This commissioned paper was
prepared for and discussed at the Council's July
2003 meeting. It was intended solely to aid discussion, and does
not represent the official views of the Council or of the United States
Government.
DRAFT
the Ethics of Stem Cell Research
Paul Lauritzen
Professor, Department of Religious Studies
Director, Program in Applied Ethics
John Carroll University,
University Heights, Ohio
JuLY 2003
. . . the final stage is come when man by eugenics, by prenatal
conditioning, and by an education and propaganda based on perfect
applied psychology, has obtained full control over himself. Human
nature will be the last part of nature to surrender to man. (Lewis,
1947)
This sudden shift from a belief in Nurture, in the form of social
conditioning, to Nature, in the form of genetics and brain physiology
is the great intellectual event, to borrow Nietzsche’s term,
of the late twentieth century. (Wolfe, 2001)
I begin with passages from an unlikely pair of authors because
although C. S. Lewis and Tom Wolfe are somewhat distant in time,
certainly different in temperament, and extravagantly different
in personal style, they share an imaginative capacity to envision
the possible consequences of modern technology. The technology that
occasioned Lewis’s reflections?“the aeroplane, the wireless,
and the contraceptive” may now seem quaint, but his warning
about turning humans into artifacts, that accompanied the passage
quoted above, is eerily prescient. Similarly, although he does not
directly take up stem cell research, Tom Wolfe’s reflections
on brain imaging technology, neuropharmacology, and genomics are
worth noting in relation to the future of stem cell research. In
his inimitable way, Wolfe summarizes his view of the implications
of this technology in the title of the essay from which the above
passage comes. “Sorry,” he says, “but your soul
just died.”
The point of beginning with Lewis and Wolfe, then, is not that I
share their dire predictions about the fate to which they believe
technology propels us; instead, I begin with these writers because
they invite us to take an expansive view of technology. I believe
that such a perspective is needed and is in fact emerging in recent
work on stem cell research. This is not to say that the sort of
traditional analysis that has framed much of the debate on stem
cells, analysis that involves issues of embryo status, autonomy,
and informed consent, for example, is unhelpful; far from it. Nevertheless,
traditional moral analysis of stem cell research is nicely complemented
by a consideration of the “big picture” questions that
Lewis and Wolfe both wish to press. This report will therefore seek
to draw attention to the literature on stem cell research that attends
both to the narrow and to the expansive bioethical issues raised
by this research.
The Moral Status of the Embryo
There is little doubt that public reflection on stem cell research
in the United States has been affected by the extraordinarily
volatile cross-currents of the abortion debate. Although I will
indicate below several reasons why framing the stem cell debate
as a subset of that on abortion is problematic, nevertheless,
in its current form, stem cell research is debated in terms dictated
by the abortion controversy, and that has meant that questions
about the status of the embryo have been particularly prominent.1
For example, the National Bioethics Advisory Commission (NBAC)
described the ethical issues raised by stem cell research as “principally
related to the current sources and/or methods of deriving these
cells” (NBAC, 1999, 45). A policy brief from the American
Association for the Advancement of Science (AAAS) begins its discussion
of the ethical dispute over stem cell research by citing the disagreement
over the status of the embryo as the decisive variable leading
to fundamentally different views on this research (AAAS, 1999,
11). The National Academy of Sciences’s report on stem cell
research claims that “the most basic [ethical] objection
to embryonic stem cell research is rooted in the fact that such
research deprives a human embryo of any further potential to develop
into a complete human being” (National Academy of Sciences,
2002, 44). The Ethics Advisory Board of the Geron Corporation
lists the moral status question as the first moral consideration
relevant to deciding the acceptability of stem cell research (Geron
Corporation Ethics Advisory Board, 1999, 32). The list could go
on.
Despite the fact that these statements all insist on the importance
of the status question, they also recognize that the debate about
the status of the early embryo is not new and that the controversy
over stem cell research does not, strictly speaking, raise novel
issues in this regard. Indeed, it is probably best to place the
initial skirmishes over stem cell research in the context of moral
debates about human embryo research generally. In fact, it is
worth noting that the report of the NIH Human Embryo Research
Panel (HERP), published in 1994, explicitly identified the isolation
of human embryonic stem cells as one of thirteen areas of research
with preimplantation embryos that might yield significant scientific
benefit and that should be considered for federal funding (See
NIH HERP, 1994, ch. 2).
Although the recommendations of the HERP were never implemented,
the fact that a high-profile panel reviewed ex utero
preimplantation human embryo research and explicitly endorsed
stem cell research, meant that the panel report would affect the
policy debate about stem cell research, even though its recommendation
that the derivation and use of stem cells be federally funded
was not adopted. For one thing, the panel’s anticipatory
support for stem cell research assured that when human stem cells
were actually derived several years later, the debate that ensued
would be tied to the abortion controversy. As members of the HERP
panel have made clear, from the start, the work of the panel was
embroiled in controversy. For example, shortly after the HERP
was impaneled, thirty-two members of Congress wrote to Harold
Varmus, the director of NIH, to complain about the composition
of the panel. A lawsuit was filed in an attempt to prevent the
panel from meeting, and members of the panel received threatening
letters and phone calls (Green, 1994; Tauer, 1995; Hall, 2003).
Given the pro-life opposition to the HERP panel and its recommendations,
it is no real surprise that initial reactions to the prospect
of human stem cell research fell out along the fault lines of
abortion politics in the country. By and large, individuals and
groups opposed to abortion tended to be opposed to stem cell research,
and individuals and groups supportive of legalized abortion tended
to support stem cell research. 2
For example, the testimony that Richard Doerflinger, the principal
spokesperson for the U.S. Catholic bishops on pro-life matters,
offered before the Senate Appropriation Subcommittee on Labor,
Health, and Education in 1998 was substantially the same as that
he offered before the HERP in 1994 on stem cell research (Doerflinger,
1998, 1994). In both cases, the fundamental issue was the status
of the embryo. Given Catholic teaching that the embryo must be
treated as a person from conception, no experimentation on the
embryo can be allowed that would not also be allowed on infants
or children. Hence, the Catholic church treats stem cell research
as it has treated previous issues involving the destruction of
human embryos; it is condemned as morally abhorrent.
In similar fashion, the arguments reviewed by the HERP panel that
supported embryo research generally in 1994, were mobilized again
four years later when stem cell research was the specific point
of contention; and again the focal point was embryo status. Consequently,
just as the HERP report opted for a “pluralistic”
view of the embryo that emphasized its developmental potential,
so, too, did the NBAC endorse the idea that the early embryo deserves
respect, but is not to be treated fully as a person.3
Moreover, the fact that the HERP defended its support of stem
cell research by stressing the developmental capacity of the embryo
also shaped the trajectory of much subsequent support for this
work, because insisting on respect for the embryo but denying
its personhood meant explaining how one could respect the embryo
while nevertheless destroying it. Daniel Callahan, for example,
posed this problem very strongly in response to the HERP report.
If “profound respect” for the embryo is compatible
with destroying it, he asked, “What in the world can that
kind of respect mean?” It is, he says, “an odd form
of esteem?at once high-minded and altogether lethal” (Callahan,
1995). Callahan was not alone in raising this issue and attempts
to answer his question continue to appear in the literature (See
Lebacqz, 2001; Meyer and Nelson, 2001; Ryan, “Creating Embryos,”
2001; Steinbock, 2001, 2000).
In retrospect, then, it seems that the HERP report served almost
as choreography for the initial debates about stem cell research,
and, as a result, the steps in the debate closely followed those
that are familiar from the abortion controversy (On this point,
see Hall 2003). The upshot, in my view, is that much of the debate
has been too narrowly focused and has a kind of repetitive and
rigid quality to it. As I noted above, for example, the Catholic
church has repeatedly claimed that the central issue raised by
stem cell research is that it involves the destruction of human
embryos, embryos it believes should be treated as persons.4
For that reason, the rhetoric with which the Catholic church condemns
embryonic stem cell research closely parallels that used to condemn
abortion. Yet, because the American bishops do not want to be
perceived as anti-science, they have also repeatedly and uncritically
praised adult stem cell research, even though there are good reasons,
given Catholic concerns about social justice, to be concerned
about the pursuit of adult stem cell research. I will return to
this point below, but for now I wish simply to note that much
of the opposition to embryonic stem cell work has resembled Catholic
opposition in being circumscribed by questions of embryo status,
narrowly construed.
A similar constriction, however, is also apparent in the preoccupations
of supporters of stem cell research. Just as opponents of this
research have ritualistically condemned the destruction of early
embryos but uncritically celebrated adult stem cell work, supporters
of embryonic stem cell research have typically insisted on using
embryos left over from IVF procedures, while repudiating the use
of embryos created solely for research. Indeed, insisting on the
distinction between so-called “spare” embryos and
“research” embryos and endorsing only the use of spare
embryos has been one way that supporters of embryo research have
tried to demonstrate their “respect” for the embryo.
Yet, it is worth asking whether the spare embryo/research embryo
distinction does not, to borrow Daniel Callahan’s image,
provide a kind of “wafting incense” to mask what supporters
still find a disquieting smell (Callahan, 1995).5
Although the debate about stem cell research might have been framed
in terms of the abortion controversy in any event, the HERP report
insured that the initial debate over stem cell work that followed
in aftermath of the public announcement of the work of John Gearhart
(Shamblott et al., 1998) and James Thomson in 1998 (Thomson et
al.) would be navigated in the wake of the conflict over abortion.
