Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Happiness
The President's Council on Bioethics
Washington, D.C.
October 2003
www.bioethics.gov
Chapter Six
"Beyond Therapy": General Reflections
The four preceding chapters have examined how several prominent
and (generally) salutary human pursuits may be aided or altered
using a wide variety of biotechnologies that lend themselves to
purposes "beyond therapy." In each case, we have discussed the character
of the end, considered the novel means, and explored some possible
implications, ethical and social. In surveying the pertinent technologies,
we have taken a somewhat long-range view, looking at humanly significant
technical possibilities that may soon-or not so soon-be available
for general use, yet at the same time trying to separate fact from
science fiction. In offering ethical analysis, we have tried to
identify key issues pertinent to the case under discussion, asking
questions about both ends and means, and looking always for the
special significance of pursuing the old human ends by these new
technological means. In this concluding chapter, we step back from
the particular "case studies" to pull together some common threads
and to offer some generalizations and conclusions to which the overall
inquiry has led.
I. The Big Picture
The first generalization concerns the wide array of biotechnologies
that are, or may conceivably be, useful in pursuing goals beyond
therapy. Although not originally developed for such uses, the available
and possible techniques we have considered-techniques for screening
genes and testing embryos, choosing sex of children, modifying the
behavior of children, augmenting muscle size and strength, enhancing
athletic performance, slowing senescence, blunting painful memories,
and brightening mood-do indeed promise us new powers that can serve
age-old human desires. True, in some cases, the likelihood that
the new technologies will be successfully applied to those purposes
seems, at least for the foreseeable future, far-fetched: genetically
engineered "designer babies" are not in the offing. In other cases,
as with psychotropic drugs affecting memory, mood, and behavior,
some uses beyond therapy are already with us. In still other cases,
such as research aimed at retarding senescence, only time will tell
what sort of powers may become available for increasing the maximum
human lifespan, and by how much. Yet the array of biotechnologies
potentially useful in these ventures should not be underestimated,
especially when we consider how little we yet know about the human
body and mind and how much our knowledge and technique will surely
grow in the coming years. Once we acquire technical tools and the
potential for their use based on fuller knowledge, we will likely
be able to intervene much more knowingly, competently, and comprehensively.
Second, despite the heterogeneity of the techniques, the variety
of purposes they may serve, and the different issues raised by pursuing
these differing purposes by diverse means, we believe that all of
these matters deserve to be considered together, just as we have
done in this report. Notwithstanding the multiplicity of ends, means,
and consequences that we have considered, this report offers less
a list of many things to think about than a picture of one big
thing to think about: the dawning age of biotechnology and the
greatly augmented power it is providing us, not only for gaining
better health but also for improving our natural capacities and
pursuing our own happiness. The ambitious project for the mastery
of nature, the project first envisioned by Francis Bacon and René
Descartes in the early seventeenth century, is finally yielding
its promised abilities to relieve man's estate-and then some. Though
our society will, as a matter of public practice, be required to
deal with each of these techniques and possibilities as they arrive,
piecemeal and independently of one another, we should, as a matter
of public understanding, try to see what they might all add up to,
taken together. The Council's experience of considering these disparate
subjects under this one big idea-"beyond therapy, for the pursuit
of happiness"-and our discovery of overlapping ethical implications
would seem to vindicate the starting assumption that led us to undertake
this project in the first place: biotechnology beyond therapy
deserves to be examined not in fragments, but as a whole.
Yet, third, the "whole" that offers us the most revealing insights
into this subject is not itself technological. For the age of biotechnology
is not so much about technology itself as it is about human beings
empowered by biotechnology. Thus, to understand the human and
social meaning of the new age, we must begin not from our tools
and products but from where human beings begin, namely, with the
very human desires that we have here identified in order to give
shape to this report: desires for better children, superior performance,
younger and more beautiful bodies, abler minds, happier souls. Looking
at the big picture through this lens keeps one crucial fact always
in focus: how people exploit the relatively unlimited uses of biotechnical
power will be decisively determined by the perhaps still more unlimited
desires of human beings, especially-and this is a vital point-as
these desires themselves become transformed and inflated by the
new technological powers they are all the while acquiring. Our desires
to alter our consciousness or preserve our youthful strength, perhaps
but modest to begin with, could swell considerably if and when we
become more technically able to satisfy them. And as they grow,
what would have been last year's satisfaction will only fuel this
year's greater hunger for more.
Fourth, as the ubiquitous human desires are shaped and colored
not only reactively by the tools that might serve them but also
directly by surrounding cultural and social ideas and practices,
the "one big picture" will be colored by the (albeit changeable)
ruling opinions, mores, and institutions of the society in which
we live and into which the technologies are being introduced. For
example, the desire for performance-enhancing drugs will be affected
by the social climate regarding competition; the eagerness to gain
an edge for one's children will be affected by whether many other
parents are doing so; and the willingness to use or forego medication
for various sorts of psychic distress will be affected by the poverty
or richness of private life, and the degree to which strong family
or community support is (or is not) available for coping with that
distress directly. Moreover, in a free and pluralistic society,
we may expect a very diverse popular reaction to the invitation
of the new technologies, ranging from exuberant enthusiasm to outright
rejection, and the overall public response cannot be judged in advance.
Yet because the choices made by some can, in their consequences,
alter the shared life lived by all, it behooves all of us to consider
the meaning of these developments, whether we are privately tempted
by them or not. It is in part to contribute to a more thoughtful
public appraisal of these possibilities that we have undertaken
this report.
By beginning with the common human desires, we have sought to
place what may be new and strange into a context provided by what
is old and familiar. We recognize the temptation to add biotechnological
means to our "tool kits" for pursuing happiness and self-improvement,
and it is not difficult to appreciate, at least at first glance,
the attractiveness of the goods being contemplated. We want to give
our children the best start in life and every chance to succeed.
We want to perform at our best, and better than we did before. We
want to remain youthful and vigorous for as long as we can. We want
to face life optimistically and with proper self-regard. And since
we now avail ourselves of all sorts of means toward these ends,
we will certainly not want to neglect the added advantages that
biotechnologies may offer us, today and tomorrow.
At the same time, however, we have identified, in each of the
previous four chapters, several reasonable sources of concern, ethical
and social. And, in each case, we have called attention to some
of the possible hidden costs of success, achieved by employing these
means. The chapter on better children raised questions about the
meaning and limits of parental control and about the character and
rearing of children. The chapter on superior performance raised
questions about the meaning of excellence and the "humanity" of
human activity. The chapter on ageless bodies raised questions about
the significance of the "natural" life cycle and lifespan, and their
connection to the dynamic character of society and the prospects
for its invigorating renewal. And the chapter on happy souls raised
questions about the connections between experienced mood or self-esteem
and the deeds or experiences that ordinarily are their foundation,
as well as the connections between remembering truly and personal
identity. Looking again at these subjects, now seen as part of "one
big picture," we think it useful here to collect and organize the
various issues into a semi-complete account, so that the reader
may see in outline the most important and likely sources of concern.
Before proceeding, we wish to reiterate our intention in this
inquiry, so as to avoid misunderstanding. In offering our synopsis
of concerns, we are not making predictions; we are merely pointing
to possible hazards, hazards that become visible only when one looks
at "the big picture." More important, we are not condemning either
biotechnological power or the pursuit of happiness, excellence,
or self-perfection. Far from it. We eagerly embrace biotechnologies
as aids for preventing or correcting bodily or mental ills and for
restoring health and fitness. We even more eagerly embrace the pursuits
of happiness, excellence, and self-improvement, for ourselves, our
children, and our society. Desires for these goals are the source
of much that is good in human life. Yet, as has long been known,
these desires can be excessive. Worse, they can be badly educated
regarding the nature of their object, sometimes with tragic result:
we get what we ask for only to discover that it is very far from
what we really wanted. Finally, they can be pursued in harmful ways
and with improper means, often at the price of deforming the very
goals being sought. To guard against such outcomes, we need to be
alert in advance to the more likely risks and the more serious concerns.
We begin with those that are more obvious and familiar.
II. Familiar Sources of Concern
The first concerns commonly expressed regarding any uses of biotechnology
beyond therapy reflect, not surprisingly, the dominant values of
modern America: health and safety, fairness and equality, and freedom.
