This topic was discussed at the Council's October
2003 meeting. This working paper was prepared by staff solely
to aid discussion, and does not represent the official views of the
Council or of the United States Government.
Staff Working Paper
Monitoring Stem Cell Research: The Ethical
Debates Reviewed The announcement of the Bush
Administration's human embryonic stem cell research funding policy
in the summer of 2001 certainly did not end the debates surrounding
the issue. The policy offered a particular target to which participants
in the debate could react, but the basic questions involved in assessing
how the federal government should approach embryonic stem cell research
remained just as relevant, and just as controversial, as they had
been before. In this paper, we offer an overview of that still continuing
debate. Without attempting to provide anything like a full account
of different positions and arguments, we hope, rather, to point
to the chief fault lines in the argument-to the issues that any
interested citizen might wish to ponder. First, we will outline
the general form of the moral argument, noting that-although other
issues are certainly also in play-the central issue has often turned
on the moral standing of the human embryo. Second, we will discuss
specific questions and critiques regarding the Administration's
policy, as those have emerged in public discussion. Finally, we
will discuss the moral standing of the human embryo, seeking again
to outline the chief fault lines in that continuing debate.
While we will raise these arguments and counterarguments, problems,
questions, and concerns, our purpose in this paper is not finally
to assess the validity of the competing claims and to arrive at
a conclusion, but-in line with the Council's charge to monitor developments
in this area-to present them more or less as they have appeared
in the public debates of the past several years. This way of proceeding
has one especially prominent drawback: it tends to present all arguments
as equivalent in their importance and prevalence. We will seek to
avoid this whenever possible, and to offer some sense of which have
been the key components of the public debate.
I. The nature of the moral argument
In casual conversation and sometimes in more theoretical reasoning,
moral questions are often analyzed under the metaphors of "weighing"
or "balancing." These metaphors, together with the language of
"value(s)," gives rise to a kind of moral reasoning familiar to
all of us and commonly used by all of us. We weigh the value of
various possibilities over against each other; we balance competing
interests. Quite often, to be sure, it may not really be clear
how this balancing actually takes place, and it may not be obvious
that there is any scale on which the various values at stake can
really be weighed. But the metaphor is a common one, used by almost
all of us at least sometimes.
We also use another related but contrasting kind of moral language,
however-what we can call the language of overriding concerns, or
sometimes perhaps the language of "rights." Most often we use this
language to suggest that certain claims have a kind of superseding
quality, and that it would be inappropriate simply to think of these
claims as one more "value" to be placed on a scale of competing
values. These sorts of principles have a kind of trump in our moral
reasoning. They offer claims to be protected even against actions
that might seem to realize important values.
These two approaches to moral reasoning are by no means mutually
exclusive, and in many cases moral judgments call upon us to employ
both at once. While some ideal or principle may be held essential
to the judgment, other goods, balanced together, shape the form
or outcome of the judgment as well.
This has certainly been the case in the public debate over federal
funding of human embryonic stem cell research. In one sense, almost
all observers have agreed that federal policy must seek a certain
balance between two competing interests: the progress of medical
research and treatment, and respect for nascent human life. Indeed,
President Bush himself framed the issue in these terms, saying a
few weeks before his decision was announced that his policy would
"need to balance value and respect for life with the promise of
science, and the hope of saving life."1
But not all participants in the debates have had the same idea of
what such balance should entail, and therefore how weight might
be assigned to the competing demands.
For some, the degree of medical promise should decisively affect
the degree of government support for embryonic stem cell research,
and therefore the degree of protection afforded to nascent human
life. This approach suggests that the decisive data (though of course
not the exclusive ones) in establishing policy must be scientific
data about what might be achieved with human embryonic stem cells.2
The greater the promise of the research, the more support it should
receive, and the more it might outweigh the reasons offered for
fundamentally opposing the techniques involved.3
In this sense, the question is truly understood at its foundation
as a balancing of competing goods, and the good given the most prominence
and weight is the very great good of medical progress toward the
relief of suffering. A great deal of the arguments against the Administration's
policy have begun from this premise-explicitly or implicitly-and
have proceeded by laying out the possible medical benefits of embryonic
stem cell research, or the harms (to patients or to American science)
of withholding support. We shall review a number of these lines
of argument in more detail below, but it is worth noting that most
of them begin from the assumption that the policy decision at hand
ought rightly to be based on a reasoned balancing of crucial moral
concerns-all of which matter, but none of which overrides the others
in any decisive way.