As I indicated, the upshot is that the discussion about stem cell
research has been more cramped than it might otherwise have been.
The discussion has been too focused on the details of embryological
development; too focused on the differences between those who
view the early embryo as a person and those who do not; and far
too individualistically oriented. Before turning to ways that
the debate might be become less cramped, let me focus more concretely
on these difficulties.
The point about the debate being framed too individualistically
is nicely illustrated in an article on abortion by Lisa Sowle
Cahill entitled “Abortion, Autonomy, and Community”
(Cahill, 1996). Cahill begins this article by claiming that, in
discussing the morality of abortion, there is no way to avoid
the question of the status of the fetus. Nevertheless, she says,
the debate about fetal status is almost always conducted with
the goal of determining the rights involved, where rights are
understood very individualistically. To the degree that the fetus
is acknowledged to have rights, those rights are pitted against
the rights of the pregnant women. Although Cahill doubts that
we can jettison the use of rights language altogether, if we are
going to use rights language, she says, we must “remove
that language from the context of moral and political liberalism”
(361). If we do so, we might be able to see that we have duties
and obligations to which we do not explicitly consent. As Cahill
puts it, “such obligations originate simply in the sorts
of reciprocal relatedness that constitutes being a human”
(361).6 For example, moving
away from an individualistic liberal view of the pregnant woman
as primarily or exclusively an autonomous moral agent might lead
us to recognize the obligations that individuals and communities
have to support her during and after a burdensome pregnancy (363).
We do not need to accept Cahill’s commitment to the Catholic
common good tradition to recognize the truth in her conclusion
that pitting the rights of the fetus against the rights of the
pregnant woman individualistically construed leads us to overlook
important social dimensions of the problem of abortion. It seems
to me that much the same dynamic is evident in the stem cell research
debate.
Consider again the central argument that the Catholic church has
made against stem cell research. The Pontifical Academy for Life
suggests that the fundamental ethical issue is whether it is morally
licit to produce or use human embryos to derive embryonic stem
cells. The reasoning the Academy provides for concluding it is
not licit is worth reproducing in full. The Academy lists five
points:
1. On the basis of a complete biological analysis, the living
human embryo is — from the moment of the union of the gametes
— a human subject with a well defined identity,
which from that point begins its own coordinated, continuous
and gradual development, such that at no later stage can
it be considered as a simple mass of cells.
2. From this it follows that as a “human individual”
it has the right to its own life; and therefore every
intervention which is not in favor of the embryo is an act which
violates that right. . . .
3. Therefore, the ablation of the inner cell mass (ICM) of the
blastocyst, which critically and irremediably damages the human
embryo, curtailing its development, is a gravely immoral
act and consequently is gravely illicit.
4. No end believed to be good, such as the use of stem
cells for the preparation of other differentiated cells to be
used in what look to be promising therapeutic procedures, can
justify an intervention of this kind. A good end does not
make right an action which in itself is wrong.
5. For Catholics, this position is explicitly confirmed by the
Magisterium of the Church which, in the Encyclical Evangelium
Vitae, with reference to the Instruction Donum Vitae
of the Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, affirms: “The
Church has always taught and continues to teach that the result
of human procreation, from the first moment of its existence,
must be guaranteed that unconditional respect which is morally
due to the human being in his or her totality and unity in body
and spirit: The human being is to be respected and treated as
a person from the moment of conception; and therefore from that
same moment his rights as a person must be recognized, among which
in the first place is the inviolable right of every innocent human
being to life’”(No. 60). (Pontifical Academy for Life,
2000; emphasis in original)
Notice that the core of the argument, namely points one and two,
is framed in terms of the rights of the individual embryo. We have
seen this emphasis already in noting Richard Doerflinger’s
various statements on stem cell research. Yet, notice also the claim
that we know the embryo to be an individual with rights on the basis
of “a complete biological analysis.” This is not, of
course, the first time that the Catholic church has made this claim.
In the Declaration on Procured Abortion, the Congregation for the
Doctrine of the Faith claimed that “modern genetic science”
confirms the view that “from the first instant, the programme
is fixed as to what this living being will be: a man, this individual-man
with his characteristic aspects already well determined” (Congregation,
“Declaration on Procured Abortion,”1974, 13). The Instruction
on reproductive technology, Donum Vitae, also
makes this claim. “The conditions of science regarding the
human embryo provide a valuable indication for discerning by the
use of reason a personal presence at the moment of the first appearance
of a human life: how could a human individual not be a human person?”
(Donum Vitae, 13).
One reason the Catholic church has played such a major role in framing
the stem cell debate is that, in defending its position, it combines
the two claims we have just noted, neither of which is explicitly
religious. First, the early embryo is an individual person with
rights and, second, the fact that the embryo is an individual person
is confirmed by modern science. Indeed, a fair amount of the literature
that supports embryo research generally can be read as an attempt
to answer the question posed in Donum Vitae: How
can a human individual not be a human person?
Certainly Catholic writers who reject the church’s teaching
on the status of the embryo have responded directly to that question
(See Cahill, 1993; Farley, 2001; McCormick, 1994; Shannon, 2001;
Shannon and Walter, 1990), but so too have non-Catholics. For example,
in a statement issued by their ethics committee, what was then called
the American Fertility Society rejected the claim in Donum Vitae
that science supports the personhood of the embryo. According to
the ethics committee “. . . it remains fundamentally inconsistent
to assign the status of human individual to the human zygote or
early pre-embryo when compelling biological evidence demonstrates
that individuation, even in a primitive biologic sense, is not yet
established. Thus, homologues (identical) twins may result from
spontaneous cleavage of the pre-embryo at some point after fertilization
but prior to the completion of implantation. Furthermore, during
very early development, an embryo is not clearly established and
awaits the differentiation between the trophoblast and the embryoblast”
(American Fertility Society, 1988, 3S).
Arguably, writers like Mary Anne Warren and Bonnie Steinbock, who
distinguish between biological or genetic humanity and moral humanity,
are also at least indirectly answering the question posed in Donum
Vitae (Warren, 1997; Steinbock 2001, 1992). Yet, whether writers
are responding more or less directly to Catholic discourse, or not
at all, the important point is that the stem cell debate has been
remarkably preoccupied with the question of whether the early embryo
is an individual person and whether and how the minute details of
embryological development help us to answer this question. This
is one reason why a fair amount of the ethics literature on the
topic reads like a textbook on embryology.
I want to be clear here: I am not suggesting that the details of
embryological development are unimportant. The maxim from the field
of research ethics applies here as well: bad science is bad ethics.
My point is rather that the preoccupation with the details of early
embryogenesis may lock us even more rigidly into an individualistic
human rights framework than we are in debates about abortion. It
also leads us to frame the debate as fundamentally about one question,
and, indeed, it tempts us to treat the question as if there is one
and only one answer. In this frame of mind, once we have that answer,
there is not a lot more to talk about. Either the early embryo is
a person with the right to life, in which case embryonic stem cell
research is wrong, or the early embryo is not a person with rights,
and then there is no moral reason to object to stem cell work. Gene
Outka has made a similar point in his assessment of stem cell literature.
As Outka puts it, in its starkest form, the crystallizing question
is whether it is cogent to claim that embryonic stem cell research
is morally indistinguishable from murder (Outka, 184). The problem
with framing the question this way, he says, is that it “encourages
an unfortunate tendency to restrict evaluative possibilities to
a single either/or. Either one judges abortion and the destruction
of embryos to be transparent instances of treating fetuses
and embryos as mere means to other’s ends, or one judges abortion
and embryonic stem cell research to be, in themselves,
morally indifferent actions that should be evaluated solely
in terms of the benefit they bring to others.” (Outka, 2002,
184).
The frame of human rights reinforces this either/or because, as
I noted, a being is either a rights-bearing entity or it is not.
I have argued elsewhere, that this either/or tends to drive people
to the extremes. Either the embryo is a person or it is essentially
a kind of property (Lauritzen, 2001). Although I will not rehearse
the argument for rejecting the two extremes here, it is worth noting
that the rhetoric associated with each extreme does not appear to
match the practice of those who adopt the rhetoric or in fact to
match the considered moral judgments of most Americans on these
issues.
I can illustrate my point in relation to the view that the early
embryo is a person with the right to life by describing a cartoon
that hangs on my office door (See appendix A). The cartoon depicts
protestors in front of a stem cell research lab condemning those
who work there as being anti-life. Down the street at the abortion
clinic, the workers are noting how quiet things have gotten at their
facility since the stem cell lab opened. The point of the cartoon,
of course, is that we may soon see protests and demonstrations of
the sort that are common at abortion clinics at facilities that
conduct stem cell research and that there is an irony in the fact
that pro-life advocates would be demonstrating against research
being done to find treatments for Alzheimer’s, Parkinson’s,
and other devastating illnesses. This is not entirely fair to the
pro-life community, but it makes a point.
In fact, I do not have trouble imaging protestors picketing stem
cell research facilities for, as we just noted, when stem cell research
and abortion are evaluated together and when the evaluative option
is a single either/or, then abortion and stem cell research may
appear indistinguishable from murder. Certainly the rhetoric of
someone like Richard Doerflinger has been consistent in condemning
both abortion and stem cell research as equivalent to murder. The
cartoon draws attention to this consistency, even while it questions
the commitment of pro-life advocates to scientific research designed
to promote the quality of life.