The following thumbnail sketches of the issues should suffice to
open the questions-though of course not to settle them.
A. Health: Issues of Safety and Bodily Harm
In our health-conscious culture, the first reason people worry
about any new biotechnical intervention, whatever its intended purpose,
is safety. This will surely be true regarding "elective" uses of
biotechnology that aim beyond therapy. Athletes who take steroids
to boost their strength may later suffer premature heart disease.
College students who snort Ritalin to increase their concentration
may become addicted. Melancholics taking mood-brighteners to change
their outlook may experience impotence or apathy. To generalize:
no biological agent used for purposes of self-perfection or self-satisfaction
is likely to be entirely safe. This is good medical common sense:
anything powerful enough to enhance system A is likely to be powerful
enough to harm system B (or even system A itself), the body being
a highly complex yet integrated whole in which one intervenes partially
only at one's peril. And it surely makes sense, ethically speaking,
that one should not risk basic health pursuing a condition of "better
than well."
Yet some of the interventions that might aim beyond therapy-for
example, genetic enhancement of muscle strength, retardation of
aging, or pharmacologic blunting of horrible memories or increasing
self-esteem-may, indirectly, lead also to improvements in general
health. More important, many good things in life are filled with
risks, and free people-even if properly informed about the magnitude
of those risks-may choose to run them if they care enough about
what they might gain thereby. If the interventions are shown to
be highly dangerous, many people will (later if not sooner)
avoid them, and the Food and Drug Administration or tort liability
will constrain many a legitimate would-be producer. But if, on the
other hand, the interventions work well and are indeed highly desired,
people may freely accept, in trade-off, even considerable risk of
later bodily harm for the sake of significant current benefits.
Besides, the bigger ethical issues in this area have little to do
with safety; the most basic questions concern not the hazards associated
with the techniques but the benefits and harms of using the perfected
powers, assuming that they may be safely used.
B. Unfairness
An obvious objection to the use of enhancement technologies, especially
by participants in competitive activities, is that they give those
who use them an unfair advantage: blood doping or steroids in athletes,
stimulants in students taking the SATs, and so on. This issue, briefly
discussed in Chapter Three, has been well aired by the International
Olympic Committee and the many other athletic organizations who
continue to try to formulate rules that can be enforced, even as
the athletes and their pharmacists continue to devise ways to violate
those rules and escape detection. Yet as we saw, the fairness question
can be turned on its head, and some people see in biotechnical intervention
a way to compensate for the "unfairness" of natural inequalities-say,
in size, strength, drive, or native talent. Still, even if everyone
had equal access to genetic improvement of muscle strength or mind-enhancing
drugs, or even if these gifts of technology would be used only to
rectify the inequalities produced by the unequal gifts of nature,
an additional disquiet would still perhaps remain: The disquiet
of using such new powers in the first place or at all, even were
they fairly distributed. Besides, as we have emphasized, not all
activities of life are competitive, and the uses of biotechnologies
for purposes beyond therapy are more worrisome on other grounds.i
C. Equality of Access A related question
concerns inequality of access to the benefits of biotechnology,
a matter of great interest to many Members of this Council, though
little discussed in the previous chapters. The issue of distributive
justice is more important than the issue of unfairness in competitive
activities, especially if there are systemic disparities between
those who will and those who won't have access to the powers of
biotechnical "improvement." Should these capabilities arrive, we
may face severe aggravations of existing "unfairnesses" in the "game
of life," especially if people who need certain agents to treat
serious illness cannot get them while other people can enjoy them
for less urgent or even dubious purposes. If, as is now often the
case with expensive medical care, only the wealthy and privileged
will be able to gain easy access to costly enhancing technologies,
we might expect to see an ever-widening gap between "the best and
the brightest" and the rest. The emergence of a biotechnologically
improved "aristocracy"-augmenting the already cognitively stratified
structure of American society-is indeed a worrisome possibility,
and there is nothing in our current way of doing business that works
against it. Indeed, unless something new intervenes, it would seem
to be a natural outcome of mixing these elements of American society:
our existing inequalities in wealth and status, the continued use
of free markets to develop and obtain the new technologies, and
our libertarian attitudes favoring unrestricted personal freedom
for all choices in private life.
Yet the situation regarding rich and poor is more complex, especially
if one considers actual benefits rather than equality or relative
well-being. The advent of new technologies often brings great benefits
to the less well off, if not at first, then after they come to be
mass-produced and mass-marketed and the prices come down. (Consider,
over the past half-century, the spread in the United States of refrigerators
and radios, automobiles and washing machines, televisions and VCRs,
cell phones and personal computers, and, in the domain of medicine,
antibiotics, vaccines, and many expensive diagnostic and therapeutic
procedures.) To be sure, the gap between the richest and the poorest
may increase, but in absolute terms the poor may benefit more, when
compared not to the rich but to where they were before. By many
measures, the average American today enjoys a healthier, longer,
safer, and more commodious life than did many a duke or prince but
a few centuries back.
Nevertheless, worries about possible future bio-enhanced stratification
should not be ignored. And they become more poignant in the present,
to the extent that one regards spending money and energy on goals
beyond therapy as a misallocation of limited resources in a world
in which the basic health needs of millions go unaddressed. Yet
although the setting of priorities for research and development
is an important matter for public policy, it is not unique to the
domain of "beyond therapy." It cannot be addressed, much less solved,
in this area alone. Moreover, and yet again, the inequality of access
does not remove our uneasiness over the thing itself. It is, to
say the least, paradoxical, in discussions of the dehumanizing dangers
of, say, future eugenic selection of better children, that people
vigorously complain that the poor will be denied equal access to
the danger: "The food is contaminated, but why are my portions so
small?" Huxley's Brave New World runs on a deplorable and
impermeably rigid class system, but few people would want to live
in that world even if offered the chance to enjoy it as an alpha
(the privileged caste). Even an elite can be dehumanized, can dehumanize
itself. The questions about access and distributive justice are,
no doubt, socially important. Yet the more fundamental ethical questions
about taking biotechnology "beyond therapy" concern not equality
of access, but the goodness or badness of the things being offered
and the wisdom of pursuing our purposes by such means.
D. Liberty: Issues of Freedom and Coercion, Overt and
Subtle
A concern for threats to freedom comes to the fore whenever biotechnical
powers are exercised by some people upon other people. We encountered
it in our discussion of "better children" (the choice of a child's
sex or the drug-mediated alteration of his or her behavior; Chapter
Two), as well as in the coerced use of anabolic steroids by the
East German Olympic swimmers (Chapter Three). This problem will
of course be worse in tyrannical regimes. But there are always dangers
of despotism within families, as many parents already work their
wills on their children with insufficient regard to a child's independence
or long-term needs, jeopardizing even the "freedom to be a child."
To the extent that even partial control over genotype-say, to take
a relatively innocent example, musician parents selecting a child
with genes for perfect pitch-would add to existing social instruments
of parental control and its risks of despotic rule, this matter
will need to be attended to.ii
Leaving aside the special case of children, the risk of overt
coercion does not loom large in a free society. On the contrary,
many enthusiasts for using technology for personal enhancement are
libertarian in outlook; they see here mainly the enlargement of
human powers and possibilities and the multiplication of options
for private choice, both of which they see as steps to greater human
freedom. They look forward to growing opportunities for more people
to earn more, learn more, see more, and do more, and to choose-perhaps
several times in one lifetime-interesting new careers or avocations.
And they look with suspicion at critics who they fear might want
to limit their private freedom to develop and use new technologies
for personal advancement or, indeed, for any purpose whatsoever.
The coercion they fear comes not from advances in technology but
from the state, acting to deny them their right to pursue happiness
or self-improvement by the means they privately choose.
Yet no one can deny that people living in free societies, and
even their most empowered citizens, already experience more subtle
impingements on freedom and choice, operating, for example, through
peer pressure. What is freely permitted and widely used may, under
certain circumstances, become practically mandatory. If most children
are receiving memory enhancement or stimulant drugs, failure to
provide them for your child might be seen as a form of child neglect.