Others, however, have suggested that the position of opponents
of research rests upon claims to a principle of inviolability, and
therefore-if these claims are valid-could not simply be outweighed
by the promise of research.4
In this view, the basic principle that the federal government should
not support the destruction of human embryos is to be upheld, regardless
of the promise of research. What remains then to be balanced is
the extent to which the government might go out of its way to advance
the secondary moral aim-the progress of medical research-within
the bounds of the principle.5
In this sense, the underlying question is understood as governed
above all by one overriding principle, and only the extent and some
particular provisions of the policy are left up to an assessment
of the moral weight of other priorities. Proponents of the various
forms of this position generally argue that the claim of the human
embryo to protection presents us with a fundamental duty, to be
ignored only in extreme circumstances, rather than just with one
good to be balanced off against others.6
In presenting the matter this way, adherents of this view consciously
emulate the model of human subjects research, which offers an example
of seeking to advance knowledge and cures but keeping from trespassing
upon the grounds of human life, safety, and dignity.7
The example of the nearly universal adherence of researchers to
human subject protections over the past several decades, these commentators
suggest, demonstrates that the needs of research are not always
treated as paramount, and that not only the general public but also
the scientific community recognizes instances in which research
work-however important it is-must be limited.8
Researchers do not balance off the interests of human subjects against
the importance of their work; rather they respect a principled boundary,
the importance of which trumps even the most promising experiment.
For some defenders of the embryo, the prospect of embryo research
raises similar concerns, and so many argue that this issue too should
be decided on the basis of a hard rule, and not by a tally on a
balance sheet of benefits.9
But this analogy holds only if the analogy of the human embryo
and the human research subject holds. Therefore, which group has
the better argument with regard to the basic character of the issue
before us may depend, in large part, on one's understanding of the
human embryo; and so in one sense the question of whether the ethical
challenge at issue ought to be understood essentially as a matter
of balance or largely as a matter of principle itself depends upon
the moral status of the embryo. That question of the moral status
of the human embryo, as we shall see later in this paper, is by
no means the only relevant question, but it may well be the most
central and critical question, and the one most responsible for
giving shape to the different basic approaches that different participants
in the public debate have pursued, and for their differing views
on the essential nature of the moral issue at stake, and of which
moral goods should be weighted most heavily, or should supersede
other concerns.
We turn next to arguments regarding that very question: which
moral concerns should be given priority in shaping government policy
toward human embryonic stem cell research.
II. The moral aims of policy
A significant part of the public debate surrounding human embryonic
stem cell research policy has involved differing views of just which
aims or ideals should most directly motivate policymakers in this
arena. The Bush Administration's funding policy-while it appears
to seek some balance between protection of human embryos and advancement
of scientific research-seems to take as its overriding principle
the concern that human embryos not be violated or destroyed. But
a number of commentators in recent years-and of course particularly
those who ascribe lesser degrees of moral status to the human embryo-have
proposed alternative principles for policy.
a) The Importance of Relieving Suffering
Many observers argue that one such competing principle is the
duty to seek to relieve the pain and suffering of others-the moral
aim that motivates the work of biomedical science. This aim is
broadly, indeed almost universally, shared. Indeed, the Administration's
own policy as outlined by its advocates, while it seeks to advance
the protection of nascent human life, at the same time explicitly
seeks also to advance medical research as far as is morally permissible.
Some commentators argue that the Administration has chosen to emphasize
the wrong one of these aims as the governing principle of its approach.
This case has generally taken as its starting point the universal
desire to relieve the suffering of those afflicted by pain and disease.
The cause of curing disease has a human face, the face of a loved
one or neighbor, bent under the suffering of an incompletely understood
and untreated disease. As a result, the motivation to know is linked
to a burning desire to relieve. How, wonder many commentators, could
anyone think of withholding support for research toward therapies
for such devastating diseases and conditions as spinal cord injury,
diabetes, and Parkinson's?10
Surely, the pain and suffering of those in need should outweigh
concerns for human embryos frozen in a laboratory, argue advocates
of this view.11
One notable strategy in support of this view in the past several
years has involved claims about disease prevalence, accompanied
by assertions that those who would obstruct the public funding of
research that might help patients suffering from such diseases must
bear the blame for the suffering and perhaps the deaths of such
patients.12
But some opponents have argued that if this line of reasoning is
to be abided then, in principle, any individual could compel us
to perform otherwise immoral actions by threatening to do some evil
if we did not comply.13
In most cases, however, the arguments for founding federal funding
policy in the importance of biomedical research do not take the
extreme form of blaming opponents for the suffering of the sick.
