regulation
that I'm sure you're familiar with. The most recent one is by medical
historian David Rothman. He wrote a very powerful op-ed piece in
the New England Journal of Medicine two years ago called "Medical
Professionalism, Focusing on the Real Issues."
And Professor Rothman argued actually that medical professionalism
had to be invented. It couldn't be restored; that there really never
was a time -- maybe it's a little harsh, but this is David talking,
and I'm sure he would defend it -- there never really was a time
when physicians could be said not to have bad interest in themselves
first.
And, of course, you'd say that's true of everybody in society.
When they weren't more interested in their income, their control,
their autonomy, and what they could do in terms of practicing medicine
without outside interference, and I certainly saw that on the Board
of Registration in medicine.
Our Medical Society in Massachusetts, like all the other medical
societies around the world, was not very happy about being regulated.
And if they were going to be regulated, they wanted a majority.
Well, we had five out of seven of our members were physicians. They
wanted physicians doing the regulation, and in some sense I don't
blame them.
But as David Rothman argues in this piece, in order to do that,
you have to go beyond self-interest, and you have to really do things
that are in the interest of the public.
David gives six recommendations to invent professionalism. I just
want to mention the fifth one because it's specifically relevant
to what we're talking about today. He said, "Professional organizations
must be persuaded to expand the agenda for which they lobby and
advocate." And then he goes on and says nearly all of these
organizations advocate for themselves for making sure that insurance
or government programs cover whatever it is they do, and as he calls
it, the special interest of organizations' members.
And then he suggests something which he says he's gotten more
hate mail than for anything he has ever written in his life. He
suggests that it's, you know, de riguer for the dermatologist to
say we should cover more dermatology services, ophthalmologists
say we should cover cataract surgery, et cetera, and for our gastroenterologists
to say we should cover colorectal cancer treatment therapy or screening.
I'm sorry.
Imagine, he says, what could have happened if these societies
had advocated for the well-being of patients without regard for
their own self-interest. Support by dermatologists and ophthalmologists
for colorectal cancer screening, he said, would carry great weight
in the debate over whether to include it as a benefit. Again, he
says the barriers to such activities are formidable, and he obviously
thinks how the public might respond to advocacy that was driven
not by narrow self-interest, but by broader professional vision
of patients' welfare.
Now, of course, the hate mail he got was from gastroenterologists.
So he went to what in the hell do dermatologists know about colorectal
screening and, you know, quite properly so. But the issue is not
a technical issue. The issue is what are your goals; whose interest
do you care about; and how do you further those interests.
And the notion that professionals, if they're to be professionals
have an obligation to go beyond this self-interest that non-professionals
go to. That's essentially a trivial -- well, not a trivial point.
he makes it very well. It's actually a critical issue. It's can
professional committees, can professional self-regulation go beyond
the interests of the members and look to protect patient welfare
in general.
In my experience on the ASRM ethics committee, it's certainly
possible but very difficult. The ethics committee couldn't do it
itself, as Rebecca has pointed out. The Executive Committee gets
to approve anything that the Ethics Committee points out, and then
after that, what enforcement there is if anyone knows about them
is often up in the air.
Nonetheless, t he fundamental question is what's the charge of
an ethics committee. What's the charge of having rules for your
members, and I spent six years on this committee, as I say. I take
full responsibility for everything I did.
On year three, which I think was around 1995, when we had on the
agenda things like post menopausal pregnancies, using fetal ova
to try to create a pregnancy. On the committee that's one of the
few thins the committee said should never be done, which is great,
and disposition of embryos, et cetera. All of these issues were
on our committee.
And before that committee or just as that committee meeting started,
I asked the chairman if I could summarize what I thought the committee's
operating assumptions were, and here's what I said, and I thought
this was an insightful critique. I said: here's our operating assumptions.
Number one, the ethical acceptability of new reproductive technologies
is to be assumed, and the burden of proof is on anyone who would
question a new technology to show how its use is unethical.
Number two, the use of a new technology cannot be declared unethical
if there are any possible ethical applications of that technology
no matter how hypothetical.
Number three, it is assumed that imagined new technologies will
ultimately work and will prove beneficial, and that any imagined
harm from the technology expected can be controlled unless proven
otherwise.
And number four, the major values to be taken into account in
evaluating new reproductive technologies are economic-- efficiency,
supply and cost-- and not ethical.
Now, I thought this was a critique, and so I was a little surprised
when Chairman Ryan turned to me and said, "George, well, of
course that's exactly right. That is how we operate and are operating.
That is our operating assumptions," and indeed, they were.
And in one sense, you know, you'd say, well, gee, you know, you
should have different operating assumptions, and I think we should,
but on the other hand, another way to say that is we believe in
what we're doing, and the burden of proof should be on other people
to prove to us that there is some harm or some other aspect that
comes into this.
Well, let me suggest a couple of other operating assumptions that
we could have instead of these. Actually Dr. Carson suggested some,
which I like a lot. She suggested safety efficacy and privacy. That
would actually be better than the ones we worked on, and even better
yet, healthy children, healthy parents, and healthy third parties.
That's terrific. That was not in existence when I was there. In
fact, I argued at a meeting of this society in Toronto not as a
member of the committee, but as a person giving a speech there that
the organization should take a firm position that their number one
concern was children.
That to my knowledge hasn't happened, but nonetheless the language
"healthy children" is a big change from my perspective
at least.
And the second thing that I think is necessary and have argued
for that is for the group to think more like physicians. Now, what
do I mean by that?
Well, even though actually your Chairman and I have argued about
the Hippocratic Oath in a prior life here, in terms of the Hippocratic
principle, first do no harm, that makes perfect sense to me in terms
of doing reproductive technologies, and do no harm to children strikes
me as the right principle to use as a starting point.
And then the second principle is to always take the welfare of
your patients as the first priority.
Now, if we started with those assumptions instead of the operating
assumption of the current chairman of the committee, which is procreative
liberty, and John Robertson is an old friend of mine. We go back
30 years, and we've been debating our whole lives and we'll never
agree with each other, and I'm not trying to score cheap points
against John. Procreative liberty is very important, but it's not
the only value. It's not the only value in society, and it's not
one that can determine everything that happens because you start
with procreative liberty. You take as an assumption that people
can do whatever they understand with informed consent that they
agree to, and that the only thing that could possibly stand in the
way is if someone could prove that there were significant harms
to a child that would not have been born but for the procedure.
Sine it is never possible to prove the second thing, you wind
up that you can always do -- that the rule is, and this is the operating
ethical rule of physicians in general, not just our own physicians,
that as long as I want to do it, it's accepted medical practice
and my patient gives informed consent, leave me alone.
And that's basic medicine today, and mostly not just here, but
mostly all right, and that's why most regulation in medicine is
done by private lawsuits and malpractice and why we have even with
the Institute of Medicine and four years afterwards talking about
100,000 deaths a year caused by physicians. We have really no movement
in the patient safety movement, no real desire by physicians to
try to clean up their act in general, and an almost impossible situation
where it is seen that the only say we can move forward is to protect
physicians against liability and keep errors secret, even though
all of the surveys show that patients want to know immediately if
doctors have harmed them due to errors.
The other models that are used in the new reproductive technologies,
and I have the one handout that I did give you in your materials,
pretty much a summary of my views of the field from my 25 years
as an outsider, are that it got started off on the wrong foot, and
my friend a colleague, Dr. Sherman Elias, a geneticist-obstetrician,
and I wrote a piece in JAMA in 1986 on this, that, again, your Chairman
was kind enough to review and give us some really good suggestions
on.