If all the defensive linemen are on steroids, you risk mayhem if
you go against them chemically pure. And, a point subtler still,
some critics complain that, as with cosmetic surgery, Botox, and
breast implants, many of the enhancement technologies of the future
will very likely be used in slavish adherence to certain socially
defined and merely fashionable notions of "excellence" or improvement,
very likely shallow and conformist. If these fears are realized,
such exercises of individual freedom, suitably multiplied, might
compromise the freedom to be an individual.iii
This special kind of reduction of freedom-let's call it the problem
of conformity or homogenization-is of more than individual concern.
In an era of mass culture, itself the by-product of previous advances
in communication, manufacture, and marketing techniques, the exercise
of uncoerced private choices may produce untoward consequences for
society as a whole. Trends in popular culture lead some critics
to worry that the self-selected nontherapeutic uses of the new biotechnical
powers, should they become widespread, will be put in the service
of the most common human desires, moving us toward still greater
homogenization of human society-perhaps raising the floor but also
lowering the ceiling of human possibility, and reducing the likelihood
of genuine freedom, individuality, and greatness. (This is an extension
of Tocqueville's concern about the leveling effects of democracy,
now possibly augmented by the technological power to make those
effects ingrained and perhaps irreversible.)
Indeed, such constriction of individual possibility could be the
most important society-wide concern, if we consider the aggregated
effects of the likely individual choices for biotechnical "self-improvement,"
each of which might be defended or at least not objected to on a
case-by-case basis (the problem of what the economists call "negative
externalities"). For example, it might be difficult to object to
a personal choice for a life-extending technology that would extend
the user's life by three healthy decades or a mood-brightened way
of life that would make the individual more cheerful and untroubled
by the world around him. Yet as we have suggested more than once,
the aggregated social effects of such choices, widely made, could
lead to a Tragedy of the Commons, where benefits gained by individuals
are outweighed by the harms that return to them from the social
costs of allowing everyone to share the goodies. And, as Huxley
strongly suggests in Brave New World, when biotechnical powers
are readily available to satisfy short-term desires or to produce
easy contentment, the character of human striving changes profoundly
and the desire for human excellence fades. Should this come to pass,
the best thing to be hoped for might be the preservation of pockets
of difference (as on the remote islands in Brave New World)
where the desire for high achievement has not been entirely submerged
or eroded.iv
III. Essential Sources of Concern
Our familiar worries about issues of safety, equality, and freedom,
albeit very important, do not exhaust the sources of reasonable
concern. When richly considered, they invite us to think about the
deeper purposes for the sake of which we want to live safely, justly,
and freely. And they enable us to recognize that even the safe,
equally available, non-coerced and non-faddish uses of biomedical
technologies to pursue happiness or self-improvement raise ethical
and social questions, questions more directly connected with the
essence of the activity itself: the use of technological means to
intervene into the human body and mind, not to ameliorate their
diseases but to change and improve their normal workings. Why, if
at all, are we bothered by the voluntary self-administration
of agents that would change our bodies or alter our minds? What
is disquieting about our attempts to improve upon human nature,
or even our own particular instance of it?
The subject being relatively novel, it is difficult to put this
worry into words. We are in an area where initial revulsions are
hard to translate into sound moral arguments. Many people are probably
repelled by the idea of drugs that erase memories or that change
personalities, or of interventions that enable seventy-year-olds
to bear children or play professional sports, or, to engage in some
wilder imaginings, of mechanical implants that would enable men
to nurse infants or computer-brain hookups that would enable us
to download the Oxford English Dictionary. But can our disquiet
at such prospects withstand rational, anthropological, or ethical
scrutiny? Taken one person at a time, with a properly prepared set
of conditions and qualifications, it will be hard to say what is
wrong with any biotechnical intervention that could improve our
performances, give us (more) ageless bodies, or make it possible
for us to have happier souls. Indeed, in many cases, we ought to
be thankful for or pleased with the improvements our biotechnical
ingenuity is making possible.
If there are essential reasons to be concerned about these activities
and where they may lead us, we sense that it may have something
to do with challenges to what is naturally human, what is humanly
dignified, or to attitudes that show proper respect for what is
naturally and dignifiedly human. As it happens, at least four such
considerations have already been treated in one place or another
in the previous chapters: appreciation of and respect for "the naturally
given," threatened by hubris; the dignity of human activity, threatened
by "unnatural" means; the preservation of identity, threatened by
efforts at self-transformation; and full human flourishing, threatened
by spurious or shallow substitutes.
A. Hubris or Humility: Respect for "the Given"
A common, man-on-the-street reaction to the prospects of biotechnological
engineering beyond therapy is the complaint of "man playing God."
If properly unpacked, this worry is in fact shared by people holding
various theological beliefs and by people holding none at all. Sometimes
the charge means the sheer prideful presumption of trying to alter
what God has ordained or nature has produced, or what should, for
whatever reason, not be fiddled with. Sometimes the charge means
not so much usurping God-like powers, but doing so in the absence
of God-like knowledge: the mere playing at being God, the hubris
of acting with insufficient wisdom.
Over the past few decades, environmentalists, forcefully making
the case for respecting Mother Nature, have urged upon us a "precautionary
principle" regarding all our interventions into the natural world.
Go slowly, they say, you can ruin everything. The point is certainly
well taken in the present context. The human body and mind, highly
complex and delicately balanced as a result of eons of gradual and
exacting evolution, are almost certainly at risk from any ill-considered
attempt at "improvement." There is not only the matter of unintended
consequences, a concern even with interventions aimed at therapy.
There is also the matter of uncertain goals and absent natural standards,
once one proceeds "beyond therapy." When a physician intervenes
therapeutically to correct some deficiency or deviation from a patient's
natural wholeness, he acts as a servant to the goal of health and
as an assistant to nature's own powers of self-healing, themselves
wondrous products of evolutionary selection. But when a bioengineer
intervenes for nontherapeutic ends, he stands not as nature's servant
but as her aspiring master, guided by nothing but his own will and
serving ends of his own devising. It is far from clear that our
delicately integrated natural bodily powers will take kindly to
such impositions, however desirable the sought-for change may seem
to the intervener. And there is the further question of the unqualified
goodness of the goals being sought, a matter to which we shall return.v
One revealing way to formulate the problem of hubris is what one
of our Council Members has called the temptation to "hyper-agency,"
a Promethean aspiration to remake nature, including human nature,
to serve our purposes and to satisfy our desires. This attitude
is to be faulted not only because it can lead to bad, unintended
consequences; more fundamentally, it also represents a false understanding
of, and an improper disposition toward, the naturally given world.
The root of the difficulty seems to be both cognitive and moral:
the failure properly to appreciate and respect the "giftedness"
of the world. Acknowledging the giftedness of life means recognizing
that our talents and powers are not wholly our own doing, nor even
fully ours, despite the efforts we expend to develop and to exercise
them. It also means recognizing that not everything in the world
is open to any use we may desire or devise. Such an appreciation
of the giftedness of life would constrain the Promethean project
and conduce to a much-needed humility. Although it is in part a
religious sensibility, its resonance reaches beyond religion.1
Human beings have long manifested both wondering appreciation
for nature's beauty and grandeur and reverent awe before nature's
sublime and mysterious power. From the elegance of an orchid to
the splendor of the Grand Canyon, from the magnificence of embryological
development to the miracle of sight or consciousness, the works
of nature can still inspire in most human beings an attitude of
respect, even in this age of technology. Nonetheless, the absence
of a respectful attitude is today a problem in some-though by no
means all-quarters of the biotechnical world. It is worrisome when
people act toward, or even talk about, our bodies and minds-or human
nature itself-as if they were mere raw material to be molded according
to human will. It is worrisome when people speak as if they were
wise enough to redesign human beings, improve the human brain, or
reshape the human life cycle. In the face of such hubristic temptations,
appreciating that the given world-including our natural powers to
alter it-is not of our own making could induce a welcome attitude
of modesty, restraint, and humility. Such a posture is surely recommended
for anyone inclined to modify human beings or human nature for purposes
beyond therapy.
Yet the respectful attitude toward the "given," while both necessary
and desirable as a restraint, is not by itself sufficient as a guide.