Rather, they speak to the promise of bringing relief to those who
most need it, and point to the immense benefits already delivered
to us by modern medicine, and argue that the federal government
should advance this cause in whatever ways it reasonably can. Many
advocates of this view express concern for the respectful treatment
of nascent human life, but argue that the claims of human embryos-whether
in general, or in particular circumstances, like those stored in
fertility clinic freezers-cannot simply trump the claims of promising
medical research.14
In response, one prominent commentator has argued in broad terms
against the underlying assumption that the demands of biomedical
research should somehow be seen as "imperative." Such work, he contends,
should not be seen as inherently imperative, and its claims for
support may be overridden even by a level of concern for nascent
human life that does not suppose that embryos possess full human
moral status. He suggests that it is not at all obvious that individuals
or the government have a responsibility to support such research,
or that such a responsibility would override other moral duties.15
Others argue that the case in favor of something approaching an
imperative need for support of human embryonic stem cell research
is undermined by the present rules governing the treatment of human
subjects in research. These rules prohibit certain sorts of procedures-however
beneficial they might be to the cause of understanding and curing
disease-if they endanger or violate the dignity of human subjects
of the research. Those who argue that the importance of medical
research and treatment should override the desire to protect human
embryos presumably would not propose to override human subject protections
in research on children or adults. They would likely approach the
matter differently because they do not consider human embryos and
children or adults to be equivalent. The difference, therefore,
has to do not with the importance of research, but with the status
of nascent human life, which again turns out to be the fundamental
point at issue.16
It is clear, nonetheless, that the moral claims of medical research
and treatment are among the most powerful in the debate over human
embryonic stem cell policy, and are acknowledged as profoundly important
even by those who do not finally take them to be decisive. Most
arguments in opposition to the present funding policy are grounded
in one or another of these claims.
b) Freedom to Research
Other opponents of the present policy argue that not only the
purpose or the product of research, but also the freedom to conduct
research itself offers the principle by which federal policy ought
to be guided. They regard restraints on scientific research as inherently
offensive and generally unjustifiable.17
The cherished ideals of freedom of thought, freedom of conscience,
and specifically in this context, freedom of inquiry, trump concerns
over the moral status of human embryos, the argument runs.18
The most common claim for the protection of research as a basic
right involves some form of an appeal to the First Amendment's protection
of free speech, interpreted through the years to cover free expression
and perhaps freedom of inquiry and thought.19
Some argue that research is a form of expression, particularly when
it is politically or socially controversial, and when restraints
upon it are imposed for moral reasons.20
"One could make the case that research is expressive activity and
that the search for knowledge is intrinsically within the First
Amendment's protection for freedom of thought," says one ethicist.21
Opponents, however, contend that this claim has never been tested
in the courts, and seems far-fetched. Most currently controversial
biological research involves the manipulation of living matter,
rather than the mere observation of natural objects. It is therefore
as much action as expression, as much creation as discovery. It
is difficult to see, they argue, how such activity (as opposed to
the reporting of the results of such activity) could be classified
as a form of expression. "Scientists may have the right to pursue
knowledge in any way they want cognitively, intellectually," argues
one observer, "but when it comes to concrete action in the lab,
that becomes conduct and the First Amendment protection for that
is far, far weaker."22
Moreover, argues at least one commentator, even if one did stipulate
that research activity is to be protected from government restriction,
it is far from clear that limits on federal funding would constitute
such a restriction. Indeed, legislative and judicial precedents
suggest it would not. The government routinely refrains from funding
activities it otherwise permits, or even guards as constitutionally
protected rights. A line of Supreme Court decisions stretching from
1977 to 1991, dealing with abortion and government funding, established
the principle that the constitution does not require government
to fund even those activities that the Constitution protects.23
The only issue in the present debate is funding, and so the protected
status of an activity seems not be a determining factor.24
And finally, some critics of the case for a right to research
point once more to the fact that scientific research-both that conducted
in private and (especially) that conducted with government funding-is
usually subject to certain restrictions already, particularly with
regard to human subject protections. The proposition that embryo
research should not be subject to such restrictions on funding or
practice hinges on an argument about the sort of subject that the
human embryo constitutes, rather than about the standing of research
as such.25
The question, therefore, is once more the question of the status
of the embryo.
c) The Moral Status of the Human Embryo However they
approach the matter, then, a substantial number of those engaged
in the debate over federal funding policy seem to be brought back
to the fundamental question of the moral status of the human embryo.