In one sense, then, the cartoon probes whether there is an inconsistency
between being pro-life and opposed to research an Alzheimer’s
disease, Parkinson’s disease, and other devastating illnesses.
I do not myself think that there is any inconsistency in being pro-life
and opposed to stem cell research, but the cartoon does point in
the direction of a fairly significant disconnect between the rhetoric
and the reality of those opposed to stem cell research because they
believe the early embryo is a person. To see this point, imagine
that, instead of a stem cell clinic, the cartoon depicted on IVF
clinic down the block from the abortion clinic and that the workers
at the abortion clinic are noting how quiet things have gotten since
the IVF clinic opened. The dramatic tension that made the original
cartoon funny would be missing from our revised cartoon precisely
because it is hard to imagine protestors disrupting the work at
IVF clinics. To be sure, the Catholic church and others have argued
that IVF is morally wrong, but the rhetoric condemning IVF is exceptionally
muted compared to that condemning abortion or stem cell research.
Nor has there been a concerted effort to put an end to IVF practice
in this country as there has been in the case of abortion and stem
cell research. Yet, if the embryo is a person from conception, then
participating in IVF as it is practiced in this country, when early
embryos are routinely frozen or discarded or both, is to be complicit
with murder. Why, then, are there no organized efforts to shut down
IVF clinics in this country? 7
Indeed, opponents of stem cell research and cloning often write
as if these technologies raise the haunting specter of human embryo
research for the first time. The reality, of course, is that the
existence of in vitro fertilization depended entirely on embryo
research and that every variation or innovation in IVF protocols
involves experimentation on human embryos. Carol Tauer is one of
the few scholars who has pressed this point. As Tauer sees it:
. . . the entire history of the research leading to the first
successful IVF is the history of attempts to fertilize oocytes
in the laboratory. Eventually these attempts succeeded, and the
first IVF baby was born, followed by thousands of others in the
ensuing decades.
The ethics literature contains scholarly discussions as to whether
it is ethically permissible to make use of medical advances that result
from unethical research. This discussion sometimes focuses on medical
research conducted by the Nazis in concentration camps and institutions
for retarded, mentally ill, and handicapped persons. Yet I have never
seen reference to reproductive technologies in this context. If the
fertilization of embryos in research is a practice that is abhorrent
to many or most people, then would it not be logical to question the
continuing use of the results of such research? (Even the Catholic
Church, which opposes the use of IVF and most other forms of assisted
reproduction, does not invoke this argument to support its opposition.)
(Tauer, 2001, 153)
If the embryo research associated with IVF points to a problem
of consistency for those who oppose stem cell research because it
involves destroying persons, it is no less problematic for those
who support stem cell research but insist on respecting the embryo
and embrace the distinction between “research” and “spare”
embryos. For as Tauer points out, Robert Edwards, the scientist
involved in the first successful IVF procedure, began studying fertilization
nearly thirty years before Louise Brown was born in 1978, and the
first successful laboratory fertilization of human eggs took place
a full ten years before she was born. Tauer quotes Edwards’
report on this work: “We fertilized many more eggs and were
able to make detailed examinations of the successive stages of fertilization.
We also took care to photograph everything because we would have
to persuade colleagues of the truth of our discoveries” (Tauer,
154).8 Nor was the creation of
these “research” embryos done secretly: Edwards and
Steptoe published their work in the journal, Nature in
1970 (Edwards, Steptoe, and Purdy, 1970).
At the very least, then, there is something of an irony in the fact
that so much attention has been devoted to developing and defending
the distinctions between embryos created solely for research and
embryos left over from IVF procedures, because there would be no
embryos left over from IVF procedures had there not been embryos
created solely for research purposes to develop IVF in the first
place. Given this fact, and given that this fact is no great secret?even
though it has not been discussed very much?it appears disingenuous
to endorse the distinction between “research” and “spare”
embryos as a way of demonstrating respect for the early embryo while
nevertheless encouraging its destruction.
I have suggested that the fact that so much of the stem cell debate
has been framed in terms of whether the embryo is a person with
rights has been unfortunate because it has cast the debate in sharply
individualistic terms and has led to a preoccupation with embryological
development narrowly construed. In addition, however, framing the
debate in terms of embryo status and embryo rights tends to exaggerate
the differences among commentators in contrast to their similarities.
Consider, for example, the response of conservative Judaism in the
United States to this issue. Rabbi Elliot Dorff has prepared a responsum
on stem cell research for the Rabbinical Assembly Committee on Jewish
Law and Standards, and his responsum is instructive.9
As responsa are, it is structured in terms of relevant questions:
in this case, two questions frame Dorff’s discussion. First,
“may embryonic stem cells from frozen embryos originally created
for purposes of procreation or embryonic germ cells from aborted
fetuses be used for research?” (Dorff, 2002, 1). Second, “may
embryonic stem cells from embryos created specifically for research,
either by combining donated sperm and eggs in a petri dish or by
cloning be used for research?” (1) I think it is noteworthy
that the very questions that frame Dorff’s analysis both reflect
and perpetuate a certain construction of the issue, but at this
juncture, my point is different: given the way the debate has been
framed, what most (non-Jewish) readers of Dorff’s analysis
are likely to focus on is the difference between his treatment of
the early embryo and that of others in the literature. Indeed, even
where you might expect to find?and do in fact find on closer inspection?similarities
between this Jewish analysis and Catholic reflection on this issue,
the first impression will be that of difference. The reason, of
course, is that our attention is drawn to Dorff’s analysis
of the early embryo, and Jewish views are sharply different about
embryo status than those of the Catholic church and other pro-life
opponents of stem cell work.10
For example, Dorff points out that, according to the Talmud, during
the first forty days of gestation, the embryo and the fetus are
considered as simply water. From the forty-first day until birth,
Jewish tradition considers the fetus as “the thigh of its
mother.” Moreover, says Dorff:
As it happens, modern science provides good evidence to support
the Rabbis’ understanding. As Rabbi Immanuel Jakobovits noted
long ago, the Rabbis’ “forty days” is, by our
obstetrical count, approximately fifty-six days, for the Rabbis
counted from the woman’s first missed menstrual flow, while
doctors today count from the point of conception, which is usually
about two weeks earlier. By 56 days of gestation by obstetrical
count the basic organs have already appeared in the fetus. Moreover,
we now know that it is exactly at eight weeks of gestation that
the fetus begins to get bone structure and therefore looks like
something other than liquid. Indeed, the Rabbis probably came to
their conclusion about the stages of development of the fetus because
early miscarriages indeed looked like “merely water,”
while those from 56 days on looks like a thigh with flesh and bones.
(16)
The contrast with Catholic teaching could hardly be more striking.
Not only are Jewish views of the status of the early embryo notably
different, but Jewish tradition claims scientific validation for its
view of the embryo, just as Catholic tradition does. Not surprisingly,
therefore, where Dorff answers both questions posed by the responsum
in the affirmative, Catholic tradition would answer both negatively.
These differences are significant and must be attended to, but it
is worth asking whether focusing on these differences does not obscure
important similarities. Consider some of the similarities. In sketching
the Jewish view of stem cell research, Dorff notes that certain theological
commitments are central. He lists at least three that would be strikingly
similar to Catholic and other Christian theological commitments.
- Our bodies are not ours; they belong to God and God commands
that we seek to preserve life and health.
- All human beings, regardless of ability or disability are created
in the image of God and are therefore to be valued as such.
- Humans are not God. We are finite and fallible and this fact
ought to promote humility and urge caution.
Now if we focused merely on questions of embryo status, we would miss
entirely these similarities between Catholic and Jewish views. More
importantly, we would miss the fact that these similarities may underwrite
significant moral reflection on stem cell research that is not rooted
in concerns about the early embryo.
For example, Dorff notes that, given Jewish theological and legal
commitments, the provision of health care must be understood as a
communal responsibility. Thus, access to therapies developed through
stem cell research is a crucial issue of justice for the Jewish community.
This theme is echoed in Laurie Zoloth’s work on stem cell research.
As Zoloth puts it:
Research done always will mean research foregone. Will this research
help or avoid the problem of access to health, given that poverty
and poor health are so desperately intertwined in this country? .
. . How can difficult issues of global justice and fair distribution
be handled in research involving private enterprise? (Zoloth, 2001,
238)
Surely these are questions that any Catholic moral theologian would
gladly press.
Indeed, attending to the similarities between Zoloth’s work
and Catholic reflection on stem cell research brings us back to Lisa
Cahill’s observation about debates on abortion: they tend to
be too focused on questions of rights individually construed. When
one shifts the frame of analysis, new and different issues and new
and different ways to approach the same issues come into view. Notice,
for example, how close Zoloth and Cahill are on the issue of rights.
According to Zoloth, Jewish tradition foregrounds questions of “obligations,
duties, and just relationships to the other, rather than the protection
of rights, privacy, or ownership of the autonomous self” (96).
This leads Zoloth to ask: “Can the interests of the vulnerable
be heard in our debate?” (105). To be sure, the American bishops
have wanted to emphasize the vulnerability of the early embryo when
they have asked this question, but Catholic tradition, like Jewish
tradition, requires that we ask this question in a way that is not
captured when moral emphasis is merely about individual rights and
personal autonomy.
