beyond therapy: biotechnology
and the pursuit of happiness
The President's Council on Bioethics
Washington, D.C.
October 2003 www.bioethics.gov Chapter
Three
Superior Performance
Human beings desire not only "better children," we desire also
to be better ourselves. Aspiration, born of the attractiveness of
some human good and the energizing awareness that we do not yet
possess it, is at the heart of much that we do and much that is
admirable about us. We strive to be better human beings and citizens,
better friends and lovers, better parents and neighbors, better
students and teachers, better followers of our faiths. Many of us
aspire also to excel in the specific activities to which we devote
ourselves; and nearly all of us admire superior performance whenever
we encounter it, even in areas where we ourselves are only mediocre.
Superior performance is pursued in a myriad of human activities.
The athlete strives to run faster, the student to know more, the
soldier to shoot more accurately, the vocalist to sing more musically,
the chess-player to play with greater mastery. Our motives for seeking
superior performance are varied and complex, as human desire and
human aspiration always are. We seek to win in competition, to advance
in rank and status, to increase our earnings, to please others and
ourselves, to gain honor and fame, or simply to flourish and fulfill
ourselves by being excellent in doing what we love. In pursuing
superior performance, human beings have long sought advantages obtainable
from better tools and equipment, better training and practice, and
better nutrition and exercise. Today, and increasingly tomorrow,
we may also find help in new technological capacities for directly
improving our bodies and minds-both their native powers and their
activities-capacities provided by drugs, genetic modifications,
and surgical procedures (including the implantation of mechanical
devices). What should we think about obtaining superior performance
through the use of such biotechnologies? That is the theme of this
chapter. But before turning to the question raised by the novel
means, we must begin with questions about the goal itself: "What
is superior performance?"
I. THE MEANING OF "SUPERIOR PERFORMANCE"
The words themselves-"superior performance"-have many meanings,
both individually and together, each of them suggestive and important.
"Superior" can mean "better than I have done before," or "better
than my opponent," or "better than the best." It can describe something
that is universally or indisputably outstanding or something that
is better only in relation to the alternatives. It can also mean-and
this is especially relevant in this context-"better than I would
have done without some 'extra edge' or 'performance enhancement.'"
Because superiority, on whatever meaning, is time-bound and precarious,
we not only seek to do better than we have done before. We also
seek to maintain abilities that seem to be slipping away and to
regain powers and abilities that we have lost. We want to become
superior and stay superior.
Even more central to our analysis is the meaning (or meanings)
of "performance." It denotes the active doing of what
we do and the active expression of what we are: living
embodied beings or agents, individually at-work in the world.
To be alive at all means that certain organic systems are performing
their functions. In the human case, active performance includes
not only the autonomic activity of a well-working organism functioning
without conscious choice and direction (for example, in heart beating,
digesting, and normal breathing). It also includes the self-directed
performance of various chosen human activities (for example,
walking, running, dancing, thinking). To "perform" an activity
is not just to do it, but to do it thoroughly, "through and through,"
to do it to completion and fullness. The idea of performance also
suggests a relationship with other performers and spectators: performance
before others, with others, and against others. Yet it is also possible
to perform certain activities without others, on one's own
and for oneself, manifesting who we are for our own enjoyment alone.
Temporally speaking, a performance is both that which is done "in-the-moment"
(a great shot to win the game, a great musical performance) and
that which is done "over time" (a great career, writing a great
symphony). It embraces that which is done effortlessly or seemingly
effortlessly (Joe DiMaggio swinging the bat) and that which is done
with great and obvious exertion (Pete Rose hustling to turn a single
into a double). Finally, and most pertinent to this inquiry, the
word "performance" sometimes means a brilliant illusion, a skilled
simulation of reality, or the separation of what one does from who
one is: performance as the make-believe acting of actors rather
than the self-revealing doings of genuine doers. "Performance" suggests
both real activity and real agency, but also the possibility of
being or seeming to be something other than who and what we are.
At the core of the notion of "superior performance"-understood
as an object of noble aspiration-is the idea of excellent human
activity: excellent, not inferior; human, not inhuman or nonhuman;
active and not passive, at-work and not idling. The reason we spend
much of our lives trying to "better ourselves"-not just materially,
but as athletes, musicians, soldiers, or lovers-is that we know
or believe that not all performances are equal: some are higher
and some are lower, some are more worthy and some are less worthy,
some are excellent and some are average. But we desire to excel
as human beings; we want to exercise our distinctively human
powers both excellently and in our peculiarly human way. We know
or believe that some performances will reveal who we are capable
of being when we are at our best.i
The striving for superior performance is, as noted, central to
our humanity. But it also raises a series of questions and dilemmas,
and sometimes unease and concern, not only about the means we employ,
but also about the goal itself. We worry that the desire to become
better could deform elements of human life that are not properly
measured according to the standard of "superiority," or that our
improvements will be achieved only at the price of our integrity
and dignity. We worry that pressures to excel will overwhelm us,
or that the desire to be the best will tempt us to "cheat" our way
to the top. We worry that putting such a high premium on excellence
will crowd out the disadvantaged, or lead us to mistreat those who
are "failures." In short, we worry about balance, fairness, and
charity-but also, and perhaps more profoundly, we worry about pursuing
the wrong goals in the wrong way, or posing as something we are
not.
These enduring questions about the pursuit of superior performance
acquire heightened visibility and greater salience as a result of
emerging new biotechnological powers, present and projected, that
promise to help us in our efforts. These powers are surgical, genetic,
and pharmacological. Some are familiar-like steroids used to enhance
athletic performance and amphetamines used to enhance mental performance.
Others are novel-such as the genetic modification of human muscles.
And still others are imaginary rather than real-such as genetically
engineered Michael Jordans or drugs that would give us perfect memory.
Most of the performance-enhancing technologies of the future,
like those in use today, will probably be developed less to aid
superior performance than to treat disease and relieve suffering.
Yet the broad powers of many drugs and devices make them readily
adaptable to uses for which they were not originally intended. Our
biotechnical armamentarium for aiding superior performance is still
extremely limited. Yet we are already witnessing the wide range
of activities that might be biologically enhanced. Modafinil, a
drug that combats narcolepsy and induces wakefulness more generally,
has been shown to enhance the performance of airplane pilots, commercial
and military. Ritalin, the amphetamine-like stimulant whose use
in children we discussed in the previous chapter, is also widely
used by high school and college students to improve their concentration
while taking the SATs or writing final exams. Viagra, a remedy devised
for male impotence, is increasingly used by the non-impotent to
enhance sexual performance. Growth hormone, the body's natural promoter
of skeletal growth, is now being used not only to treat dwarfism
but also to help the normally short to become taller. Other drugs
are used to calm the nerves or to steady and dry the hands of neurosurgeons
and concert pianists. These examples constitute but a small preview
of coming attractions.
To fully understand the meaning of using these new biotechnical
powers, in all their variety of effects and possible uses, we would
need to inquire more deeply into the meaning of "superior performance"
itself. We would need to explore the reasons we seek to become better,
the abilities we seek to enhance, the different means we might use
to enhance them, and the true character of the different activities
in which we engage. We would need to pay attention both to the ends
we seek and the means and manner by which we seek them, as well
as the differences between given human activities, their various
excellences and what it takes to attain them. And, attending to
the special issues raised by the use of bio-engineered enhancements,
we would need to address these central questions: As we discover
new and better ways to "improve" our given bodies, minds, and performance,
are we changing or compromising the dignity of human activity? Are
we becoming too reliant on "expert chemists" for our achievements?
Do such potential enhancements alter the identity of the doer? Whose
performance is it, and is it really better? Is the enhanced person
still fully me, and are my achievements still fully
mine? Have I been enhanced in ways that are in fact genuinely better
and humanly better? And, beyond these questions regarding
individuals, we would need to consider the implications for society
should such uses of biotechnology become widespread-in school, at
work, or in athletics, warfare, or other competitive activities.
Needless to say, such a comprehensive examination is beyond the
possible scope of this discussion. There are too many different
kinds of superior performance and too many conceivable biotechnical
means of enhancing the performers. To introduce the subject and
to illustrate the ethical and social issues involved, we confine
ourselves largely to one particular case study in one particular
area of human activity: human sport. It is an activity where
human excellence is both recognizable and admired, where concerns
about wrongfully enhancing performance are familiar, and where disquiet
about the use of "performance-enhancing drugs" is widely shared
if not always fully understood. As we shall see, many of the larger
questions readily emerge from this case study, and the relevance
of the present analysis for other human activities should be plain.
Where explicit comparisons with other human activities will prove
revealing, we shall not hesitate to bring them into the picture.
II. SPORT AND THE SUPERIOR ATHLETE
A. Why Sport?
At first glance, focusing on athletic excellence may seem strange.
True, sports are hugely popular and exciting, and the achievements
of our greatest athletes are very impressive. But is sport important?
Why spend time worrying about the dignity of athletics when there
are many more serious problems in the world and when many life and
death dilemmas in bioethics are so pressing? Such questions raise
a powerful point: many aspects of human life are indeed more significant
or more worth worrying about than athletics. Nevertheless, if one
is interested not only in combating human misery but also in promoting
human excellence, the world of sport is an extremely useful case
study. Indeed, what we learn of wider application from thinking
about athletics may prove far more significant than it first appears.
For one thing, sport is an area of human endeavor where human
excellence is widely admired-where we honor the best for their achievements,
and where we admire the striving of those who seek to improve, achieve,
and excel.ii
Athletic excellence appeals partly because it is open, genuine,
and publicly visible, inviting thousands of otherwise disconnected
individuals to unite in shared appreciation. In perhaps no other
contemporary activity is there such a manifestly evident and celebrated
display of individual (and group) human excellence.
Second, sport is an activity that invites deeper reflection about
our bodily nature, and especially our distinctly human bodily nature.
After all, animals and machines can do many things much better than
we can-artificial pitching machines can "throw" harder, cheetahs
can run faster. But it is the human athlete that we admire. Understanding
why this is so has implications far beyond athletics.
Third, sport is an area of life where we have made some effort-both
cultural and legal-to preserve the "dignity of the game," so to
speak, from "cheating," both biological (for example, steroids)
and mechanical (for example, corked bats). But we have done so without
always examining precisely how the dignity of the game or the excellence
of the performance would be compromised were the use of these enhancing
agents to become normal.
Thus, while we begin this analysis by acknowledging that "life
is not a game," we also suggest that things essential to sport-such
as aspiration, effort, activity, achievement, and excellence-are
essential also to many aspects of the good human life.iii
Examining the significance of performance-enhancing biotechnical
powers for human sport may help us understand the significance of
such powers for excellent human activity more generally.
B. The Superior Athlete
To be a superior athlete depends on numerous things: native gifts,
great desire, hard work, fine coaching, worthy competitors, sound
equipment, good luck. The types of talents needed will vary with
the sport or, in team sports featuring specialization, with one's
position or role. But any superior athlete requires strength, drive,
endurance, coordination, agility, vision, quickness, cleverness,
discipline, and daring, shared virtues of body and soul that manifest
themselves in different ways and degrees depending on the activity
and the way one performs it. And, in every sport, at every level
of competition, superior performance matters.
Some ways of becoming a superior athlete center on the athlete
himself: for example, healthy physical growth, better training,
more experience. Others involve outside help: better coaches, better
teammates, better competitors. Some involve improving one's equipment:
fiberglass vaulting poles, graphite tennis rackets, high-tech high-tops.
And others involve improving one's own body: high-protein diets,
vitamin supplements, anabolic steroids, genetic modifications. These
different approaches can be complementary or overlapping: better
diet improves one's capacity to train, and better training improves
one's body and its powers. We intuitively sense, however, that there
may be a difference between, for example, lifting weights, eating
egg whites, and using a graphite tennis racket, just as there appears
to us to be a difference between eating egg whites and taking anabolic
steroids. But if so, understanding the true nature and significance
of these differences is a complex matter, not easily specified.
How do the different means of becoming superior differ from
one another? Is the excellence or superiority of an activity affected
by the way it is done or pursued? Do some ways of improving
performance change the actual character of the activity? If some
performance enhancements are considered "cheating," just who or
what is being cheated-one's competitors, one's fans, oneself, or
the dignity of the activity itself? These are the sorts of questions
we shall try to answer.
C. Different Ways of Enhancing Performance
As already indicated, there are multiple ways to improve athletic
performance, from the elementary to the sophisticated, from the
old to the new. Consider, for example, competitive running. The
ancient Greek runners ran barefoot. Then the use of shoes protected
against injury. Cleats gave greater traction. Better nutrition augmented
general health and energy. Weight training strengthened muscles.