Then I got started using the artificial insemination by donor
model, and that was a big mistake, and we still use that as you
heard even in valuing how much a woman's egg is worth. We try to
figure out how much a sperm donor's time using sperm is worth, but
the sperm donor model was a mistake because historically the first
thing doctors did after they used donor sperm was literally to destroy
the records.
They don't do that anymore, but the idea was that you had to protect
the best interest of the sperm donor, even at the expense of the
best interests of the child. So if the child wanted to find out
later who his or her genetic father was, it was not possible. That's
been more or less changed now. Actually adequate record keeping
is required, but it's still extraordinarily difficult for children
of AID to find out the identity of their genetic father.
That's a bad model. I mean the last thing you want in medicine
is secrecy, it seems to me. You do want confidentiality, but you
certainly don't want secrecy from the people involved. You may want
it from society in general, but we've used that model not only to
figure out how records should be kept, what kind of confidentiality
and privacy there should be, but also to move over into a place
where I think and have argued unsuccessfully it has no place at
all, which is an ovum donation, which is nothing like sperm donation
at all. As you've heard, it's a medical procedure with major risks.
There's sharp limit of the number of ovum women can donate, and
there can be, you know, significant problems to this.
To equate it with sperm donation makes no sense, but nonetheless
we say we want gender equality and so we have to do that.
A number of people have mentioned it, even though we want to talk
about individual things, this statement at Tab 19 on financial incentives
to ovum donors, and I think I was off the committee when it actually
came out, but I was certainly honored when it was developed. So
it's another one I have to take responsibility for.
But one of the things in there which I thought was critical and
the committee was willing to put it in is that every ovum donor
should have their own physician. Okay? And what I meant by that
and what the committee meant by that is not a physician, you know,
who is involved in the IVF procedure, is already committed to the
couple or committed to make sure that eggs are gotten for these
particular patients, but is committed to this person as a patient,
to this woman who's undergoing a significant procedure with significant
risks.
And that's because I believe in two things, which is not shared
by a lot of people in the field. Number one, that there should be
no purchase and sell of eggs; that that's a problem; that that commercialization
of eggs is a problem, and it's a subterfuge to call this just giving
money for inconvenience.
And, number two, that any physician who's worthy of the name would
not subject his patient to a risky procedure just for the sake of
being paid for their inconvenience. It can't be done. It can't be
justified.
It can barely be justified in kidney donation, live kidney donation.
Even that's problematic, but at least there you have someone with
a terminal illness whose only option is to undergo dialysis, and
it can barely be justified there.
But even there we will not pay that person to donate their kidney.
That's a much more vigorous, heroic thing the person does under
those circumstances.
So in any event, I think it's problematic. The role of physicians
is problematic, and if you're going to be a physician and deal with
things like egg donation, you have to, it seems to me, put the best
interest of your patient first, do no harm first, and there are
some things that you just have to say we can't do.
Yesterday's Wall Street Journal, some of you may have read this.
A movement or not a movement, but a trend around the country and
certainly in Europe and Australia to do away with the drugs, the
hyperstimulation drugs, and then you can only retrieve one egg a
cycle and obviously it cuts down on your ability to do that, but
it's much, much, much better for the women involved in terms of
risk, and it turns out to be much cheaper, too, although long term
studies haven't done -- will have to say how successful it is to
see in the long run and how much less expensive it is.
But the point is there are alternatives that don't put healthy
women at risk for money.
The second problem, and I'll just go through this quickly, is
a problem of private contract. Because the entire system is seen
as private, personal, and secret, the notion is that instead of
having rules that apply to everybody, we should be able to contract
and define our own rules.
The New York Task Force on Assisted Reproductive Technology and
virtually every task force that's looked at this, public group that's
looked at this has said, for example, that they believe that the
proper rule should be the rule, and it actually is a rule in at
least 48 states of this country, maybe 49, that the woman who gives
birth to the child should be considered the child's legal mother
for all purposes.
That's not the rule in California, and the rule in California
is that the legal mother is the, quote, intended mother. And who
is the intended mother? It's whatever the couple, the surrogate
or whoever is involved in this decide by contract beforehand who
will be the mother.
That to me, as I wrote in this article that you have makes no
sense. I think whatever rule we have we have to be able to identify
the mother at the time of birth, and she has to be there with the
rights and responsibilities for the child, and the only woman who
is going to be there at birth is the birth mother obviously, and
she's the woman we've always considered the mother, and it seems
to me that for the child's sake and her own, that presumption should
continue and no private contract should be able to change that.
Nonetheless, this is not just ASRM talking. This is California
Supreme Court thinks that that's okay, and again, the California
Supreme Court did this on the basis of sperm donation, and they
said, "Look. If we can figure out who the father is by contract
and keep the name and identity of the sperm donor secret, we should
be able to figure out who the mother is by contract as well.
And, again, I think that that analogy does not hold, that the
court is wrong about that, but nonetheless that explains why most
surrogate mother contracts are done in California, and it also helps
explain a tremendous cultural shift between the days of Mary Beth
Whitehead when we had pictures and lawsuits and people wondering
what was going on, and today when you look on the newsstand today
People Magazine, something I read every week. No, but you should
read this if you're involved in this. This is a celebration of surrogate
motherhood and donor egg when Joan London has hired a surrogate
and gotten eggs from someone else to have twins for her and her
husband in her second marriage.
I'm not saying there's anything wrong with that, but I'm saying
she shouldn't be able to make up who's going to be the mother and
who's going to be the father; that we should know who the mother
and the father is for the sake of the children, regardless of whether
the surrogate is from Ohio, as she is here, or the contract was
made in California or that there was some other arrangement. That
shouldn't be a matter of private contract.
So those are my primary problems with the current regime. Nonetheless,
let me say I think ASRM -- and I actually do believe this -- has
done just about as well as you can do in terms of private self-regulation.
It is actually a model.
If you go around and look at some of the others, with the exception,
I think, of pediatrics, but I think pediatrics is an exception because
their patients can't give consent, and they know they have extra
obligations to the children patients they have.
And you can't have a contract informed consent model with a child.
So with the exception of the American Academy of Pediatrics, all
of whose statements are child centers and all of whose statements
begin with the best interests of the child is paramount, and almost
every other medical specialty has the basic rule that if the doctor
and the patient agree to it, it should be permissible using informed
consent documents.
Okay. Those are kind of easy questions, you know, because it's
easy to say what problems exist and what can be done around the
edges. The much harder question, and I'll just throw out a few minutes
of this and then we can discuss it, is if you wanted to regulate,
number one, is it possible. Could the public actually get involved
in this?
And, two, what are the models that exist that could be pursued?
Before you start regulating, before you even think about regulating,
obviously the first question you've got to ask is why. What's the
problem that you're trying to address because it is very, very,
very possible to create more problems than you solve, to be totally
counterproductive in doing regulation, just as it's possible to
create more problems than you solve doing ethical statements.
By the way, I may have misunderstood this statement that you made,
Sandy. If I did, I'm sorry, but it doesn't really matter because
the point is that these statements require interpretation. The disposition
of abandoned embryos, which I've signed off on and helped writing,
and I certainly agree it makes perfect sense to me and we shouldn't
keep embryos frozen forever, and that after some period of time
when you lose contact with the gamete donors, that you should be
able to destroy those embryos, and that the position taken here
was five years destroy the embryos. I think that's fine.