Or consider another shared sensibility that emerges if we move away
from questions of embryo status, namely a wariness about the human
tendency to hubris and overreaching. Zoloth put this point eloquently
in relation to the biblical story of the Tower of Babel. She notes
a rabbinic midrash on this text: “when a worker was killed,
no one wept, but when a brick fell, all wept.” Zoloth comments
on this midrash as follows:
It was this decentering of the human and reification of the thing
that was the catastrophe that felled the enterprise . . . It is
not just that they breached a limit between what is appropriate
to create and what is not, the process of the creation must be carefully
mediated, with deep respect for persons over the temptations of
the enterprise. Such a text elaborates on the tension between repairing
the world . . . and acts that claim that the world is ours to control
utterly (Zoloth, 2001, 106-107).
Beyond Questions of Embryo Status
This passage from Zoloth helps to illustrate the point I wish to make
in arguing that the stem cell debate has been too focused on questions
of embryo status and that we must move beyond status questions if
we are fully to do justice to the moral questions raised by technological
developments associated with stem cell work. For concern about human
efforts utterly to control the world is not a moral worry narrowly
tied to status questions.
Let me put this point in the form of a question that has not typically
been asked in the stem cell debate: Is adult stem cell work as unproblematic
as it is often assumed to be? That this is a productive question is
suggested by testimony of Francis Collins before the President’s
Council on Bioethics in December 2002. Collins was asked to speak
about the topic, “genetic enhancements: current and future prospects”
and he specifically addressed the issue of pre-implantation genetic
diagnosis (PGD). Although PGD is usually understood to involve screening
IVF embryos and discarding unwanted ones, it is also possible to screen
gametes. Because gamete screening may not have broad utility, Collins
did not discuss the issue at length. He did, however, offer an interesting
observation about gamete selection. Focusing on gametes, he says,
is useful because it “isolates you away from some of the other
compelling arguments about moral status of the embryo and allows a
sort of cleaner discussion about what are the social goods or evils
associated with broad alterations in the sex ratio and inequities
in access to that technology” (Collins, 2002, 7). In other words,
if in the future we could screen gametes in the same way that we can
now screen embryos, most of the moral issues raised by PGD would apply
to gamete screening, even though gametes are not embryos. Might we
not make a similar claim about embryonic and adult stem cell research?
Do not many of the most pressing issues raised by embryonic stem cell
technology remain when our focus is adult stem cell work rather than
embryonic stem cell research?
The fact that we do not immediately answer yes to this question, is
testament to how decisively the debate about abortion has structured
the stem cell debate. Nevertheless, we need to see that the answer
to this question is yes and we need to see why.
Although I will not try to address all of the issues raised jointly
by embryonic and adult stem cell research, it is worth highlighting
several that I think require fuller discussion?particularly with respect
to adult stem cell work?than they have yet received.
Commodification Issues
Moral concerns about the commodification of gametes and embryos have
been discussed extensively in the bioethics literature both in relation
to reproductive technology and in connection with embryonic stem cell
work (See Andrews and Nelkin, 2001; Annas, 1998; Corea, 1986; Radin,
1996; Resnik, 2002; Ryan, Ethics and Economics, 2001). Suzanne
Holland, for example, has discussed the growing commodification of
the human body in the biotech age. She cites a series of articles
published in the Orange County Register that documents a vast for-profit
market in human body tissue (Holland, 2001, 266). The Register’s
investigative reporters documented that most nonprofit tissue
banks obtain tissue from cadavers donated by family members of the
deceased for altruistic reasons. Most relatives are not told, and
in fact have no idea, that donated body parts will be sold for profit.
As Holland puts it:
The “gift of life” is big business in America. For a
nonprofit tissue bank, one typical donation can yield between $14,000
and $34,000 in downstream sales, sometimes far more than that. “Skins,
tendons, heart valves, veins, and corneas are listed at about $110,000.
Add bone from the same body, and one cadaver can be worth about
$220,000.” Four of the largest nonprofit tissue banks told
the Orange County Register that together they expected to produce
sales totaling $261 million in 2000. (226)
Nor is the issue of downstream commodification restricted to the
sale of donated cadaveric tissue; it arises in relation to IVF embryos
donated for research. As Dorothy Nelkin and Lori Andrews point out
in their book, Body Bazaar, IVF patients are not generally
told what the research involving their donated embryos will include.
Many will be unaware that their embryos will be used to develop
commercial stem cell lines (Nelkin and Andrews, 2001, 35).
It is significant that even the most vocal advocates of procreative
liberty and laissez-faire arrangements in reproductive matters recoil
from the prospect of selling human embryos. Yet, although the commodification
of tissue may be particularly troubling when it involves embryos,
if there is a problem with commodifying and commercializing human
tissue, it is a problem we confront with adult stem cell research
as well as with hES cell work. Lori Knowles has made a similar point
about being consistent in our moral judgments about commodifying
embryos. She notes that fears about commodifying reproduction have
led many to oppose the sale of embryos and to reject the idea that
couples who donate embryos have any proprietary interest in the
result of the research done with their embryos. As Knowles puts
it, “if it is wrong to commercialize embryos because of their
nature, then it is wrong for everyone. It is simply inconsistent
to argue that couples should act altruistically because commercializing
embryos is wrong, while permitting corporations and scientists to
profit financially from cells derived by destroying those embryos”
(Knowles, 1999, 40).
Knowles draws attention here to the fact that there is a tension
between our moral and legal traditions as they apply to developments
brought about by cloning, stem cell research, and the existence
of ex utero human embryos, among other technological breakthroughs.
For example, we patent embryonic stem cell lines, thereby insuring
massive profits for patent holders, while decrying the commodification
of embryonic life. Knowles is correct that there is a tension between
our profit-based medical research model and our commitment to altruism
and the access to health care that a commitment to justice demands.
Adult stem cell research, of course, raises very similar issues,
because the same tension exists between the need for proprietary
control of technology and the need for affordable access. For example,
patents have been sought and granted for human adult stem cells
work as well as for embryonic stem cell technologies. According
to a study on the patenting of inventions related to stem cell research
commissioned by the European Group on Ethics in Science and New
Technologies, as of October 2001, two thousand twenty-nine patents
were applied or granted for stem cells and 512 patents were applied
or granted for embryonic stem cell work (Van Overwalle, 2002, 23;
see also McGee and Banger, 2002). As a result, access to therapies
developed from adult stem cell research is likely to be as serious
an issue as access to embryonic stem cell therapies.
Indeed, issues arising from commodification of both adult and embryonic
stem cells are likely to dominate the next phase of the debate,
if only because corporate interest in this work, both nationally
and internationally, is so strong (Hill, 2003). Noting that, as
of 2002, “a dozen biotech companies have entered the stem
cell industry and have invested millions of dollars,” David
Resnik suggests that the next stage of the stem cell debate will
involve a battle over property rights relating to stem cells (Resnik,
2002, 130-31).
To be sure, the battle over property rights raises important legal
and policy question, but it also raises ethical questions as well.
For example, Resnik provides the following table of possible ethical
objections to patenting stem cells.
Deontological Objections to Property
Rights in ES cells |
Consequentialist Objections to Property
Rights in ES cells |
ES cells (and their products) should not be
treated as property; they should be viewed as having inherent
dignity or respect. ES cells should not
be treated as private property; they are res communis
or common property. |
Treating ES cells as property will have dire social consequences,
such as exploitation, destruction of altruism, and loss of
respect for the value of human life. Treating ES cells
as property will undermine scientific discovery and technological
innovation in the field of regenerative medicine. (Resnik,
2002, 139) |
Although the ethical objections to commodifying stem cell work
can not be sorted out as neatly as this table suggests, Resnik correctly
identifies a variety of such objections. I will not try to defend
it here, but my own view is that the problem is not just that stem
cells and their products may be commodified, but that market rhetoric
may come to dominate the discussion (and practice) of regenerative
medicine in a way that is dehumanizing. That is, market-rhetoric
may lead us ultimately to think of humans as artifacts. In short,
I take very seriously Margaret Radin’s argument that the rhetoric
in which we conceive our world affects who and what we are (Radin,
1996, 82).11 At the same time,
however, stem cell research is most likely to bear therapeutic fruit,
if there is a market in stem cells and their products. The pressing
moral question, then, is how do we promote the benefits that stem
cell research may yield without succumbing to a market rhetoric
that reduces humans to commodities?
Several writers have suggested that one answer may be to promote
greater governmental regulation. For example, Holland argues for
moving beyond a policy of restricting federal funding of stem cell
research but allowing an unregulated private market in this field
to active regulation to curb the private sector’s work on
stem cells. Lori Knowles suggests that the United States might adopt
a body like Canada’s Patented Medicine Prices Review Board
as a way to allow a market to function, but with oversight that
would provide access to potential cells for further research and
price controls of products to insure widespread access (Knowles,
1990, 40). George Annas has suggested that we need to establish
a federal Human Experimentation Agency to regulate in the area of
human experimentation. (Annas, 1998, 18). As Annas puts it:
Virtually all those who have studied the matter have concluded that
a broad-based public panel is needed to oversee human experimentation
in the areas of genetic engineering, human reproduction, xenografts,
artificial organs, and other boundary-crossing experiments. (19)
Francis Fukuyama has argued that a new agency with a mandate to regulate
biotechnology on broad grounds and in both the public and private
sector may be needed (Fukuyama, 2002, 215). Vanessa Kuhn argues that
“it is time to put in place legislation that will deter stakeholders
from licensing their technology to one exclusive distributor and thus
creating a monopoly market, which would set artificially-high prices
and lead to less access for the sick especially for the uninsured,
the poor, and the elderly” (Kuhn, 2002). To that end, Kuhn identifies
four possibilities:
- Development of a new kind of patent.