The "giftedness of nature" also includes smallpox and malaria, cancer
and Alzheimer disease, decline and decay. Moreover, nature is not
equally generous with her gifts, even to man, the most gifted of
her creatures. Modesty born of gratitude for the world's "givenness"
may enable us to recognize that not everything in the world is open
to any use we may desire or devise, but it will not by itself
teach us which things can be tinkered with and which should
be left inviolate. Respect for the "giftedness" of things cannot
tell us which gifts are to be accepted as is, which are to be improved
through use or training, which are to be housebroken through self-command
or medication, and which opposed like the plague.
To guide the proper use of biotechnical power, we need something
in addition to a generalized appreciation for nature's gifts. We
would need also a particular regard and respect for the special
gift that is our own given nature. For only if there is a human
"givenness," or a given humanness, that is also good and worth respecting,
either as we find it or as it could be perfected without ceasing
to be itself, will the "given" serve as a positive guide
for choosing what to alter and what to leave alone. Only if there
is something precious in our given human nature-beyond the fact
of its giftedness-can what is given guide us in resisting efforts
that would degrade it. When it comes to human biotechnical engineering
beyond therapy, only if there is something inherently good or dignified
about, say, natural procreation, the human life cycle (with its
rhythm of rise and fall), and human erotic longing and striving;
only if there is something inherently good or dignified about the
ways in which we engage the world as spectators and appreciators,
as teachers and learners, leaders and followers, agents and makers,
lovers and friends, parents and children, citizens and worshippers,
and as seekers of our own special excellence and flourishing in
whatever arena to which we are called-only then can we begin to
see why those aspects of our nature need to be defended against
our deliberate redesign.
We must move, therefore, from the danger of hubris in the powerful
designer to the danger of degradation in the designed, considering
how any proposed improvements might impinge upon the nature of the
one being improved. With the question of human nature and human
dignity in mind, we move to questions of means and ends.
B. "Unnatural" Means: The Dignity of Human Activity
Until only yesterday, teaching and learning or practice and training
exhausted the alternatives for acquiring human excellence, perfecting
our natural gifts through our own efforts. But perhaps no longer:
biotechnology may be able to do nature one better, even to the point
of requiring less teaching, training, or practice to permit an improved
nature to shine forth. As we noted earlier, the insertion of the
growth-factor gene into the muscles of rats and mice bulks them
up and keeps them strong and sound without the need for nearly as
much exertion. Drugs to improve alertness (today) or memory and
amiability (tomorrow) could greatly relieve the need for exertion
to acquire these powers, leaving time and effort for better things.
What, if anything, is disquieting about such means of gaining improvement?
The problem cannot be that they are "artificial," in the sense
of having man-made origins. Beginning with the needle and the fig
leaf, man has from the start been the animal that uses art to improve
his lot by altering or adding to what nature alone provides.vi
Ordinary medicine makes extensive use of similar artificial means,
from drugs to surgery to mechanical implants, in order to treat
disease. If the use of artificial means is absolutely welcome in
the activity of healing, it cannot be their unnaturalness alone
that disquiets us when they are used to make people "better than
well."
Still, in those areas of human life in which excellence has until
now been achieved only by discipline and effort, the attainment
of similar results by means of drugs, genetic engineering, or implanted
devices looks to many people (including some Members of this Council)
to be "cheating" or "cheap." Many people believe that each person
should work hard for his achievements. Even if we prefer the grace
of the natural athlete or the quickness of the natural mathematician-people
whose performances deceptively appear to be effortless-we admire
also those who overcome obstacles and struggle to try to achieve
the excellence of the former. This matter of character-the merit
of disciplined and dedicated striving-is surely pertinent. For character
is not only the source of our deeds, but also their product. As
we have already noted, healthy people whose disruptive behavior
is "remedied" by pacifying drugs rather than by their own efforts
are not learning self-control;vii
if anything, they may be learning to think it unnecessary. People
who take pills to block out from memory the painful or hateful aspects
of a new experience will not learn how to deal with suffering or
sorrow. A drug that induces fearlessness does not produce courage.
Yet things are not so simple. Some biotechnical interventions
may assist in the pursuit of excellence without in the least cheapening
its attainment. And many of life's excellences have nothing to do
with competition or overcoming adversity. Drugs to decrease drowsiness,
increase alertness, sharpen memory, or reduce distraction may actually
help people interested in their natural pursuits of learning or
painting or performing their civic duty. Drugs to steady the hand
of a neurosurgeon or to prevent sweaty palms in a concert pianist
cannot be regarded as "cheating," for they are in no sense the source
of the excellent activity or achievement. And, for people dealt
a meager hand in the dispensing of nature's gifts, it should not
be called cheating or cheap if biotechnology could assist them in
becoming better equipped-whether in body or in mind.
Nevertheless, as we suggested at some length in Chapter Three,
there remains a sense that the "naturalness" of means matters. It
lies not in the fact that the assisting drugs and devices are artifacts,
but in the danger of violating or deforming the nature of human
agency and the dignity of the naturally human way of activity. In
most of our ordinary efforts at self-improvement, whether by practice,
training, or study, we sense the relation between our doings and
the resulting improvement, between the means used and the end sought.
There is an experiential and intelligible connection between means
and ends; we can see how confronting fearful things might eventually
enable us to cope with our fears. We can see how curbing our appetites
produces self-command. Human education ordinarily proceeds by speech
or symbolic deeds, whose meanings are at least in principle directly
accessible to those upon whom they work.
In contrast, biotechnical interventions act directly on the human
body and mind to bring about their effects on a passive subject,
who plays little or no role at all. He can at best feel their
effects without understanding their meaning in human terms.
Thus, a drug that brightened our mood would alter us without our
understanding how and why it did so-whereas a mood brightened as
a fitting response to the arrival of a loved one or to an achievement
in one's work is perfectly, because humanly, intelligible. And not
only would this be true about our states of mind. All of our encounters
with the world, both natural and interpersonal, would be mediated,
filtered, and altered. Human experience under biological intervention
becomes increasingly mediated by unintelligible forces and vehicles,
separated from the human significance of the activities so altered.
The relations between the knowing subject and his activities, and
between his activities and their fulfillments and pleasures, are
disrupted.
The importance of human effort in human achievement is here properly
acknowledged: the point is less the exertions of good character
against hardship, but the manifestation of an alert and self-experiencing
agent making his deeds flow intentionally from his willing, knowing,
and embodied soul. If human flourishing means not just the accumulation
of external achievements and a full curriculum vitae but a lifelong
being-at-work exercising one's human powers well and
without great impediment, our genuine happiness requires that there
be little gap, if any, between the dancer and the dance.viii
C. Identity and Individuality
With biotechnical interventions that skip the realm of intelligible
meaning, we cannot really own the transformations nor can we experience
them as genuinely ours. And we will be at a loss to attest whether
the resulting conditions and activities of our bodies and our minds
are, in the fullest sense, our own as human. But our interest in
identity is also more personal. For we do not live in a generic
human way; we desire, act, flourish, and decline as ourselves,
as individuals. To be human is to be someone, not anyone-with a
given nature (male or female), given natural abilities (superior
wit or musical talent), and-most important-a real history of attachments,
memories, and experiences, acquired largely by living with others.
In myriad ways, new biotechnical powers promise (or threaten)
to transform what it means to be an individual: giving increased
control over our identity to others, as in the case of genetic screening
or sex selection of offspring by parents; inducing psychic states
divorced from real life and lived experience; blunting or numbing
the memories we wish to escape; and achieving the results we could
never achieve unaided, by acting as ourselves alone.
To be sure, in many cases, biomedical technology can restore or
preserve a real identity that is slipping away: keeping our memory
intact by holding off the scourge of Alzheimer disease; restoring
our capacity to love and work by holding at bay the demons of self-destroying
depression. In other cases, the effect of biotechnology on identity
is much more ambiguous. By taking psychotropic drugs to reduce anxiety
or overcome melancholy, we may become the person we always wished
to be-more cheerful, ambitious, relaxed, content. But we also become
a different person in the eyes of others, and in many cases we become
dependent on the continued use of psychotropic drugs to remain the
new person we now are.
As the power to transform our native powers increases, both in
magnitude and refinement, so does the possibility for "self-alienation"-for
losing, confounding, or abandoning our identity. I may get better,
stronger, and happier-but I know not how. I am no longer the agent
of self-transformation, but a passive patient of transforming powers.