We also tried to make it clear, but obviously did not as I read
this again that you should not be able to use those embryos for
research or to donate to another couple without explicit consent,
but I could see how you could reread this and say that the new regulations
on embryos for stem cells, which require contemporaneous consent,
as I believe all research should, only apply to stem cell research
and that this document gives you the right to use these embryos
for research for everything else.
For me that would be a misreading of this document. That's not
right? Okay, good. I'm glad I misunderstood that.
All right. But the other point is somebody has to read and interpret
these, and I could see how someone could read and interpret it that
way and say if someone said to them, "Well, you're violating
the regulations," they'd say, "No, you have a separate
regulation for that. This one is for this."
And if you read them together, as lawyers do all the time, you
could interpret it that way.
Okay. So the first question, as to the activities is a very important
question, is if you wanted to regulate, do you want to regulate
human experimentation and research or do you want to regulate ART,
assisted reproductive technologies?
My own bias, and it may mean nothing to you, is that we should
have a federal regulatory scheme for cutting edge research. That
should include artificial hearts, xenografts, embryo research, research
of the kind that local IRBs -- it is simply beyond their competence,
not that they don't try hard, and recently we have added to that
smallpox vaccine on children, which went to the federal government
anyway, and we weren't able to come up with any agreement except
not to do it.
But big time, risky, new types of human experimentations seem
to me to require a type of regulation that we don't have, and some
of the things that are done in ART, especially around embryos, cloning,
stem cells, would fall into that rubric as well.
So if you wanted to do that, that would be one kind of a regulatory
scheme. There would be no problems with federal authority to do
that, and it would fall into the same pattern of the proposals by
NBAC to cover all human research, not just federally funded research,
but private research as well.
The second type of research -- so that was one way -- the second
way to go is to regulate ART. That's much, much harder, but possible
because if you do that, you have to break it out in terms of federal
regulation and state regulation.
The issues that I'm actually most concerned about: who's the mother?
Who's the father? How do we insure the welfare of the children?
How do we make sure the child has access to their record, et cetera,
to their genetic information?
Those actually turned to all be issues, family law issues which
would be the province of the state. So to do that we'd have to go
-- we could still write a model situation, but we have to go state
by state, and that is not going to change. The Supreme Court is
not going to change that, nor do I think should they. Family law
issues rightly belong at the state level.
So you couldn't do that on a federal level. The federal level,
on the other hand, you could regulate the commercial aspects of
assisted reproductive technology, not just the, frankly, commercial
aspects like advertising and pricing, outlaw the purchase and sale
of gametes, if you wanted to do that, which I do; outlaw the purchase
and sale of embryos obviously.
But I think you can also regulate some of the practice, a lot
of the practice, the record keeping requirements, the screening
requirements, contract requirements, informed consent requirements,
and counseling requirements, and you could have uniform rules for
everyone, that unlike the ethical rules could be enforced. You could
set up a licensing scheme. You don't have to, but you could follow
the British model and license ART clinics.
I actually didn't realize there were 25 that weren't even members
of ASRM. It should be unacceptable. I mean, they should all be operated
under the same set of rules, it seems to me, that we should have
national standards for this, and you know, that would be something
that a separate agency could do.
Now, historically in other countries that have done this, I know
you heard from Patricia Baird. You've heard from the regulators
in England as well. It has taken a big time federal national commission
to study this issue for years to come up with recommendations which
are then adopted by the parliament or congress or whatever their
legislative group is.
It would take the same in the United States. I don't think you
could just go to Congress.
Could this group do it? If that's what you wanted to do, I think
it's possible. You could, but you probably couldn't do anything
else. I mean, it's a giant undertaking. It would require input from
many, many people. Lots of input from ASRM, as well.
I'll leave it to you whether you want to pursue that or not, but
there are models out there.
The final model and one that I actually think might satisfy both
sides, both sides being the public and the profession, is an UNOS
model, United Network for Organ Sharing model, which was followed
for like almost 20 years in this country. Can we regulate organ
transplantation? Isn't that something that we should let private
physicians and people do?
And of course, the reason we decided we needed some public input
from that is because organs came to be seen as, a very weird word,
a natural resource according to our presidential organ transplant
task force back in 1986.
And the idea, of course, is that we get organs from everyone,
and it seems unfair that everyone shouldn't be, therefore, eligible
for organs, and it also does seem -- maybe that's obviously why
we do have essentially a system of national health insurance for
livers, hearts, and kidney transplants and for nothing else in this
country.
But it also seemed that we needed a public transparent method
to see who got those organs because it was life or death decisions.
There was a shortage. There continues to be a shortage, and the
public trust was absolutely essential for this to go forward.
On the other hand, people are suspicious and rightfully so. Too
intrusive government regulation in the doctor-patient relationship.
So we wound up with the federal government, Congress, and then
regulations under HHS setting the standards for organ transplantation
and then having a private group contract it out, the United Network
for Organ Sharing, to implement those regulations.
And we can argue about how well that works overall I've been a
critic of that as well. Overall it works quite well. I think it
does work quite well, and that's a possible model for you to consider
as well.
So with that kind of personal critique of self-regulation, self-personal
experiences with ASRM and some suggestions of where you could look
for different regulatory models, let me open for questions and comments.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you very much for a very
responsive and direct and very interesting presentation.
I am somewhat at a loss as to whether we should first have some
comments directed to Professor Annas and whether the people who
are in queue would yield at least for a few minutes to get some
clarification, but I have you.
I have Robby George, Alfonso Gomez-Lobo, Frank Fukuyama, Elizabeth
and Bill Hurlbut.
You're taken care of already.
DR. GÓMEZ-LOBO: I yield.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Is there someone who would like
immediately to respond to -- Rebecca Dresser and Michael.
PROF. DRESSER: George, I just wondered if you
would give us your thoughts on the problem of getting both the state
legislatures and Congress to act in this area that is fraught with
controversy.
MR. ANNAS: Well, as I say, I don't think it's
impossible. It's more likely to get action on the federal level
probably than on the state level right now, but it's very, very
difficult. I mean that would require like you'd have -- this group,
for example, would have to say, "This is our highest priority."
That might not do it even, but if you didn't do that, definitely
nothing would happen.
On the state level we've had a remarkable report, which I commend
to you. You've probably seen it, the report of the New York State
Task Force on Assisted Reproductive Technologies. They recommended
80 different changes in their law.
To the best of my knowledge, none of them have actually taken
place yet. So that gives you some idea of how difficult it is to
pass legislation even with state group whose charge was to recommend
legislation coming up with an exceptionally well articulated program
with good reasons.
So this is a very, very difficult thing.
The second thing that happens, and I don't have to tell this group
that, is that this becomes very quickly entwined with abortion politics,
and you're going to have a lot of people who obviously don't care
about this issue, but who for them, you know, physicians and assisted
reproduction is not an issue at all will be against any regulation
of anything having anything to do with pregnancy and childbirth
because they're afraid once you regulate that then you're going
to start, you know, cutting back on abortion rights.
And I actually have a lot of sympathy for that view, and I certainly
understand it. But it just makes a life of a regulator much harder.
so there's those two political realities.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Michael Sandel.