- Set limits on exclusive licensing through compulsory licensing.
- Lower the lifespan of hES cell patents
- Set stricter guidelines for hES patent utility (2)
I do not have the expertise to make policy recommendations, but let
me stress two points. First, the policy issues with regard to commodifiying
adult stem cell work will be as vexing as those confronting regulation
of embryonic stem cells. Second, although these questions may at first
appear to be strictly legal or largely political matters, they involve
serious value judgments about the common good that are every bit as
morally vital as questions about the status of the embryo. I thus
agree with Gene Outka, that not to confront directly questions about
how stem cell research will be organized, financed, and overseen is
a kind of ethical failure (Outka, 2002, 177). Obviously, for example,
the institutional arrangements for conducting stem cell research have
implications for the questions of justice we previously noted. The
fact that so much stem cell research is being done by private corporations
insures future conflict. On the one hand, corporations have fiduciary
obligations to their shareholders and will therefore seek to control
access to stem cell lines or therapies developed from those lines
through patent protection and licensing agreements. On the other hand,
such a system is likely to further widen the gap between the health
care haves and have-nots (See Lebacqz 2001; McLean 2001).
Moreover, as Karen Lebacqz notes, if justice is an important consideration
in deliberations about stem cell work, then it ought to shape the
research agenda. The example she gives to make this point is worth
noting. Just as with organ transplants, tissue rejection may be a
major problem for stem cell therapies. This is one reason that the
prospect of combining stem cell work with somatic cell nuclear transfer
(SCNT) has been so enticing. With this combination, you could in theory
develop tissue that would be completely histocompatible. Nevertheless,
according to Lebacqz, developing stem cell therapies with SCNT is
“highly questionable,” if justice is a primary consideration.
The reason is that unique cell lines would need to be created for
each patient, and that is likely to be very expensive and thus unaffordable
for many. Although it would certainly be less expensive, the same
would likely be true for adult stem work. For that reason, rather
than pursuing an individualized approach to stem cell research, concerns
about affordable access to new therapies might urge the pursuit of
universal donor cell lines.
Embodiment, Boundary Issues, and Human Nature
In discussing the debate about embryo status, I focused primarily
on the contested question of whether the early embryo is a person
with the right to life. We saw that this question tends to lead to
the mobilization of minute details of embryological development to
support one’s view of the embryo. Yet, if attention to embryo
status tends to focus us on the microscopic, viewing stem cell research
through the lens of embryological development can also have a kind
of telescopic function through which larger issues come into view.12
For example, Catherine Waldby and Susan Squier argue in a forthcoming
issue of the journal Configurations that focusing on stem
cells and embryonic life leads us fundamentally to question what it
means to be human. According to Waldby and Squier:
Stem cell technologies have profound temporal implications for the
human life course, because they can potentially utilize the earliest
moments of ontogenesis to produce therapeutic tissues to augment
deficiencies in aging bodies. Hence they may effect a major redistribution
of tissue vitality from the first moments of life to the end of
life. In doing so however they demonstrate the perfect contingency
of any relationship between embryo and person, the non-teleological
nature of the embryo’s developmental pathways. They show that
the embryo’s life is not proto-human, and that the biology
and biography of human life cannot be read backwards into its moment
of origin. (Waldby and Squier, forthcoming)
The claim that there is a perfect contingency in the relationship
between embryo and person may at first appear to be just another “microscopic”
claim about embryo status, but it is clear that Waldby and Squier
mean to imply much more in asserting that the embryo’s development
is non-teleological. In effect, they reject the notion that there
is a meaningful trajectory to human life. What was killed, they say,
when stem cells were first derived from the inner cell mass of a blastocyte
was not a person, but a “biographical idea of human life, where
the narrative arc that describes identity across time has been extended
to include the earliest moments of ontogeny” (Waldby and Squier,
forthcoming).
That much more is at stake here than the question of whether the embryo
is a person is clear if we attend to the notion of a trajectory of
a human life. Gilbert Meilaender, for example, has argued that our
attitudes toward death and dying are importantly shaped by our conception
of what it means to have a life (Meilaender 1993). Indeed, according
to Meilaender, two views of what it means to have a life?of what it
means to be a person?have been at war with each other within the field
of bioethics over the past thirty years and these views underwrite
sharply different views not just about the issues of abortion or euthanasia
that are implicated here but with regard to practically every moral
issue we might confront in the field of bioethics.
On Meilaender’s view, having a life means precisely that there
is a trajectory that traces a “natural pattern” in embodied
life that “moves through youth and adulthood toward old age
and, finally, decline and death” (29). As he puts it elsewhere
in this essay, “to have a life is to be terra animata,
a living body whose natural history has a trajectory” (31).
Although Meilaender develops the notion of a natural trajectory of
bodily life primarily to address the issue of euthanasia and not stem
cell research, his talk of “natural history,” “natural
pattern,” and “natural trajectory” draws attention
to one of the most significant issues raised by stem cell research
and related technologies. Does stem cell research undermine the very
notion of a human life constrained by natural bodily existence? The
example on which Meilaender focuses here is instructive for thinking
about the broad implications of stem cell research in this regard.
If stem cell therapies fundamentally alter our sense of a natural
pattern to aging would they not also fundamentally alter our sense
of what it means to be human? Meilaender’s answer is that such
a change would fundamentally affect what it means to be human precisely
because we are embodied creatures and for that reason our identity
is tied to the body and the body’s history.
Leon Kass has made a similar point recently in reflecting on the prospect
that regenerative medicine might significantly lengthen the human
life span (Kass, 2003). He, too, invokes the notion of a natural trajectory,
one that stem cell research may undermine. Although it is possible
to approach the prospect of extending the human life-span in an abstract
way, he says, to think of what such a change would mean experientially
is to recognize that “the ‘lived time’ of our natural
lives has a trajectory and a shape, its meaning derived in part from
the fact that we live as links in the chain of generations”
(13). Indeed, says Kass, without something like the natural trajectory
of bodily life that currently exists, the relationship between the
generations would be decidedly different, and probably not better.
“A world of longevity,” writes Kass, “is increasingly
a world hostile to children” (13). Walter Glannon has argued
that, at the very least, increased longevity would increase competition
for scarce resources between older and younger generations. According
to Glannon, “it is at least intuitively plausible that an over
populated world with substantially extended human lives and scarce
resources could adversely affect the survival and reproductive prospects
of the young and harm them by thwarting their interest in being healthy
enough so that they could survive and procreate” (Glannon, “Extending,”
347). 13
Francis Fukuyama has also suggested some of the reasons why increased
longevity may imperil children, but he also notes that our relationship
to death may change as well (See 2002, ch. 4). “Death,”
he says, “may come to be seen not as a natural and inevitable
aspect of life, but a preventable evil like polio or measles. If so,
then accepting death will appear to be a foolish choice, not something
to be faced with dignity or nobility” (Fukuyama, 2002, 71).
Sometimes the question of the transformative possibilities that come
with stem cell research is raised even more starkly when the question
asked is not how may stem cell work affect what it means to be human,
but instead: Does stem cell research open the door to a post human
future? This is a point Waldby and Squier raise explicitly when they
discuss the combination of genetic engineering and stem cell therapy.
They suggest, for example, that xenotransplantation forces us to confront
the prospect of transgressing species boundaries.14
The conclusion of their paper is worth quoting in full:
Thus the ontological status of the embryo is not the
only thing in question. The ontological status of the graft recipient
must be negotiated, when the graft involves genetically-engineered
stem cells from another species. And the ontological status of the
illnesses to which biomedical technology responds is equally challenged,
in an endless regression, as the division between veterinary and
human medicine, or between zoonoses (diseases humans can catch from
animals) and what has recently been dubbed humanooses, is called
into question. This increasingly permeable, increasingly constructed
barrier between human and animal presents us with another form of
life to negotiate, whose boundary lies not between silicon and carbon,
but rather between steps in the evolutionary ladder?or the branching
development tree?of phylogenetic lifeforms. Stem cell technologies
thus challenge both the temporal and spatial boundaries of human
life, both our biography and our biological niche, giving a much
broader meaning to the questioning of embryonic personhood.
(Waldby and Squier, forthcoming)
Regrettably, with some notable exceptions, the ethical debate about
stem cell research has not taken up in a sustained way what it would
mean to pursue stem cell therapies that might significantly undermine
the notion of a natural human life or erode the boundary between human
and non-human species. When the issue is framed in terms of the status
of the embryo, the question tends to be whether the research should
be conducted at all. By contrast, when the issue is framed in terms
of adult stem cell work, the question is not whether, but how and
with what consequences. Yet, that is a question we have not systematically
answered. Given the potential for good embedded in the prospects of
adult stem cell research, it is not surprising that there appears
to be widespread and largely uncritical acceptance of adult stem cell
research. But, if the promise of stem research is as revolutionary
as is often claimed, we are going to need a much more expansive discussion
of stem cell research?both embryonic and adult?than we have had heretofore.