Indeed, to the extent that an achievement is the result of some
extraneous intervention, it is detachable from the agent whose achievement
it purports to be. "Personal achievements" impersonally achieved
are not truly the achievements of persons. That I can use a calculator
to do my arithmetic does not make me a knower of arithmetic;
if computer chips in my brain were to "download" a textbook of physics,
would that make me a knower of physics? Admittedly, the relation
between biological boosters and personal identity is much less clear:
if I make myself more alert through Ritalin, or if drugs can make
up for lack of sleep, I may be able to learn more using my unimpeded
native powers while it is still unquestionably I who am doing
the learning. And yet, to find out that an athlete took steroids
before the race or that a test-taker (without medical disability)
took Ritalin before the test is to lessen our regard for the achievement
of the doer. It is to see not just an acting self, but a dependent
self, one who is less himself for becoming so dependent.
In the deepest sense, to have an identity is to have limits: my
body, not someone else's-even when the pains of aging might tempt
me to become young again; my memories, not someone else's-even when
the traumas of the past might tempt me to have someone else's memories;
my achievements and potential, not someone else's-even when the
desire for excellence might tempt me to "trade myself in" for a
"better model." We seek to be happy-to achieve, perform, take pleasure
in our experiences, and catch the admiring eye of a beloved. But
we do not, at least self-consciously, seek such happiness at the
cost of losing our real identity.
D. Partial Ends, Full Flourishing
Beyond the perils of achieving our desired goals in a "less-than-human
way" or in ways "not fully our own," we must consider the meaning
of the ends themselves: better children, superior performance, ageless
bodies, and happy souls. Would their attainment in fact improve
or perfect our lives as human beings? Are they-always or ever-reasonable
and attainable goals?
Everything depends, as we have pointed out in each case, on how
these goals are understood, on their specific and concrete content.
Yet, that said, the first two human ends-better children and superior
performance-do seem reasonable and attainable, sometimes if not
always, to some degree if not totally. When asked what they wish
for their children, most parents say: "We want them to be happy,"
or "We want them to live good lives"-in other words, to be better
and to do better. The desire is a fitting one for any loving parent.
The danger lies in misconceiving what "better children" really means,
and thus coming to pursue this worthy goal in a misguided way, or
with a false idea of what makes for a good or happy child.
Likewise, the goal of superior performance-the desire to be better
or do better in all that we do-is good and noble, a fitting human
aspiration. We admire excellence whenever we encounter it, and we
properly seek to excel in those areas of life, large and small,
where we ourselves are engaged and at-work. But the danger here
is that we will become better in some area of life by diminishing
ourselves in others, or that we will achieve superior results only
by compromising our humanity, or by corrupting those activities
that are not supposed to be "performances" measured in terms of
external standards of "better and worse."
In many cases, biotechnologies can surely help us cultivate what
is best in ourselves and in our children, providing new tools for
realizing good ends, wisely pursued. But it is also possible that
the new technological means may deform the ends themselves. In pursuit
of better children, biotechnical powers risk making us "tyrants";
in pursuit of superior performance, they risk making us "artifacts."
In both cases, the problem is not the ends themselves but our misguided
idea of their attainment or our false way of seeking to attain them.
And in both cases, there is the ubiquitous problem that "good" or
"superior" will be reconceived to fit the sorts of goals that the
technological interventions can help us attain. We may come to believe
that genetic predisposition or brain chemistry holds the key to
helping our children develop and improve, or that stimulant drugs
or bulkier muscles hold the key to excellent human activity. If
we are equipped with hammers, we will see only those things that
can be improved by pounding.
The goals of ageless bodies and happy souls-and especially the
ways biotechnology might shape our pursuit of these ends-are perhaps
more complicated.2
The case for ageless bodies seems at first glance to look pretty
good. The prevention of decay, decline, and disability, the avoidance
of blindness, deafness, and debility, the elimination of feebleness,
frailty, and fatigue, all seem to be conducive to living fully as
a human being at the top of one's powers-of having, as they say,
a "good quality of life" from beginning to end. We have come to
expect organ transplantation for our worn-out parts. We will surely
welcome stem-cell-based therapies for regenerative medicine, reversing
by replacement the damaged tissues of Parkinson disease, spinal
cord injury, and many other degenerative disorders. It is hard to
see any objection to obtaining a genetic enhancement of our muscles
in our youth that would not only prevent the muscular feebleness
of old age but would empower us to do any physical task with greater
strength and facility throughout our lives. And, should aging research
deliver on its promise of adding not only extra life to years but
also extra years to life, who would refuse it?
But as we suggested in Chapter Four, there may in fact be many
human goods that are inseparable from our aging bodies, from our
living in time, and especially from the natural human life cycle
by which each generation gives way to the one that follows it. Because
this argument is so counterintuitive, we need to begin not with
the individual choice for an ageless body, but with what the individual's
life might look like in a world in which everyone made the same
choice. We need to make the choice universal, and see the meaning
of that choice in the mirror of its becoming the norm.
What if everybody lived life to the hilt, even as they approached
an ever-receding age of death in a body that looked and functioned-let's
not be too greedy-like that of a thirty-year-old? Would it be good
if each and all of us lived like light bulbs, burning as brightly
from beginning to end, then popping off without warning, leaving
those around us suddenly in the dark? Or is it perhaps better that
there be a shape to life, everything in its due season, the shape
also written, as it were, into the wrinkles of our bodies that live
it-provided, of course, that we do not suffer years of painful or
degraded old age and that we do not lose our wits? What would the
relations between the generations be like if there never came a
point at which a son surpassed his father in strength or vigor?
What incentive would there be for the old to make way for the young,
if the old slowed down little and had no reason to think of retiring-if
Michael could play basketball until he were not forty but eighty?
Might not even a moderate prolongation of lifespan with vigor lead
to a prolongation in the young of functional immaturity-of the sort
that has arguably already accompanied the great increase in average
life expectancy experienced in the past century?ix
Going against both common intuition and native human desire, some
commentators have argued that living with full awareness and acceptance
of our finitude may be the condition of many of the best things
in human life: engagement, seriousness, a taste for beauty, the
possibility of virtue, the ties born of procreation, the quest for
meaning.3
This might be true not just for immortality-an unlikely achievement,
likely to produce only false expectations-but even for more modest
prolongations of the maximum lifespan, especially in good health,
that would permit us to live as if there were always tomorrow. The
pursuit of perfect bodies and further life-extension might deflect
us from realizing more fully the aspirations to which our lives
naturally point, from living well rather than merely staying alive.
A concern with one's own improving agelessness might finally be
incompatible with accepting the need for procreation and human renewal.
And far from bringing contentment, it might make us increasingly
anxious over our health or dominated by the fear of death. Assume,
merely for the sake of the argument, that even a few of these social
consequences would follow from a world of much greater longevity
and vigor: What would we then say about the simple goodness of seeking
an ageless body?
What about the pursuit of happy souls, and especially of the sort
that we might better attain with pharmacological assistance? Painful
and shameful memories are disturbing; guilty consciences trouble
sleep; low self-esteem, melancholy, and world-weariness besmirch
the waking hours. Why not memory-blockers for the former, mood-brighteners
for the latter, and a good euphoriant-without risks of hangovers
or cirrhosis-when celebratory occasions fail to be jolly? For let
us be clear: If it is imbalances of neurotransmitters that are largely
responsible for our state of soul, would it not be sheer priggishness
to refuse the help of pharmacology for our happiness, when we accept
it guiltlessly to correct for an absence of insulin or thyroid hormone?
And yet, as we suggested in Chapter Five, there seems to be something
misguided about the pursuit of utter and unbroken psychic tranquility
or the attempt to eliminate all shame, guilt, and painful memories.
Traumatic memories, shame, and guilt, are, it is true, psychic pains.
In extreme doses, they can be crippling. Yet, short of the extreme,
they can also be helpful and fitting. They are appropriate responses
to horror, disgraceful conduct, injustice, and sin, and, as such,
help teach us to avoid them or fight against them in the future.
Witnessing a murder should be remembered as horrible; doing a beastly
deed should trouble one's soul. Righteous indignation at injustice
depends on being able to feel injustice's sting. And to deprive
oneself of one's memory-including and especially its truthfulness
of feeling-is to deprive oneself of one's own life and identity.