Regimens of practicing wind sprints or fixed-distance runs built
up endurance. Competition during training provided motivation and
experience. Coaching improved mechanics and strategy. High-tech
shoes improved efficiency of motion. Erythropoietin injections increased
oxygen carrying capacity. Anabolic steroids permitted greater weight
training leading to enlarged muscle mass. Stimulant drugs aided
alertness and concentration. Someday, insertion of synthetic muscle-enhancing
genes may make muscles stronger, quicker, and less prone to damage.iv
Where in this sequence of devices to improve running do we acquire
any disquiet regarding the means used? Why, if we are disquieted,
are we bothered?
To prepare for the answers to these questions, let us look more
closely at a number of different ways of improving athletic performance-some
celebrated and some not, some already here and some on the horizon.
They fall generally into three categories: better equipment, better
training, and better native powers.
1. Better Equipment.
Examples of superior performance through better equipment are
ubiquitous. Pole-vaulting used to be done with rigid bamboo poles
and vaults of fifteen feet high seemed virtually superhuman; now
flexible fiberglass poles are used, and vaults go over nineteen
feet. Baseball gloves were once little more than shaped padding
for the hand; now, more than twice their original size, they resemble
small bushel baskets. Curved hockey sticks, replacing the straight
ones, make possible greater puck control and faster shots. Graphite
tennis rackets yield greater racket speed and power. With such equipment
now an accepted part of the sport, used by virtually everyone in
competitive and professional athletics, players who did not use
them would be looked upon as foolish, and they would likely never
make it to the highest levels of competition.
Yet not all performance-enhancing equipment is welcomed into sport.
Corked baseball bats, for example, are believed to permit increased
bat speed and thus hitting power. Yet they are considered an unacceptable
form of cheating and are illegal in professional baseball. Players
who use them are looked down upon by many fans as "cheaters" or
seen as fools for believing they could get such an unfair advantage
without getting caught. Were someone to propose that the rules be
changed, so that everyone could use corked bats, many people would
probably still object. Owing to the importance of history and statistics
in the glamour of baseball and the desire of fans to be able to
make valid comparisons of superior performance across the generations,
their wish to see more home runs does not-at least for now-trump
their wish to preserve the "integrity of the game." Comparing graphite
tennis rackets (which we embrace) and corked baseball bats (which
we decry) suggests how our objections to performance-enhancing equipment
are often conventional, with differences due to traditions, chance
histories, or elective decisions about the rules of the game. Some
of these rules are not matters of principle but of taste, while
others involve particular discernments about what is best for individual
sports that cannot be universalized.
2. Better Training.
Better training can take several forms. It could become more rigorous,
the athlete working harder and longer than he did before or harder
and longer than his teammates or his rivals. Training could be more
effective (better, not necessarily harder), the athlete training
more intelligently or scientifically. And training could be better
coached, the athlete practicing under the guidance of someone with
superior wisdom or know-how regarding nutrition, general fitness,
or specialized skills such as batting or pitching.
All of these forms of improving performance through training proceed
through habituation, practice, and instruction, consciously and
conscientiously undertaken. Yet the effects of the training are
often written into the bodies of the athletes, in the form of increased
strength, longer endurance, greater quickness, improved coordination,
and smoother performance. Similar bodily changes might also be produced
not through active training or active training alone, but by direct
biotechnical intervention into the body of the athlete, seeking
to improve his native capacities by altering his underlying genetic
or biochemical make-up.
3. Better Native Powers.
Direct biological means of improving the powers of our bodies
range from the small and familiar to the large and novel. Least
dramatic are special diets, for example, diets high in protein,
known for decreasing body fat and increasing muscle mass. There
is laser eye surgery to correct imperfect or "low-performing" eyesight,
capable of producing permanent improvements in the patient's vision
with a single treatment. Some prominent athletes (including Tiger
Woods) have used this surgery to get "better-than-normal" eyesight,
a practice that is fully legal and considered by all professional
sports to be an acceptable "enhancement."
More invasive, more controversial, and (for now) illegal in competitive
athletics are the uses of various drugs to enhance performance:
stimulants like amphetamine to produce heightened attention and
quicker reactivity; erythropoietin (EPO) to overproduce red blood
cells and, hence, to augment the body's carrying capacity for oxygen
(so-called "blood doping"); human growth hormone to increase height
or generalized vigor; and anabolic steroids to facilitate training
that will increase overall muscle mass. Off in the future, but already
visible on the drawing board, are prospects of genetic enhancement
of bodily strength and resilience through the insertion into muscles
of genes for erythropoietin or more specific muscle growth factors.
Because so much of athletic excellence is based on strength and
swiftness, the muscle-enhancing technologies are under special scrutiny
by the sports authorities. They are also of special interest to
us. To illustrate how present and prospective biotechnologies can
enhance native bodily powers, we turn next to various technological
approaches to direct muscle enhancement, both pharmacologic and
genetic.
III. MUSCLE ENHANCEMENT THROUGH BIOTECHNOLOGY
A. Muscles and Their Meanings
Our muscles are essential to human life in many ways. They are
central agents of physical strength and speed, attributes admired
and celebrated in most human cultures. All of our motions-from walking,
swimming, and lifting, to writing, chewing, and shaking hands-depend
on them. As basic elements of physicalvigor, they also play
a role in human attractiveness and in our sense of well-being and
even our sense of who we are. Our path through the life cycle is
displayed most vividly in the changes of our musculature.
When we are young, the active use of our muscles in play and in
sports strengthens and develops them. At puberty, production of
estrogen and testosterone enhances these processes, so that the
peak of human muscular development usually occurs between ages 20
and 30. Thereafter, the strength and size of human muscles usually
declines, falling off by about one-third between the ages of 30
and 80.1 As
we age, we gradually lose the ability to dovarious physical tasks,
sometimes in part, sometimes altogether.v
There are, of course, individual variations from this general
pattern. Some people suffer from muscle diseases, often caused by
specific genetic mutations (for example, muscular dystrophy), that
render them unable to develop their muscles to the same extent as
the healthy. Others manage through exercise and fitness training
to maintain peak muscular strength and endurance much longer than
the average. Still others, sedentary and inactive, neglect those
maintenance functions altogether and fall weaker earlier than most.
Muscles do not generate human strength and speed in isolation.
They need to be physically integrated with, and function harmoniously
through their attachments to, nerves, tendons, ligaments, and bones.
While our attention will be on enhancing the activities of muscles
and their cells, this fact reminds us that any biotechnological
intervention that strengthens only muscles may unbalance the interactions
with these other body parts, with serious malfunction as a possible
consequence.
Though not exactly a matter of athletic performance, the perfection
of our musculature and body build is a matter of great concern to
many people intent on improving their body image. Muscles have always
played a prominent role in the idealizations of male human form.
A classical picture of excellence of the youthful male human form
is Michelangelo's sculpture of David, completed around 1504. The
musculature is well developed and well proportioned but without
much articulation of individual muscles; indeed, the integrated
physique points not to itself but to some impending action. Yet
David's strength and power shine through the marble, and leave us
with a mental picture of the classical ideal of muscular development
and proportion, poised for graceful and superior performance.
A more contemporary idealization of the male human form is the
modern bodybuilding champion, such as Arnold Schwarzenegger. Through
specialized weight training, perhaps with the help of anabolic steroids,
all the muscles (especially the biceps and pectoral muscles) become
much larger than those in the statue of David, and the different
groups of skeletal muscles are individually articulated. The picture
is less one of measured and proportionate strength in the service
of splendid activity, more one of "muscle-bound" power, to be admired
for its own sake.vi
Yet although they differ in proportion and muscle articulation,
both the classical and contemporary ideals testify to the importance
of muscles in images of male strength and power.vi
The body's appearance reveals more than a superficial image. As
embodied agents of our innermost will, muscles not only work our
purposes on the world, but make manifest the deep qualities of our
character, our dispositions and intentions, our self-discipline,
self-development, and self-image. We are highly attentive to posture
and motion in others, and muscular actions make possible the communication
and cooperative coordination essential for human society. All of
these qualities are especially evident-and therefore visible for
evaluation-in many forms of athletic performance.
B. Muscle Cell Growth and Development
Scientists have learned a great deal about the cellular structure
and development of skeletal muscles, as well as about how genes
important to muscle cells function and are regulated. The following
brief discussion of muscle cell biology will reveal targets for
biotechnical interventions aimed at improving muscle strength and
resilience.
The major cell type present in skeletal muscle fibers is the multinucleated
myotube, a long cylindrical cell that does the contracting. These
myotubes arise from precursor cells, mononucleated myoblasts, by
means of their fusion with each other and with pre-existing myotubes.
Myoblasts, in turn, are formed by differentiation of a particular
stem cell found in muscle tissue, called a satellite cell.2
The multiplication and differentiation of satellite cells into
myoblasts is regulated by several specific protein growth factors
(primarily insulin-like growth factor 1 [IGF-1] and hepatocyte [liver
cell] growth factor [HGF]). This process is also influenced by hormones
such as growth hormone, testosterone, and estrogen. Growth hormone
secreted by the pituitary acts on the liver to stimulate synthesis
of IGF-1 and its subsequent release into the circulation. (See Figure
1.)
Figure 1. Hormone action and muscle growth
stimulation.
In muscle tissue, IGF-1 binds to specific receptors on the surface
of satellite cells to stimulate their multiplication, producing
both differentiation of satellite cells into myoblasts as well as
more satellite cells. (See Figure 2.)
Figure 2. Schematic diagram of some important
processes in skeletal muscle fiber growth and repair.
Importantly, a slightly different form of IGF-1 (muscle IGF-1
or mIGF-1) is also produced locally in muscle tissue in response
to stretching the muscles during exercise. This form is thought
to act the same way as circulating IGF-1 does in stimulating satellite
cell multiplication and differentiation. However, because mIGF-1
is slightly different in chemical structure from IGF-1 produced
in the liver, mIGF-1 apparently does not enter the circulation,
so its effects can be restricted to promoting growth and repair
of muscle tissue locally.
C. Opportunities and Techniques for Muscle
Enhancement3
We can now see how attempts at muscle enhancement might work.
As has long been known, exercise increases muscle size and strength.
Exercise both transiently damages muscles and, in response, causes
them to increase in size and strength. Exercise (muscle stretch)
increases the production of a specific locally active form of insulin-like
growth factor (mIGF-1), a major mediator of muscle stem cell growth
and differentiation. As a consequence of IGF-induced stimulation,
muscle stem (satellite) cells multiply, differentiate, and fuse.
As a result, the number of muscle fibers increases.
Biotechnological research and development have introduced new
possibilities for producing similar muscle proliferation and enhancement,
both genetic and pharmacological. The genes for animal and human
IGF-1 have been cloned and their DNA sequences determined. Gene
expression vectors have been developed that permit the regulated
production of IGF-1 proteins (both the liver and muscle forms) for
investigation. Thus IGF-1 genes can be introduced into cells and
experimental animals-for example, by means of viral vectors-to determine
the effect of enhanced IGF-1 (or mIGF-1) production on muscle size
and strength. Recent experiments along these lines in animals have
yielded very exciting results.
For example, in experiments described by Barton-Davis and coworkers,4
recombinant virusesviii
containing a rat IGF-1 gene were injected into the anterior compartment
of the rear legs of young mice containing the extensor digitorum
longus (EDL) muscle. The resulting increased production of IGF-1
promoted an average increase of about 15 percent in EDL muscle mass
and strength in young adult mice. Strikingly, such injections led
to a 27 percent increase in the strength of the EDL muscles when
the mice approached the average lifespan of 27 months. In fact,
the continued presence of additional (rat) IGF-1 genes essentially
prevented the decline in muscle size and strength observed in untreated
old mice.ix x
An alternate route to genetic enhancement exploits the ability,
at embryonic stages of development, to create transgenic animals
in which an appropriately regulated foreign gene is expressed throughout
embryonic and adult life. Musaro and his colleagues5
introduced a rat mIGF-1 gene into early-stage mouse embryos, where
it became integrated with mouse chromosomal DNA. The resulting transgenic
mice produced substantial amounts of rat mIGF-1, in addition to
their own mouse IGF-1 and mIGF-1. Embryonic development of these
transgenic mice proceeded normally. Yet as early as ten days after
birth, the skeletal muscles of the transgenic animals were enlarged,
compared to the non-transgenic control mice. Moreover, the skeletal
muscle enlargement persisted as the transgenic mice aged. Whereas,
in unmodified (wild type) mice, muscle size and strength peaked
around six months and decreased considerably by twenty months of
age, the size and strength of skeletal muscle in the transgenic
mice (containing rat mIGF-1) remained stable at peak levels for
up to twenty months.xi
These and other experimental results stimulate thoughts about
possible extensions of these approaches to humans. They hold out
the promise of treatments for various diseases of muscle tissue,
for sarcopenia and the weaknesses of old age, and for generalized
enhancement of muscle strength and fitness in people of all ages,
diseased or not. Based on our current understanding, at least three
different approaches could be considered. First, one could introduce
muscle-enhancing genes directly into the muscles themselves. To
do so, one would need to develop recombinant virus vectors containing
the human mIGF-1 gene, under the control of appropriate regulatory
elements that would limit its expression to muscle cells near the
site of injection. Alternatively, one might introduce an appropriately
regulated mIGF-1 gene into human embryos, as was done in the experiments
with mice. Finally, one might use an approach that combined techniques
of stem cell and genetic engineering. After isolating and expanding
human muscle stem (satellite) cells in vitro, one could introduce
an appropriately regulated human mIGF-1 gene into those cells and
then transplant the genetically modified satellite cells back into
the muscles of the person being treated.