Obviously, I cannot explore this more expansive horizon in any detail
in this report, but let me in closing suggest one direction we need
to explore.
To signal the decisive break that I think we may need from the usual
bioethics frame, I want to draw attention to Martha Nussbaum’s
recent article in the journal Daedalus entitled, “Compassion
& Terror” (Nussbaum, 2003). Discussing Euripides’
play, Trojan Women, Nussbaum reflects on the fact that the
Greek poets returned obsessively to the sacking of Troy and the acts
of the “rapacious and murderous Greeks.” She explores
the poets’ compassionate imagining of the fate of Trojan women
and children to reflect on the conditions and limits of a compassionate
vision. Although Nussbaum is ultimately concerned about engendering
a compassionate vision for Americans in the face of terror?and particularly
compassion for innocent women and children far from our shores, her
analysis of compassion is thought-provoking in relation to stem cell
research.
Nussbaum notes that compassion is a complex emotion requiring a series
of judgments involving another person’s suffering or lack of
well-being. We must judge that someone has been harmed, that the harm
is serious, and that it was not deserved. Moreover, says Nussbaum,
Western tradition has stressed what could be called the “judgment
of similar possibilities.” In other words, “we have compassion
only insofar or we believe that the suffering person shares vulnerabilities
and possibilities with us” (Nussbaum, 2003, 15).
Now surely in just about everyone’s catalogue of human vulnerabilities
are illness, old age, and death. Yet, as we have just seen, stem cell
research might significantly transform the “human” experience
of illness and death, at least for some. If stem cell therapies were
to erode the notion of human nature or species membership, might they
not also erode some basic moral sensibilities? Mary Midgley, for example,
has argued that both the notion of human nature and that of human
rights are importantly tied to membership in our species because rights
are “supposed to guarantee the kind of life that all specimens
of Homo sapiens need” (Midgley, 2000, 9).
Although Nussbaum avoids the language of human nature, it is precisely
this sort of point that she highlights when she argues that compassion
requires the belief that others share vulnerabilities and possibilities
with us. Indeed, like Midgley, Nussbaum ties the notion of universal
human rights to important human functions and capabilities. The basic
idea, she says, is to ask what constitutes the characteristic activities
of human beings. In other words:
‘What does the human being do, characteristically,
as such?and not, say, as a member of a particular group, or a particular
local community?’ To put it another way, what are the forms
of activity, of doing and being, that constitute the human form
of life and distinguish it from other actual or imaginable forms
of life, such as the lives of animals and plants, or, on the other
hand, of immortal gods as imagined in myths and legends (which frequently
have precisely the function of delimiting the human)? (Nussbaum,
1995, 72)
Nussbaum notes that this inquiry proceeds by examining a wide variety
of self-interpretations and that comparing characteristic human
activities with non-human activities and, through myths and stories,
comparing humans and the gods is particularly helpful. For one thing,
such an inquiry helps us to define limits that derive from membership
in the world of nature.
Indeed, although Nussbaum is particularly attentive to the wide
variety of cultural interpretations of what it means to be human,
she insists that to ground any essentialist or universal notion
of human rights, one must attend to human biology. Although her
account of the human is neither ahistorical nor a priori, it is
linked to an “empirical study of a species-specific form of
life” (1995, 75). When she develops her account of central
human capabilities, she begins with the body. She writes:
We live all our lives in bodies of a certain sort, whose
possibilities and vulnerabilities do not as such belong to one human
society rather than another. These bodies, similar far more than
dissimilar (given the enormous range of possibilities) are our homes,
so to speak, opening certain options and denying others, giving
us certain needs and also certain possibilities for excellence.
The fact that any given human being might have lived anywhere and
belonged to any culture is a great part of what grounds our mutual
recognitions; this fact, in turn, has a great deal to do with the
general humanness of the body, its great distinctness from other
bodies. The experience of the body is culturally shaped, to be sure;
the importance we ascribe to its various functions is also culturally
shaped. But the body itself, not culturally variant in its nutritional
and other related requirements, sets limits on what can be experienced
and valued, ensuring a great deal of overlap. (Nussbaum, 1995, 76)
Nussbaum’s work both in identifying the judgments that underwrite
compassion and in tying an account of rights to human function and
capabilities that are presumably universal highlights what is at
stake, not merely with stem cell research but with a growing list
of biotechnological developments which appear to destabilize the
concept of human nature and which require that we think carefully
and hard about what it might mean for some humans to have access
to these technologies while other humans do not.15
At the very least, the combination of what Rabinow describes as
the biologicalization of identity around genetics rather than gender
and race with the possibility of manipulating that genetic identity
for those with the money or power to do so does not bode well for
securing wide-spread compassion across economic or technological
divides. Even more important, however, is the recognition that the
very notion of human rights may ultimately rest on the idea (and
what, until recently has always been the reality) of a natural human
condition that is relatively stable.
I believe that Nussbaum is correct when she claims that inquiring
into characteristic human activities and comparing these to non-human
activities helps us to define limits and thereby to promote human
flourishing. Unfortunately, what Susan Squier calls the “pluripotent
rhetoric” of stem cell research is that of limitless possibilities
(Squier, Liminal Lives). The ultimate limit, of course, is death
and yet even this limit appears illusory in some visions of our
biotech future.
It is worth noting in closing that William Safire’s New Year’s
Day column at the dawn of the twenty-first century, in January 2000,
was entitled “Why Die?” The longing behind this question
is neither new nor unfamiliar. What is new is that this longing
to escape the vulnerabilities and limitations of the body is united
with a technology that holds out the prospect of fundamentally changing
that body. Yet, I agree with Gerald McKenny that we need to ask
whether we wish to accept and promote a view of bodily vulnerability
as merely an obstacle to human flourishing, which ought to be overcome
at any cost (McKenny, 1998, 223).
Although a longing for invulnerability is perhaps a quintessentially
human trait, and although the quest to reduce the human suffering
wrought by illness and disease is morally admirable, there is no
mistaking the hubris behind the question, Why Die? Opponents of
stem cell research have, from the start, argued that there is a
kind of idolatry in a science that would reduce the human embryo
to just so much biological material. What I have tried to show in
this report is that such concerns need not be limited to those who
think that the early embryo is fully a person. Nor should this kind
of concern be limited to those who oppose stem cell research. I
do not think the early embryo is a person and I believe that both
embryonic and adult stem cell research should go forward under a
system of strict regulation. Nevertheless, I confess to being haunted
by the passages with which I began and I believe that future debates
on stem cell research must take very seriously the worries about
commodification and the possibility of fundamentally changing the
trajectory of a human life.16
Appendix A
Jimmy Margulies, Editorial Cartoonist
The Record, Hackensack, New Jersey
Cartoon used with permission of the artist.
_____________________
notes
- Given the current status of technology, deriving
human embryonic stem cells requires destroying embryos. If the
cells could be derived without the destruction of embryos or if
parthenogenetically stimulated eggs produced stem cells, issue
of status would almost certainly fade. Nevertheless, serious ethical
issues would still remain. This is one reason I believe it is
a mistake to focus narrowly on embryo status.
- Gene Outka has argued that there is an “internal
coherence” to views of the embryo, issues of complicity,
and views on adult stem cell research (Outka, 2002).
- Although the HERP report claimed that “it
is not the role of those who help form public policy to decide
which of these views [of the embryo] is correct, there is little
doubt that the panel adopted the pluralistic view. For that reason,
most commentators found the above claim disingenuous.
- Compare, for example,
the various statements that Richard M. Doerflinger has made on
the U. S. bishops’ behalf. See Doerflinger, 1988, 1998,
1999, 2001. Margaret Farley has argued that the Catholic preoccupation
with abortion has eroded its credibility on other important social
issues, including stem cell research. (See Farley, 2000).
- Another debate that is
at least partly shaped by focusing on embryo status revolves around
the question of complicity. For example, supporters of stem cell
research may harbor a residual uneasiness about endorsing the
destruction of human embryos, at least if the number of articles
in the literature explaining the concept of complicity with wrongdoing
is any indication. John Robertson, Ronald Green, and Thomas Shannon,
have all written on the issue of cooperation with evil in relation
to stem cell research. (Robertson, 1999; Green, 2002; Shannon,
2001; see also Kaveny, 2000; and Gilliam, 1997). To be sure, the
issue of complicity or cooperation with wrongdoing is a very traditional
one in moral philosophy and theological ethics. Still, if the
early embryo does not deserve the respect accorded persons and
if destroying the embryo is compatible with respecting it, then
deriving stem cells is not an act of wrongdoing and issues of
complicity do not arise. Cahill also emphasizes the way a liberal
individualist view of the person discounts the significance of
embodiment. I will return to this point below.
- Cahill also emphasizes
the way a liberal individualist view of the person discounts the
significance of embodiment. I will return to this point below.
- That both
those who view the embryo as a person and those who do not but
who insist on respect for the embryo, have been remarkably cavalier
with regard to the use of embryos in IVF programs can be seen
by the fact that there are currently over 400,000 embryos frozen
in the United States, a number we did not even know until quite
recently (Hoffman et al. in association with The Society for Assisted
Reproductive Technology and RAND, 2003).
- In a commentary
published in Nature, in September 2001, Edwards writes: “On
the verge of clinical application, stem cells offer a startlingly
fundamental approach to alleviating severe incurable human maladies.