PROF. SANDEL: I found your critique of the existing
arrangements very persuasive and thorough. My question is what would
be wrong in your view with our adopting the British system?
MR. ANNAS: Yeah, I mean, I don't think actually
-- I'm quite fond of the British system. I don't see anything wrong
with adopting it. We're not Britain obviously, but -- and I recommended
that. I commended that before, and I think that we could go that
route, you know, but then you put an awful lot of authority in one
group, and no one will support that until they have a pretty good
idea who's going to be appointed to run that organization and how
the members are going to be chosen and are they really going to
have, you know, a say.
I mean that's really the critical thing in England. I mean, they
have a different system. Obviously they have a national health service
and everything is funded and they don't have the problems. Dr. Carson
rightly pointed out that if you want to do all of these wonderful
things, you have to pay for them, including, you know, registries
of children.
And so one of the questions, having done that, even though it
was one of the few things left out of the Clinton plan for national
health insurance, could you set up a system to regulate this and
fund the procedures and not fund everything else?
So I don't think we can just have the British system just, you
know, transplanted here without understanding the whole British
system, but it's a good model to look at, absolutely.
CHAIRMAN KASS: On the questions of -- let me
just jump in with this business about your, I think, very proper
concern for the well-being of children, and several of us were talking
previously. To the extent to which one looks really at infertility
as a frustration of procreative desire and support of reproductive
liberty, the child tends to be sort of forgotten or at least left
to the side.
Could you comment on how well you think the current practices
of SART actually do safeguard the interests of the child to be one?
And, two, would the implications of some of your comments earlier
suppose that, in fact, pediatricians are those whose primary interest
is to care for the children really ought to be somehow central to
the ethics committee and other practice review committees of the
society; that there should be some kind of greater collaboration
here if professional self-regulation is, in fact, to address the
interests of all concerned, children most especially?
MR. ANNAS: Children, I think, are primarily considered
the province of the parents to take care of, you know, in this setting,
and of course, I understand that because that's what infertility
treatment is for. It's to try to help parents who can't otherwise
have children have the children.
All right. And the challenge is how do you get children more focused
and their interests more involved here, and you know, that is a
challenge. I mean, obviously the pediatricians take them right after
they're born and they're no longer in the care of these specialists,
and they may have other obstetricians even. They may not even be
delivered by the infertility specialist.
So if you wanted to have a physician model of all this, you'd
have to have a joint ethics committee, if you will, with the American
Academy of Pediatrics, ACOG, the American College of Obstetrics
and Gynecology, and in fact, those two groups do have a liaison
and do meet together, and actually there is some overlap historically
with the ethics committee of ASRM and ACOG, and since many members
of ASRM, not all, but lots, are obstetricians as well.
That's the kind of mix you have to get, but you have to get more
pediatricians involved. I think obstetricians have been involved.
And the interesting question, actually there are -- you know,
my colleague, Michael Grodin who was the liaison member of those
two committees for six years reminded me before I came here that
one of the things they wrote was a position on surrogate motherhood
back in 1994, and they wrote it together, and they wrote it based
on the best interests of the child, and his point was that the ultimate
statement was very similar to the ASRM statement. There really wasn't
any difference, even though they didn't come at it -- they didn't
mention the child, but they didn't come at it from the best interests
of the child. They came at it: does this make sense for a couple
who is trying to have a baby?
Nonetheless, the bottom line from the two was lots of caution
and here's what we do, and it wasn't different. The people coming
at it just from the interests of the child did not say we should
ban it, but both groups came out at the same.
So you may not come out differently on a lot of these things,
but you will have other considerations in the mix when you do it.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you.
Elizabeth, please.
Oh, I'm sorry. Then unless there are other immediate respondents,
let's declare both presentations open for discussion and, indeed,
discussion of the issue as well as the presentations, and I have
Robby, George, and then Alfonso.
I've got starting with Robby, and then Frank and Elizabeth and
Bill and so on.
Please, Robby.
PROF. GEORGE: Thank you, Leon.
I do have two questions that I'd like to bring Professor Annas
and Dr. Carson into conversation on, and, Rebecca, I'd be very pleased
if you could chime in on both of these as well.
The first one has to do with the general problem of self-regulation.
My own impression is that there's a problem of self-regulation which
I do not oppose with any enterprise, and with everybody who has
a vested interest in an enterprise, and that is that the enterprise
and those with an interest in it have a stake in the reputation
and good name of the enterprise and protecting that against embarrassments.
Now, the standard answer to that, whether we're talking about
medicine or any other field, think of the police, think of religious
institutions, is that, well, look. The long-term interest of the
enterprise really is served by good self-regulation and by not covering
things up because it all comes out in the end anyway, and it's worse
in the long run for everybody concerned even looking at it from
a selfish point of view if we get it out.
But, again, looking at police and religious institutions as examples,
one finds that, well, often the view taken by those with a vested
interest is a relatively short-term view. It's getting through the
problem now. It's avoiding damage to the reputation now and putting
things off and the long run will just have to take care of itself,
and of course, then in the long run, as was said, we're all dead.
So the standard answer doesn't always work so well. Now, what
some other institutions, including those I just mentioned, have
tried to do about that problem unfortunately too often after significant
embarrassments is bring in some sort of external reviewing to the
process of self-regulation.
So we're not now talking about government regulation as an alternative
to self-regulation, and there may of course also be government regulation
going on, but rather involving in the self-regulation outsiders
to the enterprise who have an interest in at least some level of
expertise, but who may not be entirely tied in with it and may,
therefore, have some objectivity and distance.
Think of police review boards, for example. So I'm wondering whether
-- this is my first question -- I'm wondering whether this is already
a feature of the self-regulation of this enterprise or industry,
and if not, whether there are particular reasons why it cannot be
here or cannot be done to a larger extent, a greater extent than
it is now.
So that's my first one.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Dr. Carson, would you want to
respond?
DR. CARSON: Yes.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Push your mic.
DR. CARSON: Thanks.
We do have exactly what you suggest. Our validation teams consist
of members as well as non-members. The validation committee, oversight
committee, as well as the site team visits have members of the CDC
on it as well.
MR. ANNAS: Yeah, I may be reiterating your question
a little differently, but I think it would be good to consider --
I never suggested this -- having some consumer groups do some suggestions
as well.
Years ago I was on the board of directors of Resolve, for example,
which is a support group for infertile couples, and their concerns
are different. A lot of them are costs and access and data, but
their concerns may be different than a profession.
And another group, which I have a number of groups, these support
groups for multiple births, they're obviously mostly all happy with
their children, but they do think a lot more can be done and should
be done both to tell people about the possibilities of having triplets
and quadruplets as well as try to figure out ways that that number
can be reduced.
I mean, the number is going down. Down to four percent is great,
but I think we'd all like to see it down to close to zero.
PROF. GEORGE: You know, we've heard rumblings
on the council, and I've picked up things outside the meeting room
here in talking with people about the possibility that as the original
IVF babies are now entering their 20s, there are concerns that unanticipated
diseases or defects are emerging so that the problem goes beyond
simply the multiple birth problem, but perhaps some of the fears
that people originally had about IVF are being born out.
If that were true, I take it that it could be a significant embarrassment
to this industry and perhaps damage it in the public eye, and it
looks to me like that's a particular area where the industry itself
probably would be better off if there were some sort of external
report on that investigation and report on that in the end rather
than the industry itself.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Dr. Carson.