None of these three approaches has yet been tried in human beings.
Each has its advantages and disadvantages.xii
Developing any one of them would take a lot of time and money, and
many technical and logistical problems would need to be overcome
before any treatment could be applied on a large scale. Even before
the first genetic treatments to increase muscle size and strength
could be tried in humans in the United States, the Food and Drug
Administration (FDA) would require demonstrations that the proposed
treatment is safe and effective.
Nevertheless, the time may be coming soon for human trials using
the first approach, undertaken not to bulk up aspiring athletes
but to treat human muscle diseases. Clinical trials of regulated
mIGF-1 gene delivery as a treatment for specific forms of muscular
dystrophy may begin within the next several years.6
These clinical trials will likely provide crucial data, en route,
on administration, optimal dose, and possible side effects. If efficacy
is demonstrated and side effects are small, one can easily imagine
the social and economic factors that will favor vast expansions
in the use of genetic muscle treatments to enhance muscle size and
strength. High school wrestling and football coaches, having learned
of the enhancing gene transfer experiments in rats and mice, have
already expressed interest in obtaining such treatments for their
athletes. Developing a product for which the eventual potential
market is up to 100 percent of the human population will be hard
to resist.
Genetic treatments for increasing muscle size and strength are
still in the future. But pharmacological means of doing so are already
here and in use, and both the desire and the rationale for their
use is clear. As noted earlier, various hormones and growth factors
play key roles in stimulating muscle stem cells to multiply, differentiate
into myoblasts, and then fuse with existing muscle fibers. Growth
hormone levels influence the size and strength of muscles, perhaps
through the intermediacy of IGF-1. Testosterone levels influence
muscle size and strength, helping to explain why men's muscles are
generally larger and stronger than women's. Finally, local growth
factors like mIGF-1 have important effects as well.
At the present time, three different sorts of drugs are being
used to increase (or try to increase) muscle strength. In the newest
practice, still on a very small scale, people have begun to use
human growth hormone in attempts to enhance muscle size and strength,
especially in the elderly. Now that the patent on human growth hormone
has expired (2002), the cost of the monthly hormone injections is
likely to drop from its steep $1,000. If this occurs, the scale
of growth hormone use might very likely increase, as promotion for
new uses grows; over the past year, unsolicited e-mail advertisements
for human growth hormone have come frequently to the e-mail boxes
of Council staff.xiii
Competitive athletes (and others) interested in boosting muscle
size and performance have started using growth hormone-though the
data suggest that its effectiveness is uncertain.7
A second approach to the enhancement of muscle performance works
indirectly, not by enlarging muscle size but by increasing muscle
endurance. Known as blood doping, it was originally accomplished
by drawing blood from athletes, separating and concentrating the
red blood cells, and then re-infusing the red blood cells into the
athletes' bloodstream. This raised the amount of hemoglobin (the
oxygen-binding protein) in the blood, and thus increased the oxygen-carrying
capacity of the blood. Much the same effect can now be obtained
by injections of the synthetic protein hormone erythropoietin, which
stimulates the body to increase its production of red blood cells.
For competitive cyclists, swimmers, and long-distance runners, increased
oxygen-carrying capacity in the blood makes possible increased endurance,
which in turn improves competitive performance.
The most commonly used chemical means of muscle enhancement are
the anabolic steroids, chemical compounds related to hormones like
testosterone. Taken orally (for example, "Anadrol" [oxymetholone],
"Winstrol" [stanozolol], or "THG" [tetrahydrogestrinone]), or by
injection (for example, "Durabolin" [nandrolone] or "Equipoise"
[boldenone]), these drugs facilitate bodybuilding. Used in combination
with weight training and special diets, they can greatly increase
muscle size and strength. It is true that the precise benefits of
these drugs for athletic performance are in dispute among scientific
researchers, and, for obvious reasons, we have not seen adequate
controlled studies to clarify their true effects. Nevertheless,
many athletes, trusting their own experience and the testimony of
teammates, are not waiting for the scientific evidence. Despite
the known health risks and despite official opposition from the
professional and college athletic authorities, as information about
their effects has diffused throughout American society, more and
more professional and amateur athletes are apparently using them.
Also believing that they are effective-and that they are dangerous
to the athletes-anti-doping sport organizations have banned most
of them. At the same time, many (including the ones listed above)
are listed as available for sale on the Internet.
Despite the opposition of Olympic and other sports officials to
their use, the public attitude toward steroid use by athletes may
be changing, at least for sports like baseball, basketball, and
football. The recent outcry regarding Sammy Sosa's corked bat seemed
to exceed any protests against the multiple revelations of steroid
use by professional athletes. Malcolm Gladwell suggests an explanation:
We have come to prefer a world where the distractible take Ritalin,
the depressed take Prozac, and the unattractive get cosmetic surgery
to a world ruled, arbitrarily, by those fortunate few who were
born focused, happy and beautiful. Cosmetic surgery is not "earned"
beauty, but then natural beauty isn't earned, either. One of the
principal contributions of the late twentieth century was the
moral deregulation of social competition-the insistence that advantages
derived from artificial and extraordinary intervention are no
less legitimate than the advantages of nature. All that athletes
want, for better or worse, is the chance to play by those same
rules.8
(Emphasis added.)
It is hard to predict how widely genetic and chemical agents of
muscle enhancement would be used, especially should safer versions
be developed. Given the popularity of bodybuilding and fitness today,
one could imagine that biotechnical agents would be useful for enhancing
these activities, both in competitive and non-competitive settings.
The commercial and competitive pressuresto use genetic muscle
treatments to build up, maintain, and repair the muscles of competitive
professional athletes in all sports would surely be very strong.
And since athletic competition extends down from professional and
collegiate ranks to youth soccer and Little League, there would
seem to be no place to draw a line against using (safe) genetic
or chemical muscle treatments. The incentive to use these treatments
during adolescence or young adulthood might increase considerably
if it should turn out that treatment during these earlier times
of life is also the best means of protecting against the sarcopenia
of old age.
Thus, it is not too farfetched to imagine that parents may one
day be faced with difficult decisions regarding the development
of their children's bodily capacities for athletics. What will and
should they do when daughter Jenny's soccer coach tells them she
would be a stronger player if they got her genetic muscle treatments,
or that she is more likely to make the team if she gets treated?
Would untreated children or aspiring athletes become significantly
disadvantaged in a society in which many others had genetic or chemical
muscle treatments? Conversely, would these new technologies at last
provide the remedy for those to whom nature dealt a weaker bodily
constitution? Given the difficulty of setting principled limits
between the therapeutic uses of these new biotechnical powers and
the uses that go "beyond therapy," why might we still seek to set
any limits at all?xiv
What is it that such limits would or should seek to defend? It is
none too soon to begin to think about these questions, for the future
that will make them anything but speculative is now visible on the
horizon.
IV. ETHICAL ANALYSIS
To begin the ethical analysis, we must try to distinguish between
different ways of achieving superior performance, and how these
ways of becoming better might alter, enhance, corrupt, or perfect
our different activities. For those performance enhancements that
we embrace, are we so sure that they are improvements, if we understand
"improvement" to mean enhancing performance in ways that serve,
rather than call into question, the dignity or excellence of human
activity? And for those performance enhancements that trouble us,
what is the nature of our disquiet? Because we want to see the bigger
picture, we deliberately take a general approach to these questions,
not tying our analysis to any specific means of boosting muscle
strength and athletic performance. Rather than spend time on issues
peculiar to a particular technique-say, the special safety concerns
of genetic transfer, as contrasted with those associated with growth
hormone or steroid use-we will concentrate on the larger issues
raised by our acquiring and using the new bodily powers that these
techniques, each in its own way, supply or promote.
A. How Is Biotechnical Enhancement Different?
The first task is to try to figure out whether using biotechnological
means to gain superior performance is different from using better
equipment or engaging in better training. If it is, what might the
differences be, and what ethical and social difference do they make?
This task is more difficult than it might at first glance seem,
for there are similarities as well as differences among these three
approaches. Some analysts will try to use such similarities to dismiss
expressions of concern regarding drug-mediated improvements: "How
are steroids really different from Air Jordan basketball shoes?
Special diets and drugs both increase the capacity to train, so
why make such a fuss about the drugs?" In response, it is worth
emphasizing in advance that the ethical evaluation of biotechnological
enhancements does not finally depend on their being found utterly
unique and unprecedented. The fact that taking anabolic steroids
or using genetic muscle enhancers could resemble, in some respects,
using special diets or special bodybuilding programs does not by
itself dissolve all our moral concerns. On the contrary, it might
lead us to think more deeply about the more familiar modes of seeking
to promote superior performance. Moreover, as we shall see, a careful
examination may reveal that, similarities notwithstanding, the differences
are in fact humanly and ethically significant.
In many areas of life, including sports, we take for granted that
better equipment makes for better performance. Better gadgets, tools,
machines, and devices are both yesterday's news and tomorrow's headlines.
We habitually think and act in ways that assume the existence of
such equipment, and in many areas of life, we work endlessly and
deliberately to make cutting-edge improvements in our "high-performance
gear." Unlike training or drugs that change the agent directly,
the equipment that boosts our performance does so indirectly, yet
it does so quite openly and in plain sight. We can see how the springier
running shoes, the lighter tennis racket, and the bigger baseball
glove enable their users to go faster, hit harder, and reach the
formerly unreachable-yet without apparently changing them in their
persons or native powers.
Yet appearances are deceiving. That their effects on our performance
are indirect does not mean that they are trivial. And that they
remain but visible tools in our hands does not mean that we remain
in fact unaltered. Although the alterations, unlike the tools that
produce them, are often hard to see, they often go very deep. Not
only do we think and act in ways that assume enhanced equipment,
we come to take its use for granted. Not only do we come to rely
on our better tools; after a while, we have trouble remembering
that we could do without them, largely because in truth we cannot
do without them. This is not to suggest that we should do
without them or that there is something wrong with accepting the
extra edge that they give us in our pursuit of excellence. It is
merely to insist that the use of equipment in sports, as in the
rest of life, changes and even binds the human users, often without
their knowing it.
The point was beautifully made by Rousseau, commenting on how
even the earliest human inventors of artful aids to better living
"imposed a yoke on themselves without thinking about it":
For, besides their continuing thus to soften body and mind,
as these commodities had lost almost all their pleasantness through
habit, and as they had at the same time degenerated into true
needs, being deprived of them became much more cruel than
possessing them was sweet; and people were unhappy to lose them
without being happy to possess them.9
(Emphasis added.)
Our gear (like all our technology) not only improves the way we
do things. In the process, it also often changes the very things
that we do. It changes the abilities that matter most, and thus
the character of our aspirations and the economy of social rewards.
Once again, this is not to suggest we should not seek further improvements
in our equipment. It is merely to recognize the far-reaching changes,
in us and our activities, that the "merely" external equipment can
cause-in all that we do, not only in sports. Because of graphite
tennis rackets, tennis today is a game of faster serves, stronger
strokes, and shorter points, and in consequence requires players
of different talents and demeanor than it did only decades ago.
Similarly, because of precision-guided weapons and drones, warfare
now requires a different and more technical kind of expertise, often
less demanding of, and less rewarding to, the physical human powers
that served best in hand-to-hand combat. And because of computers,
there is a premium on those with habits of mind shaped for programming;
indeed, the very way many people think, speak, and write has changed
to fit with the possibilities and necessities of the computer age.
Adapting Winston Churchill's sage remark about architecture, we
might say that we shape our equipment and our equipment shapes us.xv
The distinction between better equipment and better training,
and even between better equipment and better native powers, is for
additional reasons not as sharp as one might wish. For some forms
of athletic (and other) equipment are developed not to enhance specific
performance as such, but rather to help individuals change or improve
themselves precisely through better practice or training. For example,
state-of-the-art weight training equipment aims at allowing individuals
to make themselves stronger weightlifters and linebackers; state-of-the-art
flight simulators allow individuals to make themselves better pilots.
Such equipment is a tool that explicitly enables us to change ourselves
through our own activity; it is an indirect means to directed and
chosen change. Moreover-and more profoundly-the line between person
and equipment may be eroding: we already have such therapeutic interventions
as artificial limbs and mechanical implants to help blind people
to see and deaf people to hear. Mechanical implants of various other
kinds are no longer matters merely for science fiction.