Any approach to the question of federal funding of embryonic stem
cell research which aims to focus primarily on something other than
this question of the moral status of the embryo seems almost by
necessity to assume that the human embryo is not possessed of fully
human moral status.
On the other hand, if the human embryo ought rightly to be treated
as inviolable-as some have argued-then questions of balancing other
goods or giving priority to other principles are largely rendered
moot. And so to many (though as we shall discuss, not all) observers, the central questions in this arena
would appear to be those that surround the human embryo: how ought
we to think about and act toward the human embryo? And are all human
embryos to be treated the same, or are some, because of their circumstances,
origins, or prospects, to be treated differently from others?
We shall review some of the positions expressed on these critical
questions below. But the Administration's policy at least claims
a grounding in one such position-the argument that human embryos
ought not to be violated, and therefore that federal funds should
not support such violations. A number of those who have written
about the policy in recent years-including both supporters and critics-have
assessed it on these grounds, and judged it against its own claims
and terms. As a result, several general categories of criticism
of the policy itself, in its particulars, have emerged.
III. The character of the policy
Aside from the general questions of which aims ought most reasonably
to guide federal policy, a great many observers in the past two
years have of course also assessed the particulars of the administration's
funding policy, on scientific, political, and moral terms. Critics
have generally taken on the policy through one or more of three
general lines of argument: that it is arbitrary, that it is unsustainable,
and that it is inconsistent. Defenders of the policy, meanwhile,
have usually sought to answer the critics along these same lines.
a) Arbitrary One quite common line of argument criticizes
the present funding policy as essentially arbitrary, because it
relies on what is deemed a capricious cutoff date. Embryos destroyed
on August 8, 2001, can serve as resources for federally funded research,
but those destroyed the next day are not eligible. The only difference
is the date, argue some critics, and what is morally significant
about that particular date? If the policy of funding human embryonic
stem cell research serves a genuine good, these commentators suggest,
would it not be equally good regardless of when the cells lines
were derived? Would it not, therefore, make sense to permit funding
for all cell lines derived on either side of the date, provided
they are otherwise eligible?28
And if funding of research is unacceptable, then it should simply
be prohibited, regardless of when cell lines were first derived.29
"It is difficult to see," writes one critic, "what ethical reasoning
would commend a policy that takes as its central distinction the
time chosen for political convenience to deliver a presidential
address."30
Meanwhile, some supporters of the policy contend that while the
cut-off date of August 9, 2001, certainly has no inherent moral
significance, it is imbued with meaning by the simple fact that
it was the date of the announcement of the policy. That date, in
other words, was the line between past embryo-destruction, which
could no longer be undone, and future embryo destruction, which
could still be influenced by the federal government's funding rules.
If the aim was to avoid encouraging or incentivizing the future
destruction of human embryos, they argue, then drawing a hard line
between past and future would be crucial.31
That line could only reasonably be drawn at the moment of the decision's
announcement (or before it), since drawing it at some point in the
future would create a powerful incentive to quicken the pace of
work until the cut-off date arrives. The date, they say, is therefore
not a morally arbitrary marker in the context of the policy, but
is rather a crucial element of the logic of the policy.32
b) Unsustainable A further, and more common, critique
of the current policy suggests that its approach cannot be expected
to hold over time, and that it will prove unsustainable fairly quickly.
One form of this argument suggests that the policy has created
a situation in which scientists may make some progress using existing
stem cell lines, but would then be prohibited from capitalizing
on what they learn and making further progress using further lines
with federal funds. As the editors of the Washington Post
put it: "Mr. Bush's compromise policy will be a reasonable one
only as long as the existing lines are capable of supporting the
research scientists need to perform."33
Indeed, some have argued that by explicitly encouraging and speaking
of the potential medical value of human embryonic stem cell research,
the president himself created the circumstances that will make the
constraints of the policy unsustainable. "Bush's decision was at
its core an endorsement of the promise of human embryonic stem cells
and their importance to the fledgling field of regenerative medicine,"
wrote one critic, and if that is the core message of the decision,
then the resulting policy seems insufficient.34
Others have argued on more practical grounds that, regardless
of the principle expounded by the policy, its effects will be unbearable
for American scientists, and will force a reconsideration.35
The limits placed on funding in the current policy, several observers
have predicted, will seriously hamper and hold back embryonic stem
cell research work in the United States, perhaps causing prominent
scientists to leave the country in search of greater support abroad.36
If that were to occur, it is argued, the policy would prove genuinely
damaging to American science, and therefore to the national interest,
and would need to be changed.37
In response to this specific point, some defenders of the policy
have noted that for the time being there has not been news of any
notable migration of prominent stem-cell researchers to foreign
countries, and that American researchers can continue to work with
private funds.38
But even apart from worries about a "brain-drain" in the field,
some have argued that a lack of funding is preventing progress in
research, and discouraging even private funding in the field,39
and that the lines made available simply will not be enough,40
or indeed that they have already proven insufficient.41
As scientists make their case that important work is being hampered,
it is argued, the policy will prove unsustainable politically and
practically.42
A similar argument has also been made in nearly the opposite terms.