DR. CARSON: Well, let me just point out that
ASRM does -- we have active collaboration with both the AIA, American
Infertility Association, and RESOLVE, and have a long-term collaboration
with RESOLVE. We have members at our meeting, board meetings, and
so we have considerable consumer, if you will, and what I like to
say, patient input into our policies and guidelines.
In addition, we work with not only the CDC, as I mentioned, but
also the FDA, and the FDA now has worked with it, has undertaken
upon itself to look at all research procedures with human tissues,
including gametes and embryos, and we are working in collaboration
with the FDA to help them with some of their guidelines and have
their input.
In terms of public disclosure, we actually don't feel that self-regulation
is embarrassing, and I think it's because our attitude towards this
is not punitive, which is not to say when this all initially started
that we weren't very paranoid about what was happening and government
regulation.
But I think that what has happened is we're very proud of the
product that we have and what has happened, but I think our attitude
is not one of making people public spectacles of their mistakes,
but rather of correcting it, teaming them with a successful program
that has the correct procedure, and then monitoring their outcome
and making sure that they did, indeed, correct that procedure.
In terms of long-term outcome, of course, it's something that
we worry about. It's something we should worry about with everything
in medicine. We can't predict what's going to happen with any medical
procedure 20 years from now, and that includes any drug you take
or any surgery that you have, and IVF is certainly one of them.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Alfonso Gomez-Lobo and then Frank.
DR. GÓMEZ-LOBO: I had yielded, but I take
it back. I had yielded because Dr. Carson was kind enough to answer
one of my questions, but I think it's of general interest to do
with the appointment of the ethics committee, which of course that
would translate if there is, say, something like federal regulation
into a similar problem.
And let me repeat the question. How is the ethics committee appointed?
The reason to us is, of course, because the impact of the decisions
of the ethics committee seem to me to be enormous.
In the report that I read, the committee made -- the report on
donating spare embryos for embryonic stem cell research -- the committee
took a position in a major dispute concerning the question of respect
or, as it's called in the report, special respect for the human
embryo.
DR. CARSON: Let me just give you a little bit
of history of our ethics committee. the ethics committee was really
started in 1985-ish, between 19 -- I'm not exactly sure -- 1983
to 1985, by Dr. Howard Jones, and initially it was really just started
as an almost discussion group with any real charge.
And Dr. Jones felt that we should be talking about IVF and talking
about the ethical issues and bringing them to this society, and
you've heard Dr. Annas' early experience with the ethics committee.
Even the first formal committee with Dr. Ryan in charge didn't quite
have the charge of an ethics committee that one would expect.
And I'm glad to see that we've, perhaps because of your advice,
we've matured into a committee that is now on the right track with
looking at the safety, efficacy, and patient confidentiality and
privacy of these procedures.
Our committee appointments are actually appointed by the president
of our society, but they are upon the recommendation and curriculum
vitae review of the chairman of the committee, and the president
is submitted recommendations and CVs for the various interest groups.
We have incorporated a member of our affiliate societies on the
ethics committee, but now we are going to actually mandate probably
that a member of the executive committee of each affiliate society
be on the group because we feel that this will promulgate more of
the policy into our different subgroups.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Frank Fukuyama.
DR. FUKUYAMA: Well, in listening to these two
very interesting and helpful presentations, it struck me that the
issue here is actually a lot simpler than a lot of the other issues
we've been discussing on this council, which is that here it's not
a question of trying to insert complex ethical concerns which may
not be shared across the whole society, you know, into some realm
of medicine, but it's fairly straightforward, you know, kind of
safety issue of the sort that we're quite familiar with from drug
regulation.
And I think what stimulated this was a couple of earlier bits
of testimony we heard on the council about ICSI in particular and
the fact that the clinical practice in that area and possibly some
others had actually gotten way out ahead of the underlying, you
know, biology and scientific research in embryology and developmental
biology and so forth.
And so there could actually be some fairly straightforward, you
know, simple safety issues involved here.
And so then if that's the problem, then it falls in this category
of asymmetric information which is very familiar, which is the reason
the FDA, you know, regulates drugs, and I guess the question I would
put is if you think that the FDA, you know, legitimately regulates
drug safety, you know, as a federal government agency, why is this
any different? I mean, why would you argue that you shouldn't apply
the same model?
I mean, forget about the practicalities of whether you can do
it or not, but is there any reason in principle why you should prefer
self-regulation in this case?
You know, one answer actually is that, well, the FDA shouldn't
be in the business of doing this. We should rely on tort law or
we should rely on the, you know, self-interest of drug companies
not to poison people and to, you know, maintain their reputations.
I mean, a lot of the same arguments that you make about, you know,
the clinics that are in your organization could apply to the drug
industry as well, and yet we don't accept that. We say that there's
a very severe asymmetric information problem, and therefore, you
need, you know, all of these federal incentives to get that information
out to consumers about safety and so forth.
So that's the question I would put to either of you.
DR. CARSON: Well, first, although we do work
with the FDA, we still feel that self-regulation as we're doing
is more innovative in terms of the problems and also much quicker.
For example, we also feel it might be more flexible.
For example, let's look at, as an example, the U.K. model. You
cannot transfer more than three embryos in the United Kingdom. It's
a law. It's regulated and paid for; can't happen.
Well, I think in the United States we regard the embryo as an
important tissue, potentially human, but not, as I've said, with
the rights of human. But that doesn't mean that we don't protect
and consider that embryo important.
And there are some individuals who for personal reasons do not
want their embryos cryopreserved and do not want to discard their
embryos, and if they have a fourth or fifth embryo, especially if
that embryo doesn't look very good and we know that it probably
won't result in a high order multiple, that we would transfer that
embryo, and we can written in the document exceed the guidelines
for the reason and say we're putting back three healthy embryos
and one embryo does not look bad because the patient did not want
to discard it.
And I think that's something that self-regulation can be flexible
enough to have, whereas federal regulation, such as the U.K. guidelines,
cannot.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Please.
DR. FUKUYAMA: Just a follow-up question. That's
always true of self-regulation. It's always quicker, more flexible,
more adaptive, and so forth.
That being said, would you be in favor of ending FDA regulation
of pharmaceuticals because, you know, FDA regulation slows down
drug approvals, very inflexible? I mean, would you move to a model
for drugs, a similar model for drugs?
DR. CARSON: I would move that we can improve
it. I wouldn't say -- should I say that the pharmaceutical companies
should self-regulate? I don't think so. But I think we can improve
the FDA policy.
DR. FUKUYAMA: Why are you different from them?
Why is your group self-interest basically different from the group
self-interest of the pharmaceutical industry in being able to effectively
self-regulate?
DR. CARSON: I think because we are involved with
a very intimate practice of medicine rather than an industry. I
think it's a profession that takes care of people whose outcome
is not financial primarily, but pregnancy, children, healthy families
is a very important outcome variable to us and probably our primary
outcome variable, and I think that makes us different.
MR. ANNAS: And I'd add to that, you know, the
FDA regulates things, as you know. They regulate drugs and they
regulate the drug industry, and actually Congress has said they
can't regulate the practice of medicine, but I think they could
regulate the practice of medicine.
I don't think they can regulate procedures. I really think that's
a whole different thing, and one reason why, for example, surgery
is not regulated in this country except by the tort system, and
surgeons can do whatever they want.