These feeling states of soul, though perhaps accompaniments of
human flourishing, are not its essence. Ersatz pleasure or feelings
of self-esteem are not the real McCoy. They are at most shadows
divorced from the underlying human activities that are the essence
of flourishing. Most people want both to feel good and to feel good
about themselves, but only as a result of being good and doing good.
At the same time, there appears to be a connection between the
possibility of feeling deep unhappiness and the prospects for achieving
genuine happiness. If one cannot grieve, one has not truly loved.
To be capable of aspiration, one must know and feel lack. As Wallace
Stevens put it: Not to have is the beginning of desire. In short,
if human fulfillment depends on our being creatures of need and
finitude and therewith of longings and attachment, there may be
a double-barreled error in the pursuit of ageless bodies and factitiously
happy souls: far from bringing us what we really need, pursuing
these partial goods could deprive us of the urge and energy to seek
a richer and more genuine flourishing.
Looking into the future at goals pursuable with the aid of new
biotechnologies enables us to turn a reflective glance at our own
version of the human condition and the prospects now available to
us (in principle) for a flourishing human life. For us today, assuming
that we are blessed with good health and a sound mind, a flourishing
human life is not a life lived with an ageless body or an untroubled
soul, but rather a life lived in rhythmed time, mindful of time's
limits, appreciative of each season and filled first of all with
those intimate human relations that are ours only because we are
born, age, replace ourselves, decline, and die-and know it. It is
a life of aspiration, made possible by and born of experienced lack,
of the disproportion between the transcendent longings of the soul
and the limited capacities of our bodies and minds. It is a life
that stretches towards some fulfillment to which our natural human
soul has been oriented, and, unless we extirpate the source, will
always be oriented. It is a life not of better genes and enhancing
chemicals but of love and friendship, song and dance, speech and
deed, working and learning, revering and worshipping.
If this is true, then the pursuit of an ageless body may prove
finally to be a distraction and a deformation. And the pursuit of
an untroubled and self-satisfied soul may prove to be deadly to
desire, if finitude recognized spurs aspiration and fine aspiration
acted upon is itself the core of happiness. Not the agelessness
of the body, nor the contentment of the soul, nor even the list
of external achievements and accomplishments of life, but the engaged
and energetic being-at-work of what nature uniquely gave to us is
what we need to treasure and defend. All other "perfections" may
turn out to be at best but passing illusions, at worst a Faustian
bargain that could cost us our full and flourishing humanity.
Summing up these "essential sources of concern," we might succinctly
formulate them as follows:
In wanting to become more than we are, and in sometimes acting
as if we were already superhuman or divine, we risk despising
what we are and neglecting what we have.
In wanting to improve our bodies and our minds using new tools
to enhance their performance, we risk making our bodies and minds
little different from our tools, in the process also compromising
the distinctly human character of our agency and activity.
In seeking by these means to be better than we are or to like
ourselves better than we do, we risk "turning into someone else,"
confounding the identity we have acquired through natural gift
cultivated by genuinely lived experiences, alone and with others.
In seeking brighter outlooks, reliable contentment, and dependable
feelings of self-esteem in ways that by-pass their usual natural
sources, we risk flattening our souls, lowering our aspirations,
and weakening our loves and attachments.
By lowering our sights and accepting the sorts of satisfactions
that biotechnology may readily produce for us, we risk turning
a blind eye to the objects of our natural loves and longings,
the pursuit of which might be the truer road to a more genuine
happiness.
To avoid such outcomes, our native human desires need to be educated
against both excess and error. We need, as individuals and as a
society, to find these boundaries and to learn how to preserve and
defend them. To do so in an age of biotechnology, we need to ponder
and answer questions like the following:
When does parental desire for better children constrict their
freedom or undermine their long-term chances for self-command
and genuine excellence?
When does the quest for self-improvement make the "self" smaller
or meaner?
When does a preoccupation with youthful bodies or longer life
jeopardize the prospects for living well?
When does the quest for contentment or self-esteem lead us away
from the activities and attachments that prove to be essential
to these goals when they are properly understood?
Answers to these questions are not easily given in the abstract
or in advance. Boundaries are hard to define in the absence of better
knowledge of the actual hazards. Such knowledge will be obtainable
only in time and only as a result of lived experience. But centrally
important in shaping the possible future outcomes will be the cultural
attitudes and social practices that shape desires, govern expectations,
and influence the choices people make, now and in the future. This
means reflecting more specifically on how biotechnology beyond therapy
might affect and be affected by American society.
IV. Biotechnology and American Society
In free societies such as our own, choices about using biotechnologies
are not made by central planners looking to realize some dream of
a more perfect future society. They are made largely by private
individuals looking to realize their personal dream of a better
life, for themselves and for their children. The choices that they
make will, of course, be constrained by boundaries set by law and
by the limits of their own resources. More subtly, they will be
influenced by the social norms, cultural ideals, and institutional
practices of their communities-as these norms, ideals, and practices
are themselves reciprocally shaped by the aggregated results of
countless private choices. No account of our subject would be complete
without a brief look at these larger social implications.
Looking over the horizon, what sort of society might we be getting
in the coming age of biotechnology? What sort of society are we,
in fact, bringing into being, knowingly or unknowingly, by our private
choices? And how might our existing American norms, ideals, and
practices frame and color the "big picture" whose outlines are only
now becoming visible?
On the optimistic view, the emerging picture is one of unmitigated
progress and improvement, yielding a society in which more and more
people are able to realize the American dream of liberty, prosperity,
and justice for all. Projecting that the present century will continue
the remarkable achievements of the one just ended, it is easy to
imagine a society whose citizens are healthier, longer-lived, livelier,
freer, more competent, better educated, more productive, better
accomplished, and happier than they have ever been in any society
now known, including our own. Many more human beings-now biologically
better equipped, aided by performance-enhancers, and more liberated
from the constraints of nature and fortune-might someday live on
a much higher human plane than has hitherto been possible save for
very few people. This rosy picture of the future, encouraged by
our past successes, cannot be lightly gainsaid.
Yet, as we have suggested throughout this report, there are reasons
to expect more mixed or even unattractive outcomes. For example,
there are risks-small in today's United States-of a sex-unbalanced
society, the result of unrestrained free choice in selecting the
sex of children; or of a change-resisting gerontocracy, with the
"elders" still young in body but old and tired in outlook. And there
are still uglier possibilities: an increasingly stratified and inegalitarian
society, now with purchased biological enhancements, with enlarged
gaps between the over-privileged few and the under-privileged many;
a society of narcissists focused on personal satisfaction and self-regard,
with little concern for the next generation or the common good;
a society of social conformists but with shallow attachments, given
over to cosmetic fashions and trivial pursuits; or a society of
fiercely competitive individuals, caught up in an ever-spiraling
struggle to get ahead, using the latest biotechnical assistance
both to perform better and to deal with the added psychic stress.
Lacking prophetic powers, we will not hazard any guesses as to
which of these prospects is more likely to be our future. Up until
now, such visionary work has been best left to the imaginative gifts
of science fiction writers, who, more than everyone else, have thought
seriously aboutwhere biotechnology may be taking us, for better
and for worse. From now on, however, we will do well to pay attention
to this matter, devising the sorts of social indicators and empirical
research that could teach us which way the social and cultural winds
are blowing.
But if we can only dimly perceive our possible or likely futures,
we can clearly recognize some features of contemporary American
life that will, almost certainly, exercise great influence over
the future that is likely to emerge. Among them we would identify
the importance of commerce, the practice of medicine, and the ruling
ideals and ethos of the American polity. They are already playing
major roles in determining which of the many possible social futures
our grandchildren and great-grandchildren will inherit.
A. Commerce, Regulation, and the Manufacture
of Desire
Whether one likes it or not, progress in biology and biotechnology
is now intimately bound up with industry and commerce. Although
the federal government is still the major sponsor of biomedical
research, more and more scientists work in partnership with industry.
And the emergence of a vigorous biotech industry, growing rapidly
even before it has delivered very much of its great promise, is
a sign of things to come. Whatever one finally thinks about the
relative virtues and vices of contemporary capitalism, it is a fact
that progress in science and technology owes much to free enterprise.