Nevertheless, as with night and day in relation to twilight, the
blurring of the boundaries between the several approaches does not
make the territories themselves indistinct. We can still separate
in our mind those means of altering or improving performance that
work by giving us tools to perform in new ways, and those interventions
that work by changing us directly-whether through self-directed
activity and training or through direct biological interventions
in the human body and mind. We can distinguish using better sneakers
from daily running practice for an upcoming race, and both of these
from running the race with the benefit of EPO or steroids. In addition,
even though our tools change us, they do not necessarily change
us irreversibly. We can, if we wish, still try to play baseball
with the small, soft gloves of yesteryear, or softball with no gloves
at all. Despite the fuzziness at the boundary, it still makes sense
to distinguish our tools and equipment from our practice or training,
as well as from the more direct biotechnical interventions aimed
at improving our native bodily capacities.
In athletics, as in so many other areas of human life, practice
and training are the most important means for improving performance,
and superior performance is most generally attained through better
training: the direct improvement of the specific powers and abilities
of the human agent at-work-in-the-world, by means of his self-conscious
or self-directed effort, exercise, and activity. To train is to
be at work: striving, seeking, pushing, laboring, and developing.
It requires self-knowledge or external guidance about the ends worth
seeking, and it requires the desire and discipline to pursue those
ends through one's own effort. And, most importantly for our purposes,
training means acquiring by practice and effort improvements in
the very powers and abilities that training uses. One gets
to run faster by running; one builds up endurance by enduring; one
increases one's strength by using it on ever-increasing burdens.
The capacity to be improved is improved by using it; the deed
to be perfected is perfected by doing it.
This insight has some important implications. First, it calls
our attention to the very real differences in our natural endowments.
If improving through training proceeds as described, certain native
abilities are often a prerequisite. In many cases, no amount of
training can overcome the unchangeable shortcomings of natural gifts.
Second, and more important for present purposes, the source of our
different endowments may be mysterious, but our active cultivation
of those endowments, whether great or small, is intelligible: we
can understand the connection between effort and improvement, between
activity and experience, between work and result.
This leads to an important difference between improvements made
through training and improvements gained through bioengineering.
When and if we use our mastery of biology and biotechnology to alter
our native endowments-whether to make the best even better or the
below- average more equal-we paradoxically make improvements to
our performance less intelligible, in the sense of being less connected
to our own self-conscious activity and exertion. The improvements
we might once have made through training alone, we now make only
with the assistance of artfully inserted IGF-1 genes or anabolic
steroids. Though we might be using rational and scientific means
to remedy the mysterious inequality or unchosen limits of our native
gifts, we would in fact make the individual's agency less
humanly or experientially intelligible to himself.
The IGF-1-using or steroid-using athlete surely improves: he (or
she) develops and becomes superior-and certainly the scientist who
produced the biological agents of such improvement can understand
in scientific terms the genetic workings or physiochemical processes
that make it possible. But from the athlete's perspective, he improves
as if by "magic," without the self-conscious or self-directed activity
that lies at the heart of better training. True, steroids (or, someday,
genetic muscle enhancement) will enable him to perform at a higher
level only if he continues to train. True, as he trains, he still
tires, perspires, and feels his (altered) body at-work. But as the
athlete himself can surely attest, the changes in his body are decisively
(albeit not solely) owed to the pills he has popped or the shots
he has taken, interventions whose relation to the changes he undergoes
are utterly opaque to his direct human experience. He has the advantage
of the mastery of modern biology, but he risks a partial alienation
from his own doings, as his identity increasingly takes shape at
the "molecular" rather than the experiential level. Indeed, the
athlete's likely embarrassment proves the point: Even were steroids
or stimulants to become legal, one imagines that most athletes would
rather not be seen taking their injections right before the race.
For there is something shameful about revealing one's own chemical
dependence right before demonstrating what is supposed to be one's
own personal excellence.
This is not to suggest that changes in the body produced through
training and effort are not also molecular, or to ignore the fact
that the very purpose of certain biochemical interventions (such
as anabolic steroids) is to increase the individual's capacity to
train. In expressing this uneasiness about biotechnical enhancement,
we are not celebrating some fictitious agency divorced from bodily
events and consequences: whenever the body works or is at work,
the body's underlying biology changes. Neither are we casting doubts
on efforts to improve the body by means that work on it directly;
to do so would require us to cast doubts on all of medicine and
surgery, not to mention a well-ordered diet. Yet on the plane
of human experience and understanding, there is a difference
between changes in our bodies that proceed through self-direction
and those that do not, and between changes that result from our
putting our bodies to work and those that result from having our
bodies "worked on" by others or altered directly. This is a real
difference, one whose importance for the ethical analysis, as we
shall see later, may prove decisive.
Yet in trying to preserve the distinction between intelligible
agency and unintelligible agency-between getting better because
of "what we do" and getting better because of "what is done to us"-we
face a dilemma. Many of the basic activities of life-for example,
eating, breathing, and sleeping-transform our bodies without our
directing the actual work of transformation. Eating the right foods
makes our system work better. Science can come to understand why
this is so-why protein is "good" and fats are "bad," or how our
bodies break them down and to what effect. But these processes of
the body, however well understood, can never be made experientially
intelligible in the same way our self-directed activities are intelligible.
We digest and we dance, but digesting and dancing are very differently
our doings.
We can control the food we eat, but improving our native digestion
through practice is beyond our power. We dance by choice, both immediately
and self-consciously, with the movements of the body connected to
our active desire to dance and our self-awareness of dancing. Over
time we can see our dancing improve, at least within the limits
of our native capacities, and we can see that it is through our
own practice that the superior performance has occurred. Clearly,
as with eating, what happens in our bodies as we become better dancers
is invisible and mysterious at the organic and molecular levels;
it is intelligible, if at all, only in the terms of science, not
of human experience. But the lived experience of dancing-of doing
the deeds that enable us to do them again and do them better-matters
a great deal. When we dance, our improvements are "our own," made
possible by and limited by our native biology, but still the result
of our own self-directed activity.
And here we begin to understand the complexity: To be a human
organism, possessed of a body all of whose activities are mediated
by invisible and molecular events, means that our identity is always
to some degree independent of all our self-conscious efforts to
mold or control it. In important ways, our bodily identity and our
bodily capacities are inborn, inherited, and "given," and much of
what our bodies do thereafter is shaped by processes and in ways
we do not direct or fully grasp at the level of inner human experience.
We cannot make our bodies into just anything we like, no matter
how hard we try. As human individuals, we are not simply the beings
or persons that we will ourselves to be, precisely because
we are biological beings-with finite capacities and a finite body,
which make having an identity possible in the first place. And yet,
if there are limits to what we can do, there are also possibilities.
We can actively change our bodies and change ourselves in important
ways, precisely by trying, doing, working, and performing the very
activities we seek to do better.
Even in the most self-directed activities, we remain ignorant,
on the level of experience, of what is transpiring chemically in
our bodies. This fact has an important implication: The difference
between improving the body through training and improving it through
diet or drugs is not absolute but a matter of degree. Nevertheless,
the fact that the difference is one merely of degree does not make
it humanly insignificant. Some acts are more, and some acts are
less "our own" as human and as individuals. When we seek superior
performance through better training, the way our body works
and our experience and understanding of our own body at work
are more closely aligned. With interventions that bypass human experience
to work their biological "magic" directly-from better nutrition
to steroids to genetic muscle enhancements-our silent bodily workings
and our conscious agency are more alienated from one another.
The central question becomes: Which biomedical interventions for
the sake of superior performance are consistent with (even favorable
to) our full flourishing as human beings, including our flourishing
as active, self-aware, self-directed agents? And, conversely, when
is the alienation of biological process from active experience dehumanizing,
compromising the lived humanity of our efforts and thus making our
superior performance in some way false-not simply our own, not fully
human? Better nutrition seems an obvious good, a way of improving
our bodily functioning that serves human flourishing without compromising
the "personal" nature or individual agency of what we do with our
healthy, well-nourished bodies. But moving outward from there, the
puzzle gets more complicated. Where in the progression of possible
biological interventions do we lose in our humanity or identity
more than we gain in our "performance"? Is there a way to distinguish
coffee and caffeine pills to keep us awake from Modafinil to enable
us to avoid sleep entirely for several days, from amphetamines to
keep us more alert and focused, from human growth hormone, steroids,
and EPO to improve strength and endurance, from genetic modifications
that make such biological interventions more direct and more lasting?
All of them alter our bodily workings; all of them to varying degrees
separate self-directed experience from underlying biology.
Does that mean that we are incapable of distinguishing among them,
humanly and ethically? Can our disquiet about pharmacological and
genetic enhancement withstand rational scrutiny? More deeply, what
does the prospect of such interventions tell us about the nature
of human activity and the meaning of human identity? These are perhaps
the deepest questions for the ethical analysis that follows. But
to see why this is so, we must first consider some more familiar
sources of ethical disquiet.
B. Fairness and Equality
The most obvious disquiet with performance-enhancing agents in
athletics, both equipment like corked bats and biological interventions
like steroids, stimulants, or future genetic muscle boosters, concerns
fairness: the worry that players using them will have an unfair
advantage over other players, the concern that injustice will be
perpetrated against one's rivals. Games have rules, and breaking
the rules in these ways undermines the fairness of competition and
the dignity of the game. This is, of course, a proper concern. But
the question of fairness is more complicated than it looks at first.
Athletics, like many other human activities, depend on native
gifts that are unequally distributed. Indeed, human sport often
highlights and celebrates the very real differences and inequalities
in our biological "starting points." In most sports, we do not,
in the name of equality, require that our athletes (or others) with
special talents assume handicaps so that everyone might compete
on an equal footing.xvi
Although we may never settle the ancient and complicated question
about how much of our various achievements is due to "nature" and
how much to "nurture," there is no question but that gifts of nature
have much to do with all sorts of human excellence. Many individuals,
lacking certain physical and mental attributes (for example, height,
muscle potential, eye-hand coordination), will never achieve the
highest levels of human performance in certain activities no matter
how hard they strive. At the same time, nature is hardly the whole
story. Many individuals, with more limited native powers, will outperform
those who are less willing or less able to cultivate their superior
gifts.
Some have argued that allowing performance-enhancing drugs would
be an acceptable-or even desirable-means of leveling a playing field
that is unequal by nature. It could make athletic competition more
perfectly fair, allowing winners to become those who do the
best rather than those who are the best. But others argue
that such drugs would only exacerbate the naturally unequal endowments
rather than correct them. For even were there to be an "enhancement
commissar" who calculated what degree of "boost" each person needed
in order to get even with the natively gifted, there would be no
way to titrate all the relevant gifts.xvii
Besides, in a free country there would be no basis for denying the
same performance-enhancers also to the more talented. Why, if they
wish it, should those destined to be tall or bulky be refused a
chance to become taller or bulkier through growth hormone? As a
result, those who are "best by nature" would become even better
by augmenting nature's gifts with biological enhancements. And whether
we allow or disallow such enhancements, we are not likely to alter
the inherent biological inequalities that are part of being human,
and that are important for human excellence in sports and many other
activities. Fairness is always limited, to some degree, by the mysterious
gifts of nature, even if such gifts are not solely responsible or
even decisive for who will in the end become excellent or who will
perform excellently.
The inequality of natural endowments highlights a related dilemma
regarding the standards of excellence: to what extent should we
judge performances superior for being "the best they can be," rather
than simply being the "best"? For example, we celebrate both the
real Olympics, which measures the best of the best, and the Special
Olympics, which measures the best of those who strive in spite of
great natural disadvantages. In the real Olympics, we honor the
best human runner, and we appreciate the fact that the excellence
of human running is not relative; it can be truthfully and quantitatively
measured. At the same time, we judge the Special Olympians according
to a different standard. We regard their activity as a kind of excellence-of
personal achievement rather than of absolutely superior performance-even
as they compete in the same activity with much lower scores. Standards
of excellence also change with the times. In some sports, the average
professional athlete of today probably has better scores and more
physical strength than the greatest champions of yesteryear. But
which of these individuals-today's no-name or yesterday's giant-do
we judge as "superior" or more excellent?
In sum, there seems to be an "absolute" dimension to human excellence:
in certain activities, there is such a thing as the best human performance.
And yet, judging human excellence also depends on making sense of
nature's unequal allotment of gifts, as well as the way particular
human activities, for various reasons, change over time. We need
to fit our scales of excellence to the thing being weighed, resisting
the twin errors of believing that all excellence is relative or
that all excellence can simply be ranked and determined by "score."