It's not because we think that they're not dangerous. It's because
we have no idea how to regulate surgeons, and added to the surgery
aspects is this intimacy, family building, privacy, and I just think
not only doesn't FDA have the jurisdiction and would never be given
the jurisdiction. I think it would be inappropriate to have FDA
regulate medical procedures in the doctor-patient relationship.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I have Bill Hurlbut and then Elizabeth.
PROF. BLACKBURN: I had a question about the UNOS
model, the moral sharing model. One of the things that is, of course,
great pressure on the system is the shortage of supply compared
with the medical needs, and first a factual question for Dr. Carson.
I don't know whether there's considered a shortage of donated
ova. I just don't know what pressure there is in that.
And then secondly for Dr. Annas, how does that then impact? Are
the situations very comparable or how would that change or adjust
the kind of model you would use in this situation?
DR. CARSON: There are -- I'm not sure about the
word "shortage," but there are certainly much donor recipients,
and there are waiting lists for ovum donors.
PROF. BLACKBURN: Thank you.
Yeah, I wasn't even aware if that was the case.
MR. ANNAS: Yeah, I mean, I apply, as I think
I intimated, the UNOS model, federal model, of no payment in the
purchase and sale of gametes for this.
Would that result in a shortage? I mean, they're not like organs.
To get a vital organ, someone has to die in a very horrible way
usually. That leaves their organs intact.
We're actually -- I think this is still true -- the only country
in the world that has a market in ova and embryos. So other countries
have figured out a way to get around the shortage problem, and we
could, too.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Bill Hurlbut.
DR. HURLBUT: I appreciate the difficulty of regulating
a complex and rapidly changing field and also acknowledge the good
intentions of the vast majority of medical people involved, and
I'm a physician myself and feel for the goals of this enterprise.
But I'm also troubled and actually have been every since the beginning
of IVF and more so with ICSI by what I perceive, as I said earlier,
to be the lack of foundational safety studies on this, and then
by some of the ongoing practices.
And I mean, if we admit that less regulation is better and more
flexible response is better, still this seems to me a very special
realm of human existence, and take, for example, ICSI. Your statistics
show I think it was 41 percent of births or cycles involved ICSI
now. It was something pretty dramatic. Yeah, it was very high. I'll
get it out.
But my first question is: do you think ICSI is being overused?
And here without accusing anybody of anything, there would be a
temptation to, for the sake of your institutional statistics, to
have a higher incidence of fertilization, which would be easier
to do with ICSI, right?
What do you think?
DR. CARSON: Well, again, it comes on indication.
Now, in this report I'll tell you that our institution has the highest
percentage of male factor infertility in the country. So you're
talking to the medical director of the program with that high incidence,
but that's because we work with a urologist who is probably one
of the country's leading urologists in male factor infertility,
and most of our patients don't -- a third of our ICSI patients don't
have any sperm in their ejaculate. He gets the sperm from the testes.
We very frequently -- the average sperm count in the fertile man
is around 50 to 60 million per cc, and very few of our patients
have more than one million sperm total ejaculate. So they truly
cannot have it.
Now, those are truly indicated ICSI procedures. Another indication
for ICSI is a poor fertilization in a prior IVF cycle, but there
are complications, and you can actually cause the egg itself to
divide, and if you do this in an unindicated patient, you may actually
decrease your pregnancy rate.
So I don't think that ICSI is one procedure that is overused because
overusing it may actually retard your outcome.
DR. HURLBUT: Well, what is the percentage of
ICSI in cycles now? Do you know this?
DR. CARSON: I don't have that number off the
top.
DR. HURLBUT: I had it somewhere, and I'm sorry
I can't find it, but it was surprisingly high to me, and if you
consider the male infertility is in the 30 to 40 percent range,
not all male infertility requires ICSI.
I mean it just sort of seemed worrisome to me, and the reason
I bring it up is because ICSI has been associated with aneuploidy
in normal primates. You said earlier that the difference between
the outcomes may be due to the patient population that you're dealing
with, and yet there are now studies emerging. Richard Schultz is
doing studies of this nature that seem to indicate that IVF does
carry and ICSI also carries some risks that are not because of the
patient population, if you call mice or rats a patient population.
You see what I'm getting at here. I just -- you apparently feel
like these may be problems, but they're not big enough to justify
larger federal regulation. Is that what I --
DR. CARSON: Well, I think that -- first of all,
although male factor infertility does not always require ICSI, by
the time treatment gets to IVF, it almost always does because treatments
of male factor infertility per se is not with IVF mixing sperm and
eggs.
A woman can mix sperm and eggs in her own body. So by the time
that couple gets to IVF, almost all major factor infertility does
require ICSI.
Go ahead.
DR. HURLBUT: Well, here's another question. If
IVF does carry risks associated with it just, say, because of the
procedure or because the patient population is more vulnerable to
congenital -- producing offspring with congenital abnormalities,
is there a point at which one would say that the procedure is unjustifiable?
I mean, in many dimensions of medicine we wouldn't allow a drug
to be used, for example, if it carried a certain risk, and there
the patient stands to benefit. Here the issue is, you know, there's
a whole other patient.
One of my colleagues doing this work was asked a question, and
he said, "I don't think of myself as an embryo pediatrician,"
but nonetheless we have to consider what is being produced here.
How much risk do you feel is acceptable? And do you feel that
that risk is being properly assessed by the current method or should
that be a decision for the whole society?
I mean these are very urgent issues, and I understand. In my own
experience in clinical medicine, I'd say that people who want to
have children and can't are among the most suffering patients I've
ever seen, and yet there is a baby coming out of this, and that
makes this a worrisome terrain for me.
DR. CARSON: Well, I appreciate your concern,
and I think you've crystallized the concern of our society and our
ethics committee. The problem is that we don't have a good model
because those men I described can't have a baby with that. There
is no baby without ICSI. If they don't have sperm in the ejaculate,
there's just no way to.
Well, now then you can say: should they have a baby? And, again,
that's an important ethical question that I think, again, our ethics
committee and our practice committee does wrestle with.
Now, if you come to the conclusion that the technology is available
to help them have a child and if you come to the conclusion that
it is acceptable, then you have to understand that that technology
comes with costs, and one of the costs is that there is an increased
risk without an animal model of a subsequent progeny, and whether
or not that increased risk should be the same for every individual
I don't know.
Should we set a limit that we will not have this with -- I've
showed you that the increased risk is .8 percent of sex chromosomal
anomalies above live born fertile controls. Now, of course, again,
we don't know what it would be if somehow some way these patients
were able to have babies, and I don't know how we set that risk.
I don't know whether it should be the same for every single individual
and whether that's for us to decide and mandate. But we are concerned
that we do have follow-up. We try our best to get these outcomes,
and our committee do wrestle with the very difficult decisions that
you've outlined.
MR. ANNAS: May I follow that one second?
CHAIRMAN KASS: Please.
MR. ANNAS: I've probably never been able to articulate
this well, but for some ICSI patients at least, we know at least
for the Y chromosomes deletions that all of their male offspring
are going to be infertile, and the question that has always fascinated
me, and I don't know if I have an answer for it necessarily, is
can an infertility expert who sees infertility as a major disease
and devoted their life to it produce infertile children? Is that
a problem or not?
DR. CARSON: Of course it's a problem. It's something
that again, we do discuss in committees, we do discuss with our
patients, and we require that all of those patients go through genetic
counseling if they have a Y chromosomal deletion.