The possibility of gain adds the fuel of interest to the fire of
genius, and even as the profits accrue only to some, the benefits
are, at least in principle, available to all. And the competition
to succeed provides enormous incentives to innovation, growth, and
progress. We have every reason to expect exponential increases in
biotechnologies and, therefore, in their potential uses in all aspects
of human life.
Two aspects of the marriage between biotechnology and free-market
commerce pose challenges to our ability to keep control of how those
powers will be used. First, scientists and entrepreneurs, for perfectly
understandable reasons, want no interference with research or development.
Freedom to experiment is essential to discovery; freedom to invent
and to market is essential to technological advance. Distrustful
of governmental regulation and leery of public scrutiny of their
activities, biologists and technologists are especially inclined
to resist legal limitations that might be imposed on their activities
based on ethical considerations. Like those who would prefer to
"go slow," they vigorously make their interests felt in the deliberations
of government. Yet in the long run, as members of American society,
they have as much to gain or lose as anyone else from the kind of
society that their own efforts are helping to create. What sort
of society it will be will depend in part on whether industry and
the broader public will collaborate in finding ways to monitor and
regulate the uses of biotechnology beyond therapy.
Entrepreneurs not only resist governmental limitation of their
work or restrictions on the uses to which their products may be
put. They also promote public demand. The success of enterprise
often turns on anticipating and stimulating consumer demand, sometimes
even on creating it where none exists. Suitably stimulated, the
demand of consumers for easier means to better-behaved children,
more youthful or beautiful or potent bodies, keener or more focused
minds, and steadier or more cheerful moods is potentially enormous.
If the existing cosmetic industry may be taken as a model, the sky
may be the limit for a truly effective "cosmetic pharmacology" that
would deliver stronger muscles, better memories, brighter moods,
and peace of mind. The direct-to-consumer advertising of pharmaceutical
and other companies-for mood-brighteners, fatigue lesseners, youth
preservatives, and behavior modifiers-is a harbinger of things to
come. Today it is Ritalin, Botox, Rogaine, Viagra, and Prozac; could
tomorrow be "Memorase," "Popeye's Potion," "Eroticor," "Self-love,"
or "Soma"? Desires can be manufactured almost as effectively as
pills, especially if the pills work more or less as promised to
satisfy the newly stimulated desires. By providing quick solutions
for short-term problems or prompt fulfillment of easily satisfied
desires, the character of human longing itself could be altered,
with large aspirations for long-term flourishing giving way before
the immediate gratification of smaller desires. What to do about
this is far from clear; but its importance should not be underestimated.
B. Medicine, Medicalization, and a Stance "Beyond
Therapy"
Wherever they may be invented and manufactured, most new
biotechnologies, including those serving goals beyond therapy, will
probably enter ordinary use through the offices of the medical profession.
Should this occur, the pursuit of happiness and self-perfection
would become part of the doctor's business, joining many other aspects
of human life that formerly had little to do with doctors and hospitals:
childbirth, infertility, sexual mores and practices, aspects of
criminal behavior, alcoholism, abnormal behavior, anxiety, stress,
dementia, old age, death, grief, and mourning-all these have over
the past century been at least partially medicalized, and often
with good reasons and welcome results.x
The causes of medicalization are many, among them, the power of
modern biological explanation and technique; the growth in medical
knowledge and competence; the expanding domain of psychiatry, the
"doctoring of the psyche"; increased success using medical interventions;
and rising patient expectations of cure, relief, and salvation coming
from health care professionals. It is also driven by deep cultural
and intellectual currents, for example, to see more and more things
in life not as natural givens to be coped with but as objects rightly
subject to our mastery and control; to have compassion for victims,
even when the victims are victimized by their own foolish conduct;
to see the human person not in spiritual or moral terms, but as
a highly complex and successful product of blind evolutionary forces
(which still perturb him through no fault of his own); and-very
important-the acceptance of "health" as the one readily recognized
and utterly uncontroversial human good (in contrast, say, with virtue,
morality, or wisdom). With the decline in the cultural authority
of religious institutions, and with the shrinking of other communal
systems of help and support for people in difficulty, physicians
often find themselves simply "neighbor to the problem." Rightly
extending a helping hand, they often conceive and treat the problems
they encounter in a purely medical fashion.
As new biotechnologies appear, with novel uses beyond therapy,
the tendency toward medicalization will almost certainly be strengthened,
both as a matter of practice and as a matter of thought. Physicians
are the gatekeepers of biomedical technologies. They are judges
of proper use. They are aware of dangerous side effects. They prescribe
and dispense as they see fit. The medical profession is clothed
in venerable ethical dress; in the United States there are also
professional standards of good practice that offer guidance and
principles of reimbursement that set limits on free professional
and patient choices. Nevertheless, the practice of medicine is highly
decentralized, and each physician has enormous discretion in dealing
with patients, able to adapt general practices to the special needs
and circumstances of each individual. All this is comforting and
reassuring, more so than if the new biotechnical powers were wielded
by an upstart group of technicians lacking these professional assets
and virtues.
But there are difficulties when medical practice moves beyond
therapy. Where the goal is restoring health, the doctor's discretion
is guided by an agreed-upon and recognizable target. But a physician
prescribing for goals beyond therapy is in uncharted waters. Although
fully armed with the means, he has no special expertise regarding
the end-neither what it is nor whether it is desirable. To the extent
that the patient is transformed from a sick person needing healing
into a consumer of technical services, medicine will be transformed
from a profession into a trade and the doctor-patient relationship
into a species of contract, ungoverned by any deep ethical norms.
Should this occur, the medical profession and the health care system
will be called upon to practice retail sanity regarding the technologies
and wholesale madness regarding the ends, the costs, and the possible
consequences of their use. The health-care system in the United
States already constitutes roughly one-sixth of the gross national
product. What might it become in the coming age beyond therapy?
There is yet a second and perhaps more fundamental danger in the
growth of medicalization, a danger of thinking and outlook whose
consequences could well be profound. The therapeutic intention at
the heart of medicine-the goal of making whole that which is broken
or disabled-runs the risk of looking increasingly upon the entire
human condition in this way and, as a result, of regarding biotechnological
measures as the royal road to improving our lot in life. Two opposing
dangers need to be avoided. On the one hand, there is the risk of
viewing everything in human life-not only human frailties, disappointments,
and death itself, but also human relationships, pride and shame,
love and sorrow, and all self-discontent-under the lens of disease
and disability. Such a tendency would encourage everywhere the idea
of human life as "victimhood" in need of rescue; it would discourage
everywhere the idea that human beings are responsible agents and,
at their best, noble creatures aspiring to and capable of genuine
excellence and flourishing. On the other hand, there is the risk
of attacking human limitation altogether, seeking to produce a more-than-human
being, one not only without illnesses, but also without foibles,
fatigue, failures, or foolishness.xi
Seen against these problematic temptations, the remedy for the
dangers lurking in the drift toward greater medicalization and "beyond
therapy" is, paradoxically, to be found in rethinking the very idea
of "beyond therapy." It is to be found in adopting a standpoint
toward human life that is, in another sense of the term, radically
beyond therapy. It does not start with medicine to discover
the terrain that lies beyond the goals of medicine. It looks beyond
the therapeutic view of life altogether. It rejects and goes beyond
the "therapy versus enhancement" distinction for a reason deeper
than those we gave at the outset of this report (see Chapter One):
for medicine, sickness, and healing are not the natural or best
lens through which to look upon the whole of human life. Health,
though a primary human good, is not the only-or even the supreme-human
good.
Going "beyond therapy" in this sense means returning to an account
of the human being seen not in material or mechanistic or medical
terms but in psychic and moral and spiritual ones. It is to see
the human being as a creature "in-between," neither god nor beast,
neither dumb body nor disembodied soul, but as a puzzling, upward-pointing
unity of psyche and soma whose precise limitations are the source
of its-our-loftiest aspirations, whose weaknesses are the source
of its-our-keenest attachments, and whose natural gifts may be,
if we do not squander or destroy them, exactly what we need to flourish
and perfect ourselves-as human beings. Readers, we hope,
will recognize that this entire report has been written from this
more-than-therapeutic perspective and with this richly humanistic
intent.