Still, there is a danger of sentimentality, as well as of confused
thinking, in admiring athletes largely for the excellence of extra
effort. The perfectly fitting praise of the resolve, effort, and
devotion necessary to perform in the face of serious handicap is
praise more for human will and determination, less for superior
performance as such. As we shall emphasize below, human performance
humanly done does involve human intention, choice, and will; yet
it would be strange to celebrate mainly human willfulness in activities
such as athletics that display, above all, bodily grace
and beauty. This observation suggests that, in athletics, it
is the harmonious and seemingly seamless fusion of mind and body
that is crucial to the athletic ideal of superior performance. Neither
the human body regarded as mere animal, nor the human body regarded
as recalcitrant slave to be whipped into shape by an unbending will,
but the human being displaying in visibly beautiful action the workings
of heart, mind, and body united as inseparably as the concave and
the convex-that, as we shall argue shortly, is the heart of humanly
superior performance.
Finally, at least in sports, fairness understood as "playing by
the rules" is a matter of convention. When it comes to steroids,
EPO, or corked baseball bats, the concern about unfair advantage
is to a large degree self-created. It is only because these performance-enhancing
agents are disallowed, and because those who use them must do so
outside the rules and surreptitiously, that we regard their use
as unfair. But if steroids were declared legal in competition, everybody
(or nearly everybody) who desired to compete at the highest level
in most sports might well use them. The problem of fairness of access
and extra advantage would largely disappear-though the problem of
natural inequality would remain. It is therefore not enough to defend
the rules (no steroids, no corked bats) and decry those who break
them. The rules themselves-why they exist and what they are defending-must
be understood and supported. This must be done on grounds that go
beyond equality and fairness toward others to the nature and meaning
of the activity itself.
C. Coercion and Social Pressure
A second source of disquiet centers on issues of freedom and coercion,
both overt and subtle. The pride most nations (and schools) take
in their athletes is often far from benign, and there are well-known
cases in which countries and coaches have forced athletes to use
performance-enhancing drugs. In East Germany before the fall of
communism, to take just a single example, the young members of the
women's Olympic swim team took regular doses of the anabolic steroid
known as Oral-Turinabol. This improved their strength and endurance,
but it also caused terrible masculinizing side effects (severe acne,
uncontrollable libido, gruff voices, abnormal hair growth). Those
women who were brave enough to inquire about what they were taking
were told that the drugs were simply "vitamin tablets." As one of
the swimmers testified years later: "I was fifteen years old when
the pills started. . . . The training motto at the pool was, 'You
eat the pills, or you die.' It was forbidden to refuse."10
But the potential for coercion-or at least intense social pressure-is
certainly not limited to tyrannical regimes and despotic coaches.
Should the use of an enhancing agent become normal and widespread,
anyone who wished to excel in a given activity, from athletics to
academics, might "need" to use the same (or better) performance-enhancements
in order to "keep up." Anecdotal evidence suggests that this "soft
coercion" may already be a problem, given the widespread underground
use of illegal substances in many professional sports. True, the
individual users, in such circumstances, are still choosing the
drugs for themselves. They are free in a way the East German swimmers
were not. But their choice is constrained by the fact-or by the
belief-that it would be impossible to compete, or compete on an
equal playing field, without them. They see the alternative of not
using them as a kind of "unilateral disarmament," virtually guaranteeing
that only those individuals with every biological advantage would
excel or succeed. In professional sports, where not only victory
but big money is at stake, the pressures not to disarm oneself pharmacologically
will be-are already-enormous.
The point can be generalized beyond athletics, and when this is
done, we see additional reasons for concern. In a meritocratic and
results-oriented society such as ours, the vast numbers of people
caught up in the race "to get ahead" come to feel increasing pressures
to enhance their performance. Most are probably moved less by the
desire for excellence, more by the love of gain or the wish to beat
out the next fellow. As mounting social and economic competition
keeps ratcheting up the pressures, people look for any advantage
that might win them the more lucrative or higher-status job or that
would increase their children's chances of gaining admission to
the more prestigious schools. Under these social conditions, with
spiraling love of gain conjoined with rising demand for recognition,
the temptation in all walks of life to use biotechnologies for some
"extra edge" probably rises with the pressure to compete. Today,
professional athletes-and those who dream of becoming professional
athletes-often succumb to the temptation. Tomorrow, the same might
be true in many other areas of human endeavor.
Yet these quite legitimate concerns about pressure and constraint
must be examined more closely. For the fact is that athletic (and
other) competition is, in important ways, constraining or pressure-filled
by nature. By becoming better, our opponents force us to match their
improvements or fall behind and fail. By the entirely accepted (and
generally laudable) means of training, dieting, or superior coaching,
they challenge us to meet or better their improvements. Moreover,
the quest for excellence, even in activities (like music or ballet)
that are not in essence competitive, typically comes with stiff
demands, and anyone who is serious about superior performance has
little choice but to yield to or embrace them. The question therefore
becomes: Which demands and "necessities" of the pursuit of superior
performance are defensible and which are not? Which serve human
excellence and which compromise or undermine it?
Seen most clearly, the concern about coercion, as with equality
and fairness, turns out to be a pointer to other and deeper concerns,
concerns about what gives an individual performer his or her dignity,
and what makes an individual performance humanly excellent. If there
is a core difficulty here, it is with the biological enhancers themselves,
not with the fact that individuals might feel constrained or compelled
to use them.
D. Adverse Side Effects: Health, Balance,
and the Whole of Life
One of the central concerns about the biotechnical agents themselves
is the risk and reality of adverse and undesirable "side effects,"
in the first instance, on bodily health and safety. The unintended
cost of seeking stronger muscles and superior performance through
drugs or genetic engineering could well be bodily (or mental) harm.
With drugs like steroids, the grave long-term health risks are well
known: they include, among others, liver tumors, fluid retention,
high blood pressure, infertility, premature cessation of growth
in adolescents, and psychological effects from excessive mood swings
to drug dependence. With looming biotechnical powers like genetic
muscle enhancement, the side effects are for now uncertain. But
until proven otherwise, it makes sense to follow this prudent maxim:
No biological agent powerful enough to achieve major changes in
body or mind is likely to be entirely safe or without side effects.
Moreover, targeted interventions aimed at enhancing normally functioning
capacities, not repairing broken parts, could produce lopsided "improvements"
that throw whole systems out of kilter: monster muscles could threaten
unenhanced bones and ligaments.
The concern about safety is a real one: to be an athlete should
not mean accepting a sentence of premature death or serious disease
or disability, later if not sooner. As admirers of athletes, we
should not want to exploit those we most esteem; we should not want
to use them up for our own entertainment and satisfaction; and we
should not want to treat our fellow human beings as expendable animals.
But the concern about safety must also be subjected to scrutiny.
Athletic activity is often intrinsically unsafe: Boxing and football,
hockey and skiing-such activities require daring, toughness, and
sometimes even contempt for "mere safety" as being far less important
than victory and achievement. Superior performances in these activities
would be less excellent or less genuine if fully stripped of their
perils. Inasmuch as risk and sacrifice are part of what it takes
to be superior, one might even argue that an athlete's willingness
to use such drugs, at so great a personal cost, is not dehumanizing
but admirable-a sacrifice of oneself to the game one loves.
Of course, there seems to be a difference between the uncertain
dangers of the playing field and the deliberately self-inflicted
harm of using performance-enhancing drugs.Playing a game with the
risk of great harm seems different from inflicting high-tech, premeditated,
long-term damage on oneself to gain a short-term advantage. The
hazards intrinsic to the game are generally unavoidable, while those
associated with taking the drugs are utterly unnecessary. But again,
we must wonder: Why should we value the long-term over the short-term-the
long healthy life over the short and glorious one? Isn't part of
our admiration for athletics precisely the "gladiator spirit,"including
the willingness to forego "mere safety" for brief but memorablemoments
on the field of glory? Absent further analysis, there would seem
to be a potential nobility on the part of the athlete who seeks
excellence at whateverpersonal cost. And yet, there also seems to
be something perverse, or ignoble, in coming deliberately to abuse
one's body for the sake, presumably, of showing off its beautiful
and splendid gifts and activities. There seems to be something dehumanizing
in coming to rely so heavily on one's chemist to excel, to the point
where one might wonder whether such excellence is still "personal"
at all.
Some enhancements, both here and coming, may become physically
safe, with few side effects that compromise the long-term health
of those who use them. Yet there are other consequences "to the
side" that deserve our concern, for such enhancements might change
the body or mind in ways beyond making them ill. For it stands to
reason that drugs sufficiently capable of affecting us in ways we
desire are likely to affect us in ways that we do not seek and cannot
predict. Perhaps certain hormones that boost training capacity and
aggressiveness will make the individual emotionally less "well-balanced"
in everyday life. Or perhaps by taking drugs that increase tolerance
for physical pain, the individual will decrease his or her experience
of other physical pleasures. Part of the problem with certain biological
enhancements, in other words, may be that they isolate one set of
human powers-the powers that make for a superior runner, linebacker,
or weight lifter-at the expense of other areas of life: health,
to be sure, but also calmness, balance, equanimity, pleasure, creativity,
and so forth. Such enhancements risk creating a distorted form of
human excellence-magnifying certain elements of human life while
shrinking others.
But the "distortions" of life in pursuit of superior performance
cannot be blamed on biotechnical enhancers alone. In any society
in which people feel driven by the desire for success, whether measured
in terms of wealth, power, or status, many human activities (including
athletics) are easily bent out of their natural shape in order to
serve these external goals. Yet the difficulty exists even when
superior performance is pursued not for outside ends but for its
own sake. All human excellence, to some degree, requires at least
some distortion: putting aside many activities or aspirations to
excel in one; leaving several powers undeveloped to develop a few;
sacrificing most human goods to pursue a single one at the highest
level; and perhaps becoming so excellent in one particular area
of human endeavor that most other human beings only encounter such
superior performance at a distance. All excellence, in other words,
requires at least some separation from the majority: the separation
required by long hours of practice and the separation inherent in
performing in the arena or on the stage. We need think only of the
strange life lived by Olympic gymnasts, often whisked away from
normal childhood at a very early age to enter the all-consuming
world of the training camp. Or the women's Olympic volleyball teams
that not only practice but live in camp together 365 days a year
for nearly the entire four years between the quadrennial events.
Sometimes this separation from others and from ordinary life enables
individuals to embody the best that human beings are capable of,
at least in a particular area of activity. At other times, the separation
might be so severe, and the way we pursue our chosen activity so
distorting of the human whole, that the dignity of the performer
is called into question. He or she might be a great athlete, but
only by becoming inhuman in other ways. Viewed more fully, the concern
about side effects, beginning with health, gets us to the deepest
matters and the greatest "side effect" of all: that we improve performance
at the cost of our full humanity; that we become "better" by no
longer fully being ourselves.
E. The Dignity of Human Activity
The preceding analysis has considered several sources of our disquiet
about different technical and biotechnological agents that might
enhance or alter athletic performance: unfairness and inequality,
coercion and constraint, and adverse effects on the health and balance
of human life. Each has indicated something important; but none
gets us to the core issue. The problem is not simply inequality
and unfairness, since our natural endowments are unequal to begin
with, and the conventions outlawing certain enhancements could be
changed to allow everyone equal access to the same technical and
biotechnological advantages. The problem is not simply coercive
pressure, since only if there is something intrinsically troubling
about bioengineered enhancements should we be really troubled by
the pressures to use them, especially given that "pressures" are
inherent in the pursuit of athletic or any other kind of excellence.
And the problem is not simply health hazards and adverse side effects,
or the ways that enhancing certain human capacities might limit
or endanger other elements of human life. For the pursuit of athletic
(and other) excellences necessarily seeks something higher than
mere safety, and excellence nearly always requires putting aside
some aspirations to pursue others; the individual accepts less excellence
in many aspects of life in order to be excellent in this one. Yet
the concern about compromising the whole of life for the sake of
one isolated part points us closer to the heart of the matter: understanding
the true dignity of excellent human activity, and how some new ways
of improving performance may distort or undermine it.
Our deepest concerns are tied to the large questions we raised
at the start of this chapter: What is a human performance,
and what is an excellent one? And what makes it excellent
as a human performance? For it seems that some performance-enhancing
agents, from stimulants to blood doping to genetic engineering of
muscles, call into question the dignity of the performance
of those who use them. The performance seems less real, less one's
own, less worthy of our admiration. Not only do such enhancing agents
distort or damage other dimensions of human life-for example, by
causing early death or sexual impotence-they also seem to distort
the athletic activity itself. It is not simply that our greatest
sportsmen could become bad fathers if their enhancements made them
uncontrollably aggressive or left them prematurely dead. It is that
they are, despite their higher scores and faster times, bad or diminished
as sportsmen-not simply because they cheated their opponents,
but because they also cheated, undermined, or corrupted themselves
and the very athletic activity in which they seem to excel.