We also offer preimplantation genetic diagnosis so that those
individuals can have females and promulgate that Y deletion.
MR. ANNAS: I guess that's the question. Should
you require that?
I know you say the informed consent model. It's a tough question.
I don't have an answer to it either.
DR. CARSON: That's a tough one.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I was myself next in the queue.
I would like to go back to something that was implicit in Gil
Meilaender's question previously, and it's also triggered by the
way Frank, I think, rather modestly put the kinds of concerns that
are around the table.
Safety, efficacy, and privacy are goods all of them, but they
don't exhaust the goods that are of concern to us in this counsel
and certainly don't exhaust, it seems to me, the goods that are
of concern to us in the area of assisted reproduction or of reproduction
and, therefore, of assisted reproduction, which is to say that one
is concerned not just that children be healthy, although health
is a good, but it's not the only good.
And I think that we've all gotten so used to the existence of
this practice and welcome its blessings in the relief of infertility
that it's no longer perhaps so much a part of our consciousness;
that this step, beneficial though it is, represents, as you yourself
said, a kind of unnatural development in human procreation, one
which leads to lots of others.
I mean, there would be no question about embryo research were
there not to begin with the extra embryos available. There would
be no question of preimplantation genetic diagnosis to screen the
embryos were one not already engaged in the practice of having multiple
embryos here from which one could then choose.
And it does seem to me that as the society looks without prejudice
now, but to look and ask what's going on here, I think the society
as a whole would see not just individual infertile couples with
the desire to have a child that this technology can satisfy, but
the society would see that we've embarked upon a new way of bringing
children into the world, a new way of parents prospectively exercising
some kind of quality control over their children, not necessarily
through designer babies, but even through just the simple question
of selection, of which the selection of sex of offspring for nonmedical
reasons is already upon us, and if, as Francis Collins suggested
in his presentation, the prospects of screening embryos for not
just diseases but also for traits at least in some cases he forecast
within ten years.
And it seem to me the society might well in thinking about this
say, "Look. Well and good safety, efficacy, and privacy, but
we don't want as a society to encourage sex selection. The use of
sex as a way of preventing sex linked diseases is only incidentally
sex selection. If you could identify those diseases in some other
way and you could identify the male child who, in fact, was not
afflicted, you wouldn't abort or prevent the implantation of all
males."
So society seems to rightly say we don't want to go down this
route and we also don't want to go down the route of PGD for trait
selection, and yet I don't hear anything in the kind of principles
that are now of concern to the profession, safety, efficacy and
privacy, and after that freedom because you don't want to get in
the way of the private reproductive choices of any couple. They
are the ones who are sort of going to set the bar for what risks
they want to subject their child to, if their desire is powerful
enough or they're willing, in fact, to have infertile male children
ad infinitum, who is the society to say that their desire and freedom
should not rule?
So thinking now not so much from the perspective of the individual
couples or of the profession which exists primarily to serve them,
but thinking of the community that has a stake in how children are
born, what our relation to them is, what kind of control we exercise
over their origins. The question is can one be confident that these
are matters best left to self-regulation.
I mean, the Canadians have -- I'm not up to date as to whether
the bill has passed there or not. I know it was in the third reading
and there are amendments proposed. So I suspect it hasn't passed
-- but they laid down some fairly strict guidelines about what would
or would not be permitted and then left other sorts of things to
the question of professional regulation and discretion.
That's a long winded way of asking whether there aren't ethical
concerns that are not exhausted by the ones that are highlighted
by you that are concerns to the society as a whole, and if so, whether
the professional society would welcome the guidance of the community
as a whole on those matters, leaving you free with respect to the
things that are not thereby set out of bounds.
How are we supposed to think about those sorts of things?
DR. CARSON: Well, actually on my last slide that
was actually, I think, my first question to your committee.
I think that you've pointed out these are complex issues, and
I don't really know the answers to your questions, and we are concerned
about whether we really are asking all of the right questions. What
else are we doing?
For example, let me just share a personal vignette. I was absolutely
certain I was not going to give candy to my first child and he was
going to get carrots and celery and only healthy things to eat.
And then, you know, his grandmother gave him an M&M. Well,
that ended that, right?
And this is just to show that my experience as a parent changed
radically before and after I was a parent, and of course, most of
our couples are not parents, and we as physicians try to guide them
and help them make this decision that we have from the experience
of being parents, of being professionals, but there's a certain
point that you can lead horses to water, but you can't make them
drink, and the point of making them drink with regulation and with
mandates is set by each different country differently.
And I think personally that the self-regulation is a better model
for the instance that I described that allows us to be a little
bit more flexible. It allows us to incorporate the different diversity
and ethnic values to embryos that our different religious and ethnic
groups have in this country.
Without that flexibility and with mandated transfer of only three
embryos, we won't be able to respect all of those things. Should
they be respected? Should we have a mandate?
I don't know. At current we don't, and those are some of the issues
that perhaps we're not looking at enough, and again, we welcome
any suggestions that you have in terms of areas that we're not looking
at and ways we can accomplish that.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Okay. I just have a couple more
unless people -- thank you.
I have Mary Ann and Rebecca Dresser.
PROF. GLENDON: George, I have a question for
you. Thank you for your presentation and for identifying yourself
in the beginning as somebody who is pro regulation, and I'd like
to ask you a question about that.
Because it seems to me that in the background here, not just in
ART, but in a whole range of analogous issues, the question isn't
just self-regulation or no regulation. It's self-regulation plus
which kind of regulation.
And you a few minutes ago said "except for the tort system,"
and I wanted to come back to that and ask you whether when you discussed
the weaknesses of self-regulation you also had in mind the weaknesses
of the tort system, you as a lawyer had in mind the weaknesses of
the tort system as a method of regulation in the medical area.
Because it seems to me that that system might just be the worst
of all possible worlds, and I say that partly because my colleague
at Harvard Law School, Paul Weiler, did a study of medical malpractice
litigation, which showed, on the one hand, that most injuries from
medical malpractice remain uncompensated, but on the other hand,
the awards that are given in medical malpractice cases are often
on little evidence and grossly excessive.
MR. ANNAS: Well, certainly I don't agree with
everything your colleague found in his study, and Troy Brennan and
others have done other studies, but there are certainly problems
with the malpractice system. Nobody likes the system. It mostly
leaves most people uncompensated and only works well for quite public
injuries which have large payouts, and even then we can wonder whether
they're too large.
And it doesn't work at all, as far as we can tell, or very poorly
for deterrence, for quality assurance.
Everybody agrees with that more or less, but nobody agrees what
to do about that, and that's one of the debates we're having now
in this area, but I agree it's not a good system, but you can't
just throw it out. You have to replace it with something that's
better, and you need to know what your goals are in terms of compensation
and quality control and giving the public a form in which to vent
its frustrations.
But in terms of reproductive technologies in general, it works
even worse there. At least historically it has worked terrible there
because people wanted to keep their infertility a secret. That's
no longer the case, but historically that was the case.
So you have hardly any suits at all involving artificial insemination
by donor, and even to this day most of the lawsuits -- Dr. Carson
is exactly right -- involve what essentially are custody disputes,
you know, who's going to get the baby when it's all over.
You see hardly any lawsuits involving problems with the child.
Most of those are not going to be directed at the IVF clinic anyway.
They'll probably be directed at the obstetrician or at the hospital.