C. Biotechnology and American Ideals
The significance of these two prominent features of American life-the
power of free markets and the prestige of medicine-points us also
toward a greater understanding of the implications of our new biotechnical
powers for our American ideals. In a certain sense, as a people
committed to life, liberty, and the pursuit of happiness, we may
tend to be especially drawn to the promise of biotechnology. Some
of the techniques we have discussed offer the prospect of longer
and livelier life, of expanded liberty made possible by improved
abilities and powers, and of a more successful and fulfilling pursuit
of happiness. Medicine thrives in a culture that values life; science
and enterprise thrive in a society that values freedom; technology
flourishes in a nation eager to make life more prosperous and comfortable.
And yet, these very ideals also offer reasons to moderate the
desires that drive us toward greater biotechnological prowess, and
to look upon new possibilities through the lens of a rich yet temperate
understanding of the human condition. Even as they encourage progress,
the American principles may serve to moderate a dangerous utopianism.
Our devotion to life is understood in light of the human dedication
to the good life, and so calls for reflection on our most
basic priorities, and on just what it is that gives life its significance.
Our aspiration to liberty is grounded in some sense that we men
and women are the beings deserving of liberty, and capable of using
it well. It reminds us, also, that our actions always run the risk
of curtailing the freedom of others, including especially that of
future generations-to whom we owe the same liberty passed down to
us. And our nation's declared commitment to the pursuit of happiness-understood
in light of our devotion to life, and our dedication to meaningful
liberty-invites us to consider the nature (and also the limits)
of happiness, and to wonder what sort of happiness a people so devoted
and dedicated might rightly pursue.
But these American ideals, and the character of the nation they
have helped to shape, moderate not only our hopes but also our fears.
The reservations we have raised in this report are the worries of
a free and decent people-concerned for its character and its goodness
and its soul. Had we looked only at the perils of the technologies
that seem to lie in our future, and had we sought to imagine the
worst, it would not have been difficult to raise up specters of
terrifying and inhuman violations, or of an unprecedented despotism
of man over man, with powerful new technologies serving as the whips
of new slave-masters. The recent history of the human race offers
no dearth of sources for such nightmarish visions. But that is not
what we perceive when we peer over the horizon, because our society,
dedicated as it is to life and liberty and happiness, is always
alert to repel such excesses.
Rather, the concerns we have raised here emerge from a sense that
tremendous new powers to serve certain familiar and often well-intentioned
desires may blind us to the larger meaning of our ideals, and may
narrow our sense of what it is to live, to be free, and to seek
after happiness. If, by informing and moderating our desires and
by grasping the limits of our new powers, we can keep in mind the
meaning of our founding ideals, then we just might find the means
to savor some fruits of the age of biotechnology, without succumbing
to its most dangerous temptations.
To do so, we must first understand just what is at stake, and
we must begin to imagine what the age of biotechnology might bring,
and what human life in that age could look like. In these pages,
we have sought to begin that vital project, in the hope that these
first steps might spark and inform a public debate, so that however
the nation proceeds, it will do so with its eyes wide open.
_______________
Footnotes
i.
For example: It mattered to the young woman we cited in Chapter
Five that the young man said he loved
her only because he was high on Ecstasy. It matters to all of
us that the people we have dealings with are not psychotropically
out of their right minds. In neither case is the issue one of
unfair advantage.
ii.
The danger of despotism of one generation over the next is,
in fact, one of the arguments sometimes voiced against human
cloning. See our report, Human Cloning and Human Dignity:
An Ethical Inquiry, Washington, D.C.: Government Printing
Office, 2002.
iii.
Freedom does not automatically increase with a growing range
of options. On the contrary, if the options differ but little
from one another (Nike rather than Adidas, Budweiser rather
than Coors), and if the choosing agent expends growing energies
on choices that contribute but little to his or her genuine
well-being, enjoying one's greater number of options might represent
a curtailment of a deeper and more genuine freedom.
iv.Which
of the imaginable social consequences will in fact occur is,
of course, an empirical question, though it is worthwhile to
think about the alternatives in advance. Indeed, anticipatory
reflection might play a role in helping to forestall some of
the worst possible outcomes. We return to the relation of biotechnology
to American society in the last section of this chapter.
v.
The question of the knowledge and goodness of goals is often
the neglected topic when people use the language of "mastery,"
or "mastery and control of nature," to describe what we do when
we use knowledge of how nature works to alter its character
and workings. Mastery of the means of intervention without knowing
the goodness of the goals of intervening is not, in fact, mastery
at all. In the absence of such knowledge of ends, the goals
of the "master" will be set rather by whatever it is that happens
to guide or move his will-some impulse or whim or feeling or
desire-in short, by some residuum of nature still working within
the so-called master or controller. To paraphrase C. S. Lewis,
what looks like man's mastery of nature turns out, in the absence
of guiding knowledge, to be nature's mastery of man. (See his
The Abolition of Man, New York: Macmillan, 1965, paperback
edition, pp. 72-80.) There can, in truth, be no such thing as
the full escape from the grip of our own nature. To pretend
otherwise is indeed a form of hubristic and dangerous self-delusion.
For reasons given in the text, therapeutic medicine, though
it may use the same technologies, should not be regarded as
"mastery of nature," but as service to nature, as we come to
know, through medical science, how it might best be served.
vi.
By his very nature, man is the animal constantly looking for
ways to better his life through artful means and devices; man
is the animal with what Rousseau called "perfectibility."
vii.
We have also noted that other people, suffering from certain
neuro-psychiatric disorders, become capable of learning self-control
only with the aid of medication addressed to their disorders.
viii.
This is not merely to suggest that there is a disturbance of
human agency or freedom, or a disruption of activities that
will confound the assignment of personal responsibility or undermine
the proper bestowal of praise and blame. To repeat: most of
life's activities are non-competitive; most of the best of them-loving
and working and savoring and learning-are self-fulfilling beyond
the need for praise and blame or any other external reward.
In these activities, there is at best no goal beyond the activity
itself. It is the possibility of natural, unimpeded, for-itself
human activity, that we are eager to preserve against dilution
and distortion.
ix.
The gift of added years of expected future life is surely a
great blessing for the young. But is the correlative perception
of a seemingly limitless future an equal blessing? How preciously
do people regard each day of life when its limits are out of
sight?
x.
"Medicalization," a term coined by sociologists, means in the
first instance a way of thinking and conceiving human phenomena
in medical terms, which then guides ways of acting and organizing
social institutions. More fully, it is the tendency to conceive
an activity, phenomenon, condition, behavior, etc., as a disease
or disorder or as an affliction that should be regarded as a
disease or disorder: (1) people suffer it (the essence
of patient-hood) or it befalls them; they are victims
of it, hence not responsible for it; (2) the causes are physical
or somatic, not "mental" or "spiritual" or "psychic";
(3) it requires (needs) and demands (has a claim to) treatment,
aimed at cure or at least relief and abatement of symptoms;
(4) at the hands of persons trained in the healing arts and
licensed as healers; and (5) this conception of the condition
will be supported by the society, which will also support efforts
at treatment out of its interest in the health (as opposed
to the morals or the education) of its people. The term is used-both
in the literature and by us here-as neutral description, without
any implied judgment. We have discussed medicalization of mental
life briefly in Chapter Five.
xi.
Or without birthmarks, the superficial sign of being marked
from birth as finite and frail. See Nathaniel Hawthorne, "The
Birth-mark."
_______________
Endnotes
1.
This discussion depends heavily on a paper by Michael J. Sandel,
"What's Wrong with Enhancement," prepared for the President's
Council on Bioethics, Washington, D.C., December 12, 2002. Copy
available at the Council's website, www.bioethics.gov.
2.
The discussion that follows depends heavily on a paper by Leon
R. Kass, "Beyond Therapy: Biotechnology and the Pursuit of Human
Improvement," prepared for the President's Council on Bioethics,
Washington, D.C., January 16, 2003. Copy available at the Council's
website at www.bioethics.gov.
3.
See, for example, Jonas, H., "The Blessings and Burdens of Mortality,"
Hastings Center Report, January/February 1992; Kass, L.,
"L'Chaim and Its Limits: Why Not Immortality," in Life,
Liberty, and the Defense of Dignity: The Challenge for Bioethics,
San Francisco: Encounter Books, 2002.
|