What is at stake here is the very meaning of human agency, the
meaning of being at-work in the world, being at-work as myself,
and being at-work in a humanly excellent way. To clarify
this claim, we must consider several aspects of human activity and
human agency. Before doing so, we must first address the matter
of competition and its significance for the things we do.
1. The Meaning of Competition.
We have already noted, in the discussion of coercion and constraint,
the distortions that social pressures to get ahead introduce into
athletics and other human activities. Yet unlike many of our activities-such
as learning, doctoring, or even governing-athletics are intrinsically
competitive. They involve a contest of single opponents or opposing
teams, matching their talents against one another and seeking on
that day or in this event to be better than the rest (or better
than the best). Sometimes competition is friendly, a playful meeting
of fellows who take pleasure in each other's achievements. Sometimes
competition is fierce, mixed with a desire not only to see oneself
victorious but to see one's opponent roundly defeated. Most often,
competition mixes the friendly and the fierce: good friends are
often rivals on the playing field, and bitter opponents often have
a deep respect for one another as being worthy foes, demanding and
evincing one's own best efforts.
But not all human activity, as we have noted, is intrinsically
competitive and rivalrous. Consider, as a comparison to human sport,
the activity of making music. It is certainly the case that musicians
sometimes compete with one another: for first chair in the orchestra,
for record contracts, for prizes and public esteem. But strictly
speaking, when engaged in these rivalries they are not at work making
music. Indeed, it seems misguided to say that music is in its
essence a competitive activity-in the way Olympic running and
professional chess are intrinsically competitive activities. When
the string quartet or the symphony orchestra makes music, it has
no opponent against whom it is competing. Moreover, no musician's
performance or excellence can be "measured" in the same way as the
shot-putter's or the runner's when he or she breaks a world record.
To be sure, we can judge some musical performances as clearly better
than others, and individuals strive to become better musicians than
they were before. But the many forms of musical excellence seem
to belie final comparative judgments about better and worse: two
individuals can play the same sonata or sing the same song very
differently but both excellently, each capturing something essential
but something different in the music. Runners in the same race may
run differently-with different styles, each embodying a different
form of excellent running-but in the end we can say, at least in
a given race, who is the "best."
And yet, even those activities that are intrinsically competitive,
such as sports, are not simply competitive in their essence.
The dignity of athletic activity is not defined only by winners
and losers, faster and slower times, old records and new. Competition
can sometimes blind us to the fact that it is not simply the separable,
measurable, and comparative result that makes a performance
excellent-but who is performing and how. The word
"superior" itself captures this dichotomy, meaning both "better
than one's competitor" but also denoting a performance or activity
that is simply outstanding in itself. Excellent running seems to
have a meaning-the human body in action, the grace and rhythm of
the moving human form, the striving and exertion of the aspiring
human runner-that is separable from competition, even when the runner
is running competitively. Even in the most competitive activities,
the deepest meaning may not be honorable victory, or beating one's
best human opponents in a worthy way, but rather the human agent
at-work in the world-especially the lived experience, for both the
spectator and doer, of a humanly cultivated gift, excellently-at-work.
2. The Relationship between Doer and Deed.
This leads us to the second consideration: the relationship between
the doer and the deed, or between the human agent and the human
activities he or she engages in. As said above, the dignity of human
sport (or any other human activity) is determined not simply or
predominantly by the measured and separate result, but also
by who achieves it and how. Seen not as a detachable
deed but as an activity of an agent, athletic performance
depends on both the doing of a deed and the identity
of the doer. The purpose of competitive running, for example,
is to cover the set distance as quickly as possible. But this is
only part of the story. The man on roller skates moves more quickly
than the runner. But he obviously engages in a different activity-moving
quickly, but not running-and thus should be judged according to
a different standard. (Just because we have invented roller
skates, cars, and airplanes-all faster ways of moving-does not mean
we have stopped competing in running.)
Animals run, often quickly. In contrast with mechanized movement,
in animal running doer and deed are seamlessly united. And as already
noted, the average cheetah runs much faster than the fastest human
being and is beautiful to behold. But we do not honor the cheetah
in the same way we honor the Olympic runner, because the Olympian
runs in a human way as a human being. (Of this, more
soon.) In a word, in athletic performance seen as a performance
of a performer, we cannot separate the "result" (the fastest time)
from the "activity" (human running). In assessing athletic performance,
we do not in fact separate what is done from how it
is done and who is doing it, from the fact that it is being
done by a doer. And we should not separate the score from the
purpose of keeping score in the first place: to honor and promote
a given type of human excellence, whose meaning is in the doing,
not simply in the scored result. Tomorrow's box score is at most
a ghostly shadow of today's ballgame.
Consider another example: the best human chess player playing
against a chess-playing computer. It is worth asking how or whether
man and machine are really "competing" at all, and to what extent
we can really compare the superior capacity of a computer to "play"
chess with the distinctive excellence of a human chess player. On
one level, of course, they are indeed competing: playing the same
game according to the same rules. And yet, the computer "plays"
the game rather differently-with no uncertainty, no nervousness,
no sweaty palms, no active mind, and, most importantly, with no
desire or aspiration and no hopes or expectations regarding possible
future success. In this new type of competition, our best human
being faces off against our best human artifact. But the computer's
way of "playing" is really a kind of simulation-the product of genuine
human achievement, to be sure, since building such a computer is
its own manifestation of human excellence. But is this simulation
the real thing-playing chess?xvii
And by building computers that "play" perfect chess, do we change
the meaning of the activity itself? Do we reorient the very character
of our aspiration-from becoming great human chess players
to becoming better chess-playing machines, or, if you prefer,
from becoming great chess players to producing
the best-executed game of chess? Why, if chess is no more
than the sum of opposing moves that are in principle calculable
by a machine, would human beings wish to play chess at all, especially
if the machines can do it better?
The answer is at once simple and complex: We still play chess
because only we can play chess as human beings, as
genuine chess players. We still run because running, while
not as fast as moving on wheels, retains a dignity unique to itself
and unique to those who engage in this activity. The runner on steroids
or with genetically enhanced muscles is still, of course, a human
being who runs. But the doer of the deed is, arguably, less obviously
himself and less obviously human than his unaltered
counterpart. He may be faster, but he may also be on the way to
becoming "more cheetah" than man, or more like the horses we breed
for the racetrack than a self-willing, self-directing, human agent.
He does the deed (running), and his resulting time may be measurably
superior. But he is also (or increasingly) the passive recipient
of outside agents that are at least partly responsible for his achievements.
3. Acts of Humans, Human Acts: Harmony of Mind
and Body.
This brings us to a third and closely related consideration, the
specific difference of a human act or performance. For in
judging a performance to be genuinely and humanly superior, we care
not only that there be an integral connection between doer and excellent
deed. We care also that the doer-at-work display those qualities
that make us admire the performance as a human activity and
as his own activity. Borrowing a useful distinction from
moral philosophy, not all acts done by humans are human
acts, acts that spring from the roots of our humanity. Not all acts
done by persons are personal acts.
One common way of getting at the crucial difference is to talk
about "true" and "false" acts, acts that do and acts that do not
spring truly from who or what we are. This is what people have in
mind when they say that athletes who use steroids or a corked bat
to hit the ball farther than they could before are not only breaking
the rules, but getting their achievements "on the cheap," performing
deeds that appear to be, but that are not in truth,
wholly their own. This makes sense as far as it goes, but it gives
rise to the question, "What would make an act of humans genuinely
a human act?" "What would make the deed truly one's own?"
Comparison with the doings of animals other than man proves helpful.
In the activity of other animals, there is necessarily a unity between
doer and deed; acting impulsively and without reflection, an animal-unlike
a human being-cannot deliberately feign activity or separate its
acts from itself as their immediate source. Yet though a cheetah
runs, it does not truly run a race. Though it senses and pursues
its prey, it does not seek a goal with full consciousness or with
ambitions to surpass previous performances. Though its motion is
voluntary (not externally compelled), it does not run by choice.
Though it moves in ordered sequence, it has not planned the course.
Its beauty and its excellence-and these are not to be disparaged-it
owes largely to nature and instinct.
In contrast, the human runner chooses to run a race and sets before
himself (herself) his (her) goal. He measures the course and prepares
himself precisely for it. He surveys his rivals and plots his strategy.
Though constrained by the limits of his flesh, he cultivates and
disciplines his body and its natural gifts in pursuit of his goal.
The end, the means, and the manner are all matters of conscious
awareness and deliberate choice, from start to finish. In a word,
what makes the racer's running a human act humanly done is that
it is done freely, knowingly, and by conscious choice.
So far so good. But if the humanity of our actions rests solely
on their being rooted in knowledge and conscious choice, we face
this difficulty: Is not a decision to enhance our bodies through
drugs or genetic intervention also a matter of human choice? Why
would this not be precisely the expression of our rational
will, a manifestation of its peculiarly human ability not to be
enslaved by the limitations of our animal bodies? If it is the presence
of free, knowing, and conscious choice that makes for a human act,
then the bulking up of the genetically or drug-enhanced athlete-and
derivatively, his drug-assisted superior performance-would seem
to be preeminently human or even superhuman, a manifestation
of our ability to transcend nature's and our personal limitations
in a way no animal can.
This welcome objection invites a fuller account, with a three-part
response-one regarding the mind (and will), another regarding the
body, the third regarding their peculiar interrelations as expressed
in athletics and human activity more generally, as well as in human
desire and aspiration.xix
The point about the mind has already been prepared
by our earlier discussion of the difference between gaining superior
performance through training and practice and gaining superior performance
through biotechnological intervention and engineering. We called
attention to the difference between perfecting a capacity by using
it knowingly and repetitively and perfecting a capacity by means
that bear no relation to its use. And we stressed the difference,
on the plane of human experience and understanding, between
changes to our bodies that do and those that do not proceed through
intelligible and self-directed action, capable of being informed
by the knowledge of human experience. Thus, though the decision
to take anabolic steroids to enhance athletic performance can be
said to be, in one sense of the term, a rational choice, it is a
choice to alter oneself by submitting oneself to means that are
unintelligible to one's own self-understanding and entirely beyond
one's control. In contrast with the choice to adopt a better training
regimen, it is a calculating act of will to bypass one's own will
and intelligibility altogether.
Yet the problem with biotechnical enhancement lies not merely
on the side of exaggerated and self-contradictory willfulness. It
lies also with its mistaken identification of the human with the
merely rational and its neglect of our embodiment. For the humanity
of athletic performance resides not only in the chosenness and intelligibility
of the deed. It depends decisively on the performance of a well-tuned
and well-working body. The body in question is a living body, not
a mere machine; not just any animal body but a human one; not someone
else's body but one's own. Each of us is personally embodied. Each
of us lives with and because of certain bodily gifts that owe nothing
to our rational will. Each of us not only has a body; each of us
also is a body.
In few activities is this truth more manifest than in sports.
When we see the outstanding athlete in action, we do not see-as
we do in horse racing-a rational agent riding or whipping a separate
animal body. What we mainly see is a body gracefully and harmoniously
at work, but at work with discipline and focus, and tacitly obeying
the rules and requirements of the game. We can tell immediately
that the human runner is engaged in deliberate and goal-directed
activity, that he is not running in flight moved by fear or in pursuit
moved by hunger. Yet while the peculiarly human character of the
running is at once obvious, the "mindedness" of the bodily activity
is tacit and unobtrusive. So attuned is the body, and so harmonious
is it with heart and mind, that-in the best instance-the whole activity
of the athlete appears effortlessly to flow from a unified and undivided
being.xx
At such moments the athlete experiences and displays something
like the unity of doer and deed one observes in other animals, but
for humans that unity is a notable achievement which far
transcends what mere animals are capable of. A great sprinter may
run like a gazelle, a great boxer may fight like a tiger, but one
would never mistake their harmony of body and soul for the brute
instinct that spurs an animal toward flight or fight.
Athletic activity is not only generically human and manifestly
a bodily matter; it is also emphatically the work of particular
individuals. This is hardly accidental. Although we are all equally
embodied, we are not bodily identical. On the contrary, our differing
identities are advertised and displayed in our unique bodily appearance.
True, in many gifts of body and mind we are indistinguishable from
our fellow human beings; but in some gifts many of us are specially
favored. It is the special distribution and assortment of common
and particular gifts, allotted to each of us, that constitute the
biological beginnings of our individual identity. In pursuing superior
athletic (or other) performance, we are cultivating and exercising
both our common and our particular gifts, seeking our own individual
flourishing. We discipline our gifts through choice and effort in
the service of enabling them to shine forth in our own beautiful
and splendid activity. We take pleasure in our own performance and
achievement. The added bonus of victory and the recognition that
follows from it we esteem largely because they confirm that our
own embodied excellence has been attained and that our desire for
superior performance has been satisfied.