Fondly believed to be a recent development, they have in fact
been part and parcel of human in-vitro fertilization (IVF) from
as long ago as 1962.”
- Dorff’s
responsum was accepted by the Committee on Law and Standards by
a vote of twenty-two to one in March 2002. On the basis of Dorff’s
responsum the Rabbinical Assembly passed a resolution in April
2003 supporting stem cell research for therapeutic purposes. (Resolution
in Support of Stem Cell Research and Education, April 2003: available
at www.rabassembly.org.)
- Alpers
and Lo draw the distinction between commodification and commercialization
as follows: “The issue of commodification involves treating
either human beings or symbols of human life as merchandise or
vendible goods. . . . Commercialization refers to the practice
of realizing large profits from the development and sale of techniques
or products that involve distinctive human material, such as embryos,
eggs, or tissue” (Alpers and Lo, 1995).
- Radin
quotes Georg Lukács on the reification of commodities and
the effects on human consciousness. Lukács writes: “The
transformation of the commodity relation into a thing of ‘ghostly
objectivity’ cannot therefore content itself with reduction
of all objects for the gratification of human needs to commodities.
It stamps its imprint upon the whole consciousness of man; his
qualities and abilities are no longer an organic part of his personality,
they are things which he can ‘own’ or ‘dispose
of’ like the various objects of the external world”
(Radin, 1996, 82). When we think about genes for enhancing memory
or muscle mass, it is worth keeping in mind Lukács’s
claim that human qualities and abilities may come to be thought
of as objects for sale in the external world.
- Erik
Parens has noted the importance of attending to the big picture
raised by stem cell work and how the politics of abortion has
obscured that picture. See Parens, 2000.
- In another
essay, Glannon argues that substantially increasing the human
life span would profoundly affect issues of personal identity
and thus a sense of personal responsibility for one’s action.
He ties his argument in interesting ways to the biology of memory
function (Glannon, “Identity”). For a classic philosophical
discussion of the problems associated with immortality, see Williams,
1973.
- Although
he is not discussing stem cell research explicitly, Paul Rabinow’s
discussion of technological change wrought during the last two
decades is worth noting. He writes: “In the United States,
for example, in the last two decades, while the most passionate
value conflicts have raged around abortion, a general reshaping
of the sites of production of knowledge has been occurring. To
cite the biotechnology industry, the growing stock of genomic
information, and the simple but versatile and potent manipulative
tools (exemplified by the polymerase chain reaction) is to name
a few key elements; a more complete list would include the reshaping
of American universities, the incessant acceleration in the computer
domains, and the rise of ‘biosociality’ as a prime
locus of identity?a biologicalization of identity different from
the older biological categories of the West (gender, age, race)
in that it is understood as inherently manipulable and re-formable”
(Rabinow, 1999, 13). A couple of pages later, he writes: “My
analysis points to the fact that the basic understanding and practices
of ‘bare life’ have been altered. The genome projects
(human, plant, animal, microorganismic) are demonstrating a powerful
approach to life’s constituent matter. It is now known that
DNA is universal among living beings. It is now known that DNA
is extremely manipulable. One consequence among many others is
that the boundaries between species need to be rethought; transgenic
animals made neither by God nor by the long-term processes of
evolution now exist (16).
- For a
science fiction exploration of this theme of selected genetic
enhancement, species boundary crossing see Octavia Butler, Dawn.
- A number
of people either helped with the preparation of this report or
provided feedback on an earlier draft. Thanks to Christa Adams,
Diana Fritz Cates, William FitzPatrick, James L. Lissemore, Charlie
Ponyik, Mary Jane Ponyik, Kristie Varga, Lisa Wells, and the ethics
writers group at John Carroll University.
___________
Alpers, Ann, and Bernard Lo. “Commodification and Commercialization
in Human Embryo Research.” Stanford Law and Policy Review,
vol. 6, no. 2 (1995): 40.
American Association for the Advancement of Science and Institute
for Civil Society. Stem Cell Research and Applications Monitoring
the Frontiers of Biomedical Research. (November 1999).
American Fertility Society Ethics Committee. “Ethical Considerations
of the New Reproductive Technologies in Light of Instruction on
the Respect for Human Life in Its Origin and on the Dignity of Procreation.”
Fertility and Sterility, vol. 49, (1988): Supplement.
Andrews, Lori, and Dorothy Nelkin. Body Bazaar: The Market for
Human Tissue in the Biotechnology Age. New York, NY: Crown
Publishers, 2001.
Annas, George J. Some Choice: Law, Medicine, and the Market.
New York: Oxford University Press, 1998.
Butler, Octavia E. Dawn. Boston, MA: Warner Books, 1997.
|
Cahill, Lisa Sowle. “Abortion, Autonomy, and Community.”
In Abortion: A Reader. Ed. Lloyd Steffen (Cleveland: Pilgrim
Press, 1996), 359-72.
______. “The Embryo and the Fetus: New Moral Contexts.”
Theological Studies, vol. 54 (1993): 124-42.
Callahan, Daniel. Hastings Center Report, vol. 25, no.
1 (1995): 39.
Collins, Francis S. “Testimony before the Presidents Council
on Bioethics.” (December 13, 2002). Available at: http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/dec02/session5.html.
Congregation for the Doctrine of the Faith, “Declaration on
Procured Abortion,” 1974.
______. “Donum vitae,” 1987.
Corea, Gena. The Mother Machine. New York: Harper and Row,
1985.
Doerflinger, Richard M. “Hearing on Stem Cell Research,”
Testimony of Richard M. Doerflinger on behalf of the Committee for
Pro-Life Activities United States Conference of Catholic Bishops
before the Subcommittee on Labor, Health, and Human Services, and
Education Senate Appropriations Committee (July 18, 2001): available
at http://www.usccb.org/prolife/issues/bioethic/stemcelltest71801.htm.
______. “Public Comment before the National Bioethics Advisory
Commission,” National Conference of Catholic Bishops (April
16, 1999): available at http://www.usccb.org/prolife/issues/bioethic/nbac.htm.
______. “Hearing on Legal Status of Embryonic Stem Cell Research,”
Testimony of Richard M. Doerflinger on behalf of the Committee for
Pro-Life Activities, National Conference of Catholic Bishops before
the Senate Appropriations Subcommittee on Labor, Health, and Education
(January 26, 1999): available at http://www.usccb.org/prolife/issues/bioethic/test99.htm.
______. “Testimony of Richard M. Doerflinger on behalf of
the Committee for Pro-Life Activities National Conference of Catholic
Bishops before the Senate Appropriations Subcommittee on Labor,
Health and Education,” Hearing on Embryonic Cell Research
(December 2, 1998): available at http://www.usccb.org/prolife/issues/bioethics/1202.htm.
______. “Public Comment: NIH Human Embryo Research Panel.”
United States Conference of Catholic Bishops (February 2, 1994).
______. “Ethical Problems in the Use of Tissues from Abortion
Victims,” Public Comment, Meeting of the Human Fetal Tissue
Transplantation Research Panel, (Bethesda, Maryland: National Institutes
of Health, September 14, 1988): available at http://www.usccb.org/prolife/issues/
fetalresearch/rd91488.htm.
Dorff, Elliot N. “Stem Cell Research.” Final Draft (August
2002).
Edwards, R. G. “IVF and the History of Stem Cells.”
Nature, vol. 413 (September 27, 2001): 349-51.
Edwards, Steptoe, and Purdy. “Fertilization and Cloning In
Vitro of Preovulation Human Oocytes.” Nature
277 (1970): 1307-1309.
Farley, Margaret A. “Roman Catholic Views on Research Involving
Human Embryonic Stem Cells.” The Human Embryonic Stem
Cell Debate: Science, Ethics, and Public Policy. Cambridge,
MA: The MIT Press, 2001. 113-18.
______. “The Church in the Public Forum: Scandal or Prophetic
Witness?” The Catholic Theological Society of America,
Proceedings of the Fifty-fifth Annual Convention, Vol. 55 (June
8-11, 2000): Presidential Address, 87-101.
FitzPatrick, William. “Surplus Embryos, Nonreproductive Cloning,
and the Intend/Foresee Distinction.” Hastings Center Report
(May-June 2003): 29-36.
Fukuyama, Francis. Our Posthuman Future. New York: Farrar,
Straus and Giroux, 2002.
Gearhart, John. “New Potential for Human Embryonic Stem Cells.”
Science, vol. 282 (November 6, 1998): available at: http://www.sciencemag.org/
cgi/content/full/282/5391/1061.
Geron Ethics Advisory Board. “Research with Human Embryonic
Stem Cells: Ethical Considerations.” Hastings Center Report,
vol. 29, no. 2 (March-April 1999).
Gilliam, Lynn. “Arguing by Analogy in the Fetal Tissue Debate.”
Bioethics, vol. 11, no. 5 (1997): 397-412.
Glannon, Walter. “Extending the Human Life Span.” Journal
of Medicine and Philosophy, vol. 27, no. 3 (2002): 339-54.
______. “Identity, Prudential Concern, and Extended Lives.”
Bioethics, vol. 16, no. 3 (2002): 266-83.
Green, Ronald M. “Benefiting from ‘Evil’: An Incipient
Moral Problem in Human Stem Cell Research.” Bioethics,
vol. 16, no. 6 (2002): 544-56.