So if you want to regulate new uses of like ICSI, you can't do
it with tort, which is too blunt. I mean, maybe it will turn out
that there are problems and there will be a class action lawsuit
in 20 years or something, but it's not going to do any good for
current practice.
DR. HURLBUT: Let me just clarify the record on
this. I found the statistics.
MR. ANNAS: Okay, good.
DR. HURLBUT: It was slightly higher than I had
thought. The total of all the cycles done was 42.6 percent. So there
might be reason to think ICSI is being overused.
DR. CARSON: And malpractor infertility is about
40 percent of infertile couples.
DR. HURLBUT: Not all male factor requires ICSI.
So that could be said.
DR. CARSON: that's correct, but also some of
those couples are repeat cycles, are repeat cycles. So if a woman
doesn't get pregnant, she goes through another cycle, and that would
be another ICSI.
DR. HURLBUT: Okay, but do you think ICSI might
be being overused is really the question. No?
I mean, I'm asking you. I'm not --
DR. CARSON: I don't think so because I think
the overuse might cause a problem, and so the motivation to have
a higher success rate would not be achieved.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Before I call on Rebecca, George,
would you mind? I had meant really when I had put the question to
Dr. Carson also to address the question to you, my own question
about whether or not the criteria of safety, efficacy, privacy,
and in some way freedom of choice are sufficient in this area, given
what's actually at stake and whether you yourself think that one
could rely on professional regulation to perhaps set some of the
boundaries toward appropriate and less appropriate uses of this
technology, especially when you combine it with prospects of selection
and the like.
I mean, is this a matter to be left to the private choices of
the consumers or do you yourself favor or think it's reasonable
to develop some kind of --
MR. ANNAS: It sounds like a leading question
to me.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I don't know the answer. I don't
know what you would say.
MR. ANNAS: Well, that's okay.
Safety and efficacy are obviously things that we should take for
granted. That's what FDA does with drugs and devices and we shouldn't
expect physicians to offer procedures that aren't safe and effective.
The problem with this area has been that the federal government
never funded any research. So we're doing kind of research and practice
together. So safety and efficacy are reasonable goals, but you wouldn't
expect from any physician.
Privacy has some unique aspects in this particular area, but has
tended to mean let the couple decide whatever they want to do, and
that's fine as far as it goes as long as the interests of children
and society are factored in there.
And the question is: how do you get the interests of children,
which I have always thought should be first, but it's hard to put
them first; how do you get them accounted for?
But the British system you heard a presentation. In the British
system, there it's in their statute that the best interests of children
shall be the number one concern of their regulatory agency, and
that the interests of the nation shall take precedent, whatever
those are, shall take precedence over the interests of the couples,
a very interesting concept as well, you know. So see how they figure
that on what the interests of the nation are exactly. It's a good
question.
But there the regulatory agency is tasked to figure that out and
to have that reflected in their decisions.
And I certainly think that -- and I doubt SART disagrees -- that
we have to broaden the players and the discussion into how we set
these rules.
I mean, not to come back to my colleague John Robertson, but he
is the chairman of the ethics committee, and I was pretty flabbergasted
to read in the January 2003 issue of Nature and Genetics that he
believes as a personal matter, not speaking for the society, that
PGD is perfectly appropriate to use for deafness and it's perfectly
appropriate to use it to help a deaf couple have a deaf child, to
have a healthy child, but to have a deaf child.
That strikes me as something physicians cannot be involved with.
There's no way to say that that is a technology or that that is
a health child. Even if the deaf community considers it a healthy
child, the greater society does not and I don't think should promote
the technology for those type of researchers.
He also says he believes that and he says evidence indicates that
when new uses of PGD help parents to have healthy, wanted children,
society will accept them.
Well, we need society to say that, not to have some person with
a preformed view say that.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Thank you.
Rebecca Dresser, please.
PROF. DRESSER: On Mary Ann's point, one thing
I've heard about the tort system in this area is that if you're
looking at harm to a child, the difficulties in proving caution
are so high or so severe that lawyers won't take the case, and they
just don't get into the system.
PROF. GLENDON: Can I just?
PROF. DRESSER: Sure.
PROF. GLENDON: What I was thinking about really
is down the line the harm to the women that may appear later on
as a result of the massive hormone injections.
PROF. DRESSER: Yeah, that's a possibility.
The other point I wanted to make is I think this discussion brings
home something I keep harping on. This safety and efficacy is an
ethical judgment. I mean, it's balancing. Are the risks so great
that the benefits don't justify doing the procedure, or what are
the benefits? How valuable are they?
And here in this area, how much value you put on the opportunity
to have a biological child makes a huge difference. If you don't
think that's very valuable, then the ICSI risk is unjustified and
the ICSI is unsafe.
If you think that is incredibly valuable, then a 15 percent risk
in ICSI of certainly infertility, which, you know, people can have
a very good quality of life if they're infertile; so that risk would
not be so high, and you would say -- or too high -- and you would
say the procedure is justified.
So who gets to value risks and expected benefits is crucial in
this area, and you know, the FDA does it with drugs, with their
advisory committees which do often include patient representatives.
They have gotten a little bit more diverse in terms of the value
judgments.
In this committee, the ASRM ethics committee, the people on the
committee are balancing these things, and whether they're the appropriate
ones to be doing it is a good question, and obviously the infertility
patients are valuing these things, and they're putting an incredibly
high value on having a biological child.
So I think we should keep remembering that the safety and efficacy,
oh, well, that's something different than ethical. To me that --
CHAIRMAN KASS: No, I regard them as --
PROF. DRESSER: -- that's crucial.
CHAIRMAN KASS: I regard them as ethical concerns.
PROF. DRESSER: So if we could ever get the legislature
or Congress to take a stand on, you know, the value of the healthy
child in this context is paramount, and you know, we will accept
very few risks to the physical health of the child or the psychological
health. That would be, you know, in a democracy that would probably
be ideal, but it has been difficult to get our legislators to take
a stand on something like that.
CHAIRMAN KASS: Well, having the somewhat ill
deserved reputation I have of being an enemy of IVF is tied to a
paper written in 1971 in the New England Journal after the first
successful laboratory fertilization by Edwards, I guess seven years
before Louise Brown.
The question was whether this was unethical experimentation on
the unborn, question mark, and the sole concern was, in fact, George
Annas' concern to say that one shouldn't be simply guided by our
sympathy for the powerful desires of the parents. There is a third
party here for whom it's not yet clear that the prospective parents
who don't yet have the living child in front of them to care for
have the best interests of that child in mind until, as Dr. Carson
says, the child is there.
Look. Unless someone wants to add, we're late. We had originally
budgeted half an hour here for the council amongst itself to discuss
the fruits of this discussion. Our guests have been forthcoming
and we've not been shy, but I don't think we've cheated ourselves
out of this.
Let me simply say that we will build in our discussion of strengths
and possible weaknesses of professional self-regulation when the
staff brings to the council at our next meeting its preliminary
document for discussion on our review of the current situation of
regulation in this area, with special attention to the ethical issues,
including safety and efficacy.
Let me thank Dr. Carson and Professor Annas very much for your
presence, for your generosity, for your clear presentation, and
the wonderful way in which you responded to the questions. Thank
you very much.
If I could ask counsel members, briefly we have only one presentation,
one person to speak in the public session, and that is Richard Doerflinger
from the U.S. Conference of Catholic Bishops.
Thank you both very much.
(Applause.)
|