In trying to achieve better bodies through muscle-enhancing agents,
pharmacological or genetic, we are not in fact honoring our bodies
or cultivating our individual gifts. We are instead, whether we
realize it or not, voting with our syringes to have a different
body, with different native capacities and powers.xxi
We are giving ourselves new and foreign gifts, not nature's and
not our own, and-exaggerating, but in the direction of the truth-treating
ourselves rather as if we were batting machines to be perfected
or as superior horses bred for the race and bound to do our bidding.
These acts of will do not respect either our own individuality or
the dignity of our own embodiment-on which, by the way, our will
absolutely depends for its very existence.
At the root of all human activity is desire or aspiration, especially
when it aims at excellence. Human aspiration for superior performance,
for excellent activity, for something memorable and great, is not,
finally, the product of pure reason or pure will. Neither is it
merely the product of our animality. It stems rather from that peculiar
blending of mind and desire, perhaps peculiar to human beings, called
by the Greeks eros, the longing for wholeness, perfection,
and something transcendent. In one formulation, it is the desire:
(1) for the good, (2) to be one's own, (3) always.11
The root of this longing lies in the awareness that, alas, we are
not entirely unified and undivided beings. We are rather frail and
finite in body and conflicted in soul. Being conscious of our finitude
and self-division, we strive to make of ourselves something less
imperfect, something more noble, something fine-something that would
be fulfilling as much as is humanly possible. Further, we pursue
this aspiration as ourselves and-at least to begin with-for ourselves.
We would not seek excellence on condition that, in order to attain
it, we would gladly have to become someone or something else.xxii
Not the excellence of god or beast, not even the excellence of some
generic human person or disembodied human will, but the excellence
of our own embodied allotment of human possibility is our goal.
It is doubtful, to say the least, that biotechnical transformations
of our bodies-or minds-will contribute to our realizing this goal
for ourselves.
The ironies of biotechnological enhancement of athletic performance
should now be painfully clear. First, by turning to biological agents
to transform ourselves in the image we choose and will, we in fact
compromise our choosing and willing identity itself, since we are
choosing to become less than normally the source or the shapers
of our own identity. We take a pill or insert a gene that makes
us into something we desire, yet only by seeming to compromise the
self-directed path toward its attainment. Second, by using these
agents to transform our bodies for the sake of better bodily performance,
we mock the very excellence of our own individual embodiment that
superior performance is meant to display. Finally, by using these
technological means to transcend the limits of our natures, we are
deforming also the character of human desire and aspiration, settling
for externally gauged achievements that are less and less the fruits
of our own individual striving and cultivated finite gifts.
There is, we might add, no limit in principle to the desire to
transcend the limits of our own nature. The desire to have a perfect
body, one that perfectly executes the dictates of the will, is tantamount
to a desire to transcend our embodiment altogether, to become as
gods, to become something more-than-human. No doubt the longing
for perfection has inspired many of the greatest human achievements.
But unless guided by some idea of the character of human
perfection, such longings risk becoming a full-scale revolt against
our humanity altogether. Fueled in addition by a thirst not merely
to excel but to defeat and surpass our rivals, the desire for superhuman
powers easily becomes boundless.
The argument we have offered seems to have landed us in this strange
position: We seek to defend human willing or agency, in the sense
of defending our being what we really do. But we also seek to recognize
the biological limits of the will, in the sense that much that is
central about us is not truly our doing. Biotechnology seems to
promise the triumph of the will with less willing effort and bodily
excellence in bodies not quite ours: we can become what we desire
without being the responsible and embodied agents of our own becoming.
A more human course, however, might be accepting that we cannot
will ourselves into anything we like, but we can still live with
the dignity of being willing, self-directed, embodied, and aspiring
persons, not biological artifacts, not thoroughbreds or pitching
machines. Better, in other words, to be great human runners with
permanent limitations than (non)human artifacts bred to break records.
Though our subject has not been athletics as such, but the uses
of biotechnical means to enhance athletic performance, our analysis
casts light on the ways in which the currently popular view of sports
may already be corrupting genuine human excellence and may lead,
unless we change our tastes, to enormous pressure to pursue any
and all biological performance-enhancers, should they be safe and
effective. For we have long since blurred the line between athletics
and entertainment. If the baseball-loving public cares mainly about
how many homers are hit or how far they go, then it will matter
less how much the deeds flow from the unadulterated yet cultivated
gifts of the hitter. Only if superiority of performance continues
to mean not just the excellence of a detached act, but of the act
as displaying the excellence of a superior human being, excellently
at-work-in our own mindful and aspiring embodiments-can we preserve
the full sense of humanly superior performance.
F. Superior Performance and the Good Society
Much of the above analysis focuses on the excellence of the individual
person at-work in the world. But any analysis of superior performance
must also take into account the performer's relationship with others:
teammates and competitors, teachers and admirers, co-workers and
friends, as well as the larger community. It is true that the individual,
even when working in tandem with his fellows, is excellent as himself.
But excellent human activity is by nature situated within a community,
a society, and a culture. The human individual flourishes as himself,
but he does not flourish alone. And he rarely flourishes without
enormous contributions from others, people near and even far to
whom he is indebted for nurture, rearing, coaching, encouragement,
employment, and the appreciation and support of the activity in
which he gets the opportunity to excel. Likewise, all excellence
is particular to time and place, even if particular examples of
human excellence are "for all time," and even if we can admire those
who perform in activities that we no longer engage in ourselves.
In myriad ways, society has a stake in excellent human activity.
It rewards, honors, and nourishes the superior performances of its
members. But it also expects, demands, and depends upon them. In
many everyday functions-flying airplanes, fixing computers, educating
children-we rely on others to "get the job done" or "rise to the
occasion" when needed. We need them to perform and perform well,
not just occasionally or sporadically, but steadily and reliably.
Allowing some leeway to beginners, we expect practice will make
perfect, we expect people to improve on the job and through the
experience of repeated performance.
Beyond its everyday utility, superior performance also ennobles
society: it makes everyone better; it raises the spirits of a community;
it nourishes the desire to be better and to do better, as individuals
and as a people. The example of superior performers gives those
who are still developing an image of who or what they might aspire
to become themselves. And everyone may be elevated by discovering
that human beings-like them in being human, unlike them in the superior
ways they perform-can do the beautiful and marvelous things they
themselves cannot do, but in which they can surely, if only partially,
participate as appreciators and admirers.
Our analysis of human sport sheds light also on the entire range
of such socially valuable and excellent performances, both those
that adorn our community and those that make it possible. Each of
these human activities has its own character and meaning, and hence
also its own dignity. In music, as in sport, the body is gracefully
at work, but at work in a different way: the fingers striking the
keys, the hand and arm moving the bow, the voice singing at perfect
pitch. The musician takes inspiration from others-perhaps including
rivals-but he does not compete. He makes music-arranging
notes and melodies as a composer and playing them as a performer.
But he also captures what is musical-hitting notes and singing
harmonies as they were meant to be hit and be sung. He knows the
notes and his body knows the movements. And guiding it all is his
musical understanding of the musical whole, grasped in both heart
and mind, that both inspires the performance and that is, when given
life in the playing, its completion.
In a similar way, one might describe a range of other human activities-painting,
dancing, building, designing, writing. Each of these activities
has a distinct character and excellence, and each retains a dignity
unique to itself, demanding and rewarding different human powers
and capacities. But each of them, like sport, involves a humanly
cultivated gift, a human doer and human deed, a deed performed,
at its best, in a humanly excellent way. It is the human
musician, not the synthesizing machine, whom we admire and defend:
the musician with desire and fallibility, who creates what did not
exist before and rises to the occasion when the moment most demands
it. Most important, while such superior performances are the work
of individuals, all of society shares in their excellence, as it
always does when taste is receptive to genius. Properly appreciative
witnessing is participating, and it enables everyone present
to experience the surpassing human possibility in a passing human
moment.
In addition, even those activities necessary for life in society
and devoted to some external result or purpose-for example, human
work to produce some useful object or to perform some needed service-can
be done in a way that is dignified or undignified, human or dehumanizing.
The difference is not simply how many objects are produced, with
what efficiency and what effectiveness. What matters is that we
produce the given result-the objects that we make-in a human way
as human beings, not simply as inputs who produce outputs. Indeed,
it is here that the temptation to improve performance-to make workers
more focused by giving them Ritalin, less sleepy by giving them
Modafinil, more muscular by genetically enhancing their muscles,
and so on-is most tempting. If all that matters is getting more
out of them-or more out of ourselves, by any means possible-then
improving performance by every biotechnical intervention available
makes perfect sense. But as we have seen with human sport, more
is at stake than simply improving output. What matters is that we
do our work and treat our fellow workers in ways that honor all
of us as agents and makers, demanding our own best possible performance,
to be sure, but our best performance as human beings, not animals
or machines.
But there is one further complication. Defending what is humanly
good or excellent must not only guard against the possibility of
dehumanization; it must defend first against the many threats to
personal or communal survival itself. When the very existence of
the human agent or human society is at stake, certain special superior
performances are not only edifying but urgent: for example, the
superior performance of soldiers or doctors. What guidance, if any,
does our analysis provide for such moments of extreme peril and
consequence, in war or in medicine, when superior performance is
a matter of life or death? Are some biotechnical interventions to
enhance performance justified in these activities (surgery, war)
while not justified in the other activities of human life (sports,
music, test-taking)? In these circumstances, might we treat men
as alterable artifacts-or willingly become artifacts ourselves-in
order to "get the job done"?xxiii
There may indeed be times when we must override certain limits
or prohibitions that make sense in other contexts-offering steroids
to improve the strength of soldiers while rejecting them for athletes,
offering amphetamines to improve the alertness of fighter-pilots
while rejecting them for students, offering anti-anxiety agents
to steady the hands of surgeons while rejecting them for musicians.
When we override our own boundaries, we do so or should do so for
the sake of the whole, and only when the whole itself is at stake,
when everything human and humanly dignified might be lost. And we
should do so only uneasily, overriding boundaries rather
than abandoning them, and respecting certain ultimate limits to
ensure that men remain human even in moments of great crisis. For
example: Even if they existed, and even in times of great peril,
we might resist drugs that eliminate completely the fear or inhibition
of our soldiers, turning them into "killing machines" (or "dying
machines"), without trembling or remorse. Such biotechnical interventions
might improve performance in a just cause, but only at the cost
of making men no different from the weapons they employ.
This particular case, in short, is the exception that proves the
rule: even in moments of great crisis, when superior performance
is most necessary, we must never lose sight of the human agency
that gives superior performance its dignity. We must live, or try
to live, as true men and women, accepting our finite limits, cultivating
our given gifts, and performing in ways that are humanly excellent.
To do otherwise is to achieve our most desired results at the ultimate
cost: getting what we seek or think we seek by no longer being ourselves.
We are well aware that this assessment of human activity and human
dignity, highly philosophical, may not be persuasive to some people.
And even those who might share the foregoing views of the possible
corruptions of using direct biotechnical intervention to gain superior
performance might be reluctant to argue against it for others. In
a free country, so they might say, people should be allowed to take
their muscle enhancers or alertness pills, even if we would not
use them ourselves. Where's the harm if some football players here
and there take steroids or a few ambitious college-bound students
take stimulants before their SATs?
Perhaps none. Human life is complicated, innovations abound, and
human activities often change their character without necessarily
losing their integrity. But we must at least try to imagine what
kind of society we might become if such biotechnical interventions
were to become more significant in their effects and more widespread
in their use. We might come to see human running and dog races,
singers and synthesizers, craftsmen and robots, as little different
from one another. Human beings, here mostly for our entertainment
or our use, might become little more than props or prop-makers.
We might lose sight of the difference between real and false excellence,
and eventually not care. And in the process, the very ends we desire
might become divorced from any idea of what is humanly superior,
and therefore humanly worth seeking or admiring. We would become
a society of spectators, and our activities a mere spectacle. Or
a society of parasites, needing and taking, but never doing or acting.
Worst of all, we would be in danger of turning our would-be heroes
into slaves, persons who exist only to entertain us and meet our
standards and whose freedom to pursue human excellence has been
shackled by the need to perform-and conform-for our amusement and
applause.
For a while-perhaps indefinitely-we might relish the superior
results that only our biotechnical ingenuity made possible: broken
records on the playing fields, more efficient workplaces, improved
national SAT scores. But we would have gone very far, potentially,
in losing sight of why excellence is worth seeking at all, and hence
what excellence really is, and how we pursue it as human beings,
not as artifacts.
_________________
Footnotes
i.
This chapter is, accordingly, about both the
excellence and the humanity of "superior performance," and about
whether improvements in performance do or do not compromise
the humanity or individuality of the agent.
ii.
Other areas where this is also true include
music, dance, theater, and other performing arts.
iii.
Similarly, the things that can corrupt, tarnish,
or merely complicate sports-greed, vanity, the desire to injure
or crush a rival-can corrupt, tarnish, or merely complicate
most other human activities.
iv.