______. The Human Embryo Research Debates: Bioethics in the
Vortex of Controversy. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
______. “At the Vortex of Controversy.” Kennedy
Institute of Ethics Journal vol. 4, no. 4 (1994): 345-56.
Hall, Stephen S. Merchants of Immortality: Chasing the Dream
of Human Life Extension. New York: Houghton Mifflin Company,
2003.
Hoffman, David I. et al. “Cryopreserved Embryos in the United
States and Their Availability for Research.” Fertility
and Sterility, vol. 79, no. 5 (May 2003): 1063-69.
Holland, Suzanne. “Contested Commodities at Both Ends of Life:
Buying and Selling Gametes, Embryos, and Body Tissues,” Kennedy
Institute of Ethics Journal, vol. 11, no. 3 (2001): 266.
Kass, Leon R. “Ageless Bodies, Happy Souls: Biotechnology
and the Pursuit of Perfection.” The New Atlantis,
no. 1 (spring 2003).
______. Life, Liberty and the Defense of Dignity: The Challenge
for Bioethics. San Francisco, CA: Encounter Books, 2002.
Kaveny, M. Cathleen. “Appropriation of Evil: Cooperation’s
Mirror Image,” Theological Studies, vol. 61, no.
2 (June 2000): 280-313.
Knowles, Lori P. “Property, Progeny, and Patents.” Hastings
Center Report, vol 29. no. 2 (1999): 38.
Kuhn, Vanessa. “Stem Cells: Equity or Ownership?” The
American Journal of Bioethics, vol. 2, no. 1 (winter 2002):
2.
Lauritzen, Paul. “Neither Person nor Property: Embryo Research
and the Status of the Early Embryo,” America (March
26, 2001).
______. Cloning and the Future of Human Embryo Research.
New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
______. “Expanding the Debate over Stem Cell Research,”
Dialog: A Journal of Theology, vol. 41, no. 3, (fall 2002):
238-39.
Lebacqz, Karen. “Stem Cells and Justice,” Dialog,
vol. 41, no. 3 (fall 2002).
______. “On the Elusive Nature of Respect.” The
Human Embryonic Stem Cell Debate: Science, Ethics, and Public Policy.
Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2001. 149-162.
Lewis, C. S. The Abolition of Man. New York: The Macmillan
Company, 1947.
Macklin, Ph.D., Ruth. “Ethics, Politics, and Human Embryo
Stem Cell Research.” Women’s Health Issues,
vol. 10, no. 3 (May/June 2000): 111-15.
Magnus, David, Arthur Caplan, and Glenn McGee, ed. In Who Owns
Life? Amherst, New York: Prometheus Books, 2002.
McCormick, R. A. “Who or What is the Preembryo?” In
Corrective Vision: Explorations in Moral Theology. Kansas
City: Sheed & Ward, 1994.
McGee, Glenn, and Elizabeth Banger. “Ethical Issues in the
Patenting and Control of Stem Cell Research.” In Who Owns
Life? Ed. David Magnus, Arthur Caplan, and Glenn McGee. Amherst,
New York: Prometheus Books, 2002. 243-264.
McKenny, Gerald P. “Enhancements and the Ethical Significance
of Vulnerability.” In Enhancing Human Traits: Ethical
and Social Implications. Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University
Press, 1998. 222-37.
McKibben, Bill. Enough: Staying Human in an Engineered Age.
New York: Henry Holt and Company, 2003.
McLean, Margaret. “Stem Cells: Justice at the Gate.”
Dialog, vol. 41, no. 3 (fall 2002).
Meilaender, Gilbert. “Terra es animata: On Having
a Life.” Hastings Center Report, vol. 23, no. 4 (July-August
1993): 25-32.
Meyer, Michael J., and Lawrence J. Nelson. “Respecting What
We Destroy: Reflections on Human Embryo Research.” Hastings
Center Report, vol. 31, no. 1 (January/February 2001).
Midgley, Mary. “Biotechnology and Monstrosity: Why We Should
Pay Attention to the ‘Yuk Factor.’” Hastings
Center Report, vol. 30, no. 5 (2000): 7-15.
National Academy of Sciences. Stem Cells and the Future of Regenerative
Medicine. Washington D.C.: National Academies Press, 2002.
National Bioethics Advisory Commission. Ethical Issues in Human
Stem Cell Research. vol. 1. Rockville, Maryland: NBAC, 1999.
Nelkin, Dorothy, and Lori B. Andrews. Body Bazaar: The Market
for Human Tissue in the Biotechnology Age. New York, NY: Crown
Publishing, 2001.
National Institutes of Health, “Report of the Human Embryo
Research Panel.” (September 1994).
Nussbaum, Martha C. “Compassion and Terror.” Daedalus,
vol. 128, no. 4 (winter 2003): 10-26.
______. “Human Capabilities, Female Human Beings.” Women,
Culture, and Development: A Study of Human Capabilities. Ed.
Martha C. Nussbaum and Jonathan Glover (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
1995), 61-104.
Outka, Gene. “The Ethics of Stem Cell Research.” Kennedy
Institute of Ethics Journal vol. 12, no. 2 (2002): 175-213.
Parens, Ph.D., Erik. “Embryonic Stem Cells and the Bigger
Reprogenetic Picture.” Women’s Health Issues,
vol. 10, no. 3 (May/June 2000): 116-20.
Pontifical Academy for Life. “On the Production and the Scientific
and Therapeutic Use of Human Embryonic Stem Cells.” Vatican
(August 25, 2000): available at http://www.petersnet.net/browse/
3021.htm.
Rabinow, Paul. French DNA: Trouble in Purgatory. Chicago,
IL: The University of Chicago Press, 1999.
Radin, Margaret Jane. Contested Commodities. Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press, 1996.
Resnik, David. “The Commercialization of Human Stem Cells:
Ethical and Policy Issues.” Health Care Analysis,
vol. 10 (2002):127-54.
Robertson, John A. “Ethics and Policy in Embryonic Stem Cell
Research.” Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal, vol.
9, no. 2 (1999): 109-36.
Roche, J.D., Patricia A. and Michael A. Grodin, M.D., F.A.A.P. “The
Ethical Challenge of Stem Cell Research.” Women’s
Health Issues, vol. 10, no. 3 (May/June 2000): 136-39.
Ryan, Maura. “Creating Embryos for Research: On Weighing Symbolic
Costs.” Cloning and the Future of Human Embryo Research.
Ed. Paul Lauritzen. New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
______. The Ethics and Economics of Assisted Reproduction.
Washington, D.C.: Georgetown University Press, 2001.
______. “The Politics and Ethics of Human Embryo and Stem
Cell Research.” Women’s Health Issues, vol.
10, no. 3 (May/June 2000): 105-10.
Safire, William. “Why Die?” The New York Times (January
1, 2000).
Shamblott, M. J. et al. “Derivation of Pluripotent Stem Cells
from Cultured Human Primordial Germ Cells.” Proceedings
of the National Academy of Sciences, vol. 95 (1998): 13726-31.
Shannon, T. A., and A. B. Walter. “Reflections on the Moral
Status of the Preembryo.” Theological Studies, vol.
51 (1990): 603-26.
Shannon, Thomas. “Human Embryonic Stem Cell Therapy.”
Theological Studies, vol. 62, (2001): 811-24.
Squier, Susan. Liminal Lives, unpublished manuscript.
Steinbock, Bonnie. “Respect for Human Embryos.” In Cloning
and the Future of Human Embryo Research. Ed. Paul Lauritzen.
New York: Oxford University Press, 2001.
______. “What Does ‘Respect for Embryos’ Mean
in the Context of Stem Cell Research?” Women’s Health
Issues, vol. 10, no. 3 (May/June 2000): 127-30.
______. Life before Birth: The Moral and Legal Status of Embryos
and Fetuses. New York, NY: Oxford University Press, 1992.
Tauer, Carol. “Responsibility and Regulation: Reproductive
Technologies, Cloning, and Embryo Research.” In Cloning
and the Future of Human Embryo Research. Ed. Paul Lauritzen.
Oxford University Press: New York, 2001. 153.
______. “Preimplantation Embryos, Research Ethics, and Public
Policy.” Bioethics Forum, vol. 11, no. 3 (1995):
30-37.
Thomson, James A. et al. “Embryonic Stem Cell Lines Derived
from Human Blastocysts.” Science, vol. 282 (November
6, 1998).
Van Overwalle, Geertrui. Study on the Patenting of Inventions
Related to Human Stem Cell Research. Luxembourg: Office for
Official Publications of the European Communities, 2002. 23.
Waldby, Ph.D., Catherine, and Susan Squier, Ph.D. “Ontogeny,
Ontology, and Phylogeny: Embryonic Life and Stem Cell Technologies.”
Configurations (Forthcoming).
Warren, Mary Anne. Moral Status: Obligations to Persons and
Other Living Things. New York, NY: Oxford University Press,
1997.
Williams, Bernard. Problems of the Self: Philosophical Papers
1956-1972. Cambridge, England: Cambridge University Press,
1973.
Wolfe, Tom. Hooking Up. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus and
Giroux, 2001.
Zoloth, Laurie. “Jordon’s Banks: A View from the First
Years of Human Embryonic Stem Cell Research.” In The Human
Embryonic Stem Cell Debate. Ed. by Suzanne Holland, Karen Lebacqz,
and Laurie Zoloth. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, 2001. 238.
|