We leave out of the account some further enhancements of "running,"
such as the use of wheels, or even motors, on the soles of shoes.
Such changes, of course, would transform the activity into something
other than running.
v.The
age-related loss of muscle size and strength has been named
"sarcopenia." (The term "sarcopenia" was first suggested by
I. H. Rosenberg in 1989. It is derived from Greek words meaning
"poverty of flesh." See Rosenberg, I., "Summary Comments," American
Journal of Clinical Nutrition 50: 1231-1233, 1989.) We shall
consider sarcopenia further in Chapter Four, "Ageless Bodies."
vi.
The very idea of "muscle-bound" looks away from activity, and
implies restricted freedom of motion; the hypertrophied
muscles cut down somewhat the range of possible motion around
some joints.
vii.
Interestingly, female bodybuilders initially
pursued the same path as the males. The result was women bodybuilding
champions with smaller but similarly individually developed
and articulated skeletal muscles. More recently there has been
an aesthetic reaction against the resulting female muscle "overdevelopment"
and, commercially at least, the more popular and profitable
activity today is women's fitness competition.
viii.
Recombinant viruses, engineered to express a
specific foreign gene, are frequently used to stimulate the
production of functionally effective amounts of the foreign
protein to treat disease. Recombinant viruses created from genetically
engineered human Adenovirus-associated Virus (AAV) have proved
to be efficient delivery systems of foreign genes into muscle
cells. As AAV is a small virus, only small foreign genes can
be used effectively with this virus. Fortunately, the DNA sequence
encoding IGF-1 is small enough to function well in AAV-based
recombinant viruses.
ix
Professor H. Lee Sweeney, the leader of the
team conducting this research, gave a fuller description of
his group's recent findings in his presentation to the Council
in September 2002. According to Professor Sweeney, the insertion
of IGF-1 genes into mouse muscles not only blocked the normal
age-related decline of muscle size and strength; in addition,
the researchers found, it caused the muscle tissue of older
mice to retain the optimal power and speed normally found only
in younger mice. It also improved the rate of repair of damaged
muscle tissue. Other experiments on rats showed that, when IGF-1
gene injections were accompanied by strenuous exercise, not
only did the rats develop bigger and stronger muscles, they
also retained those enhanced muscles far longer than they normally
would after the exercise had ceased. Should comparable results
be attainable with human skeletal muscles, gene insertion would
appear to hold great promise, both as therapy for muscular dystrophy
and age-related sarcopenia and as a means to enhance athletic
performance. See Sweeney, H., "Genetic Enhancement of Muscles,"
presentation at the September 2002 meeting of the President's
Council on Bioethics, Washington, D.C. Transcript available
on the Council's website, www.bioethics.gov.
x.
(From previous page.) In this study, approximately 1010
recombinant AAV particles in 100 microliters of fluid were injected
into a single small muscle compartment of mice. If such treatments
were eventually to be applied to humans, large amounts of recombinant
AAV containing the human IGF-1 DNA sequence would be required.
Assuming such future treatments were shown to be safe and effective,
producing sufficient recombinant AAV to treat millions of dystrophic
and aging humans would remain a substantial logistical challenge.
However, there may be ways around this logistical problem involving
the production and transplantation of human muscle stem cells
engineered to produce more IGF-1.
xi.
The growing understanding of muscle physiology
at the molecular level coupled with sophisticated genetic engineering
has made it possible to enlarge skeletal muscles selectively,
without damaging heart muscles in the process. In previous studies
of this type, the IGF-1 transgene was not connected to gene
expression regulatory elements that restricted production of
mIGF-1 to muscle tissue. This led to overproduction of IGF-1
in the circulation, and eventually to pathological enlargement
of the heart muscle. But in the studies with transgenic mice
cited here, the rat mIGF-1 transgene was connected to gene expression
regulatory elements that restricted production of the rat mIGF-1
protein only to muscle tissues containing primarily fast-twitch
fibers. Side effects on the heart muscle did not occur.
xii. The first approach would be similar
to other human gene therapy projects in children and adults.
The appropriately regulated human mIGF-1 gene would be combined
with a vector capable of efficient delivery to muscle cells,
perhaps AAV. This material could be produced in large volumes,
carefully characterized by tests in experimental animals, stored
frozen and used as needed. While the logistics of producing
the large amounts of recombinant AAV that would be required
for treatment of thousands or millions of patients are daunting,
in principle this would be possible. The advantages of this
approach are (1) that it would develop and use a single, well-characterized
biological agent; (2) that treatment could be started very slowly
by introducing the recombinant mIGF-1 gene-containing AAV into
one muscle at a time and evaluating its effects; (3) that treatment
could be stopped immediately if untoward side effects developed.
Disadvantages include (1) the possibility that a large number
of injections would be necessary to treat each of the large
number of human skeletal muscles; (2) the possibility that this
would not be an effective treatment for humans who had antibodies
to AAV as a consequence of a previous infection.
The second approach is a radical proposal, as it envisions treatment
of blastocyst-stage human embryos in vitro with a genetic procedure
that was intended to change the early development of skeletal
muscle size and strength and reduce the rate of loss later in
life. This approach shares some advantages with the first approach
in that (1) a single biological agent could be prepared and
characterized that could treat all embryos; (2) only a single
treatment early in embryonic development would be needed, instead
of multiple injections into different muscles. The major disadvantages
of this approach are the difficult ethical questions it would
raise, as well as the difficulty of meeting the safety criteria
demanded of any germ-line or embryo genetic engineering (see
Chapter Two, "Better Children").
The third approach depends upon the ability to isolate human
muscle stem (satellite) cells and expand them in vitro. [This
has recently been reported for mice. See Qu-Peterson, Z., et
al., "Identification of a novel population of muscle stem cells
in mice: potential for muscle regeneration," Journal of Cell
Biology 157(5): 851-864, 2002.] The isolated human muscle
stem cells would then have their mIGF-1 production genetically
modified by introducing an appropriately regulated exogenous
mIGF-1 gene copy. In theory, this could produce modified muscle
stem cells that multiplied continuously in vitro to produce
larger numbers of cells, and that differentiated appropriately
in vitro. In this case, genetically modified satellite cells
would be injected into skeletal muscles. The advantages of this
approach include (1) it would develop and use a single, well-characterized
biological agent to modify the muscle stem cells in vitro, and
(2) the dose of modified stem cells could be varied as necessary
to optimize treatment of individual skeletal muscles. The disadvantages
include the possibility that a separate preparation of muscle
stem cells would have to be made from each patient needing treatment,
in order to get around the immune-rejection problem.
xiii.
Earlier this year, the FDA enlarged the domain
of approved uses for human growth hormone to include preventive
treatment of short stature. To be eligible for approved use,
a child's height must be more than 2.25 standard deviations
below the mean for age and sex; that is, he or she must be among
the shortest 1.2 percent of children. Obviously, successful
treatment of this group would automatically create another group
of children who were now the shortest 1.2 percent. Even before
there was FDA approval, the uses of growth hormone were already
expanding, with increasing acceptance of medical intervention
for social gains. In an August 1996 article in the Journal
of the American Medical Association, Leone Cuttler and colleagues
report that six out of ten children receiving growth hormone
are not actually growth-hormone deficient. Some of these children
have other medical problems that stunt growth, but many receive
treatment because their parents simply want their children to
be taller. (Cuttler, L., et al., "Short stature and growth hormone
therapy: a national study of physician recommendation patterns,"
Journal of the American Medical Association 276: 531-537,
1996.)
xiv.
It has been suggested that along with the regular
Olympics and the Special Olympics, we have the "Bio-Olympics,"
where the competition is unconstrained and the athletes are
free to use any legal form of pharmaceutical or physiological
enhancement.
xv.
Better equipment is thought to be better because
it does what old equipment did more effectively. But as it does
so, the activities in which the old equipment was used are also
altered, and not necessarily improved as a whole. We
certainly have better tennis rackets-but is the game better
now than it was then? We certainly have better weapons-but are
the soldiers of today humanly superior to the soldiers of old,
and is warfare today "better" than it used to be?
xvi.
This bizarre prospect, the logical extension
of a preoccupation with equality, is the ingenious conceit of
a short story by Kurt Vonnegut, "Harrison Bergeron," in his
collection, Welcome to the Monkey House. The goal is
accomplished by the work of a "handicapper general" who is charged
with weighing down all elevated gifts, physical and mental.
xvii. Even beyond the native gifts, we
could never titrate the important advantages of proper nurture,
rearing, coaching, encouragement, experience, or faith.
xviii.
Would anyone be interested in watching a chess
match "played" by two computers? If so, why? Would that
be a "chess match" in any ordinary sense?
xix.
These questions about mind, body, and their interrelation, we
are well aware, are deep and difficult philosophical matters.
We have no illusion that we have done more here than signal
their crucial importance to the ethical analysis at hand.
xx.
The perceived "at-one-ness" of the runner can produce a parallel
sense of at-one-ness in the spectators, also manifesting mind,
body, and heart. Unselfconsciously we spectators are stunned
by the manifestation of genuine human excellence: it holds our
attention, it takes away our breath; it wins our heart. In appreciating
seamless excellence, we have moments of seamless excellence
ourselves, sharing reflectively in the glory of the superior
human performance we are witnessing. This "superior performance"
of the spectators has important implications for the character
of the whole society, a matter to which we return in the final
section of this chapter.
xxi.
To be sure, these transforming agents do not in fact produce
a completely different body. And a steroid-enhanced athlete
probably still feels that he is the same person he was before
the treatment. But the fans, seeing him for the first time in
his new physique, so suddenly acquired, often wonder if the
newly minted slugger really has the same body, really is the
"same" person. More important, the implicit aspiration, even
in these modest transformations, is indeed to have a body more
perfect than one could ever acquire simply by cultivating one's
own natural gifts. In this sense, using these agents on one's
muscles expresses the same desire as having major cosmetic surgery
on one's face: to become, to some extent, someone else, someone
with a more perfect body. The use of analogous agents on one's
psyche-say, to acquire a superior temperament or a different
set of memories-is likewise a (tacit) aspiration to become someone
else. We shall explore this subject in Chapter Five, "Happy
Souls."
xxii.
For example: No sane person, we suggest, would
choose to be the fastest runner on two legs if it required becoming
an ostrich. And few people would choose to acquire someone else's
perfections of body or mind on condition of becoming that other
person. Who, in the event of such self-transformative improvements,
would we say now enjoyed them?
xxiii.
Though both are concerned with matters of life
and death, soldiering and doctoring are different. The two "wholes"
that they serve are different, the community being both more
comprehensive and much less intrinsically perishable. The existence
of all individual life within a community depends on the survival
of that community. An argument could be made to cut soldiers
a bit more slack than physicians in doing whatever it takes
to "get the job done," precisely because the whole itself is
at stake in time of war. A counter-argument could also be made,
not on the basis of the superiority of the good being served,
but rather the means used (cutting the body to heal it versus
cutting the body to kill it), which might justify cutting more
slack to surgeons than to soldiers.
_________________
ENDNOTES
1.
Tzankoff, S., "Effect of Muscle Mass on Age-Related
BMR Changes," Journal of Applied Physiology 43: 1001-1006,
1977.
2.
Asakura, A., et al., "Muscle satellite cells are
multipotential stem cells that exhibit myogenic, osteogenic, and
adipogenic differentiation," Differentiation 68(4-5): 245-253,
2001; Zammit, P., et al., "The skeletal muscle satellite cell:
stem cell or son of stem cell?" Differentiation 68(4-5):
193-204, 2001.
3.
This discussion owes much to the work of Professor H. Lee Sweeney
and his colleagues at the University of Pennsylvania and elsewhere
(see Bibliography), and to his description and discussion of that
work at the September 2002 meeting of the President's Council
on Bioethics. Transcript available at the Council's website, www.bioethics.gov.
4.
Barton-Davis, E., et al., "Viral mediated expression
of insulin-like growth factor I blocks the aging-related loss
of skeletal muscle function," Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences 95: 15603-15607, 1998.
5.
Musaro, A., et al., "Localized Igf-1 transgene
expression sustains enlargement and regeneration in senescent
skeletal muscle," Nature Genetics 27: 195-200, 2001.
6.
H. Lee Sweeney, personal communication with Council staff, 2002.
7.
Weber, M., "Effects of growth hormone on skeletal
muscle," Hormone Research 58(3):43-48, 2002.
8.
Gladwell, M., "The Sporting Scene: Drugstore Athlete,"
The New Yorker, September 10, 2001.
9.
Rousseau, "Discourse on the Origin and Foundations
of Inequality (Second Discourse)," transl. Roger D. and Judith
R. Masters, in The First and Second Discourses, ed. Roger
D. Masters, New York: St. Martin's Press, 1964, p. 147.
11.
Plato, Symposium, 206A.
|