That is, some have said that if or when ongoing embryonic stem cell
research produces a spectacular breakthrough in understanding or
treating disease, the pressure to alter the policy would prove unstoppable.43
This way, whether the future brings announcements of great progress,
or whether it brings no news of advances, the result will be pressure
for a policy that funds research more broadly.
Those defenders of the policy who have addressed these claims
of unsustainabilty, have generally pointed to the policy's stated
grounding in principle-a principle that would not change in light
of scientific advances. "The general question is, well, will these
cell lines be enough?," one observer has noted, "and a complicity
argument [like that at the heart of the policy] will only work if
the answer to that question is well, I guess they'll have to
be enough."44
Or, put differently, if the policy is founded primarily in a judgment
about the moral status of the human embryo, and only secondarily
in a judgment about the value of embryonic stem cell research, then
advances in research alone would not be sufficient to overturn it.
If it is right before such advances, it would still be valid after45-though
again, of course, whether it is right to begin with is itself a
point of great contention.
c) Inconsistent In responding to critiques like those
just discussed, defenders of the Administration's policy generally
point to the principles that define the approach of the policy,
as partially laid out in a previous staff paper (prepared for the
Council's September meeting). But some criticism of the policy has
directed itself precisely to that claim of consistent adherence
to principle, and proposed that the policy is morally contradictory,
or at least inconsistent, in its own terms.
One common form of this charge of inconsistency has to do with
the distinction drawn in policy between public and private funding.
The Administration's policy addresses itself only to federal funding
of embryo research, and not to the conduct of such research in the
private sector. But the source of funding, this line of criticism
suggests, could have no bearing on the question of the embryo's
moral status. If federal funding for research that destroys human
embryos is so troublesome, then why should such research be allowed
to proceed when privately funded? Acting to restrict one but not
the other may be prudent, but it seems inconsistent.46
Though the president cannot simply ban embryo research himself,
he could attempt to convince the Congress to do so, and he could
have done so as an element of his funding policy decision. But he
did not. In fact, some prominent defenders of the policy might be
said to contribute to these doubts about its grounding in consistent
principle, by making the fact of ongoing private research an element
of their defense.47
There may be some political or structural reasons for drawing
a distinction in federal policy between what is funded and what
is permitted-questions of federalism and other legal realities no
doubt enter the picture, and indeed those who publicly defend the
human embryo are, in many cases, actively seeking prohibitions on
all embryo research in individual states.i
But, critics point out, they generally say little on the larger
question of permissibility at the federal level. By making so much
of the importance of funding, these critics argue, the policy puts
into question the importance of preventing embryo destruction more
generally, and so the importance of the policy's declared guiding
principle.
A related criticism contends that the distinction drawn between
techniques in which human embryos are destroyed and techniques that
follow on the heels of that destruction is itself inconsistent-a
distinction without a difference, drawn for political cover.48
"Pretending that the scientists who do stem cell research are in
no way complicit in the destruction of embryos is just wrong, a
smoke and mirrors game," writes one critic, "it would be much better
to take the issue on directly by making the argument that destroying
embryos in this way is morally justified-is, in effect, a just sacrifice
to make."49
Similar objections have also been raised by observers on the other
side of the embryo question, who believe embryo destruction is not
morally justified, and that the present policy does not sufficiently
distance the federal government from support of such destruction.
"The federal government, for the first time in history, will support
research that relies on the destruction of some defenseless human
beings for the possible benefit to others," one critic contended
in the immediate wake of the August 9, 2001 announcement, "however
such a decision is hedged about with qualifications, it allows our
nation's research enterprise to cultivate a disrespect for human
life."50
A further critique of the policy on grounds of consistency focuses
more particularly on the specific elements of the claim to non-complicity,
detailed in an earlier staff paper, prepared for the Council's September
2003 meeting. If, as many of its advocates argue, the policy takes
embryo destruction to be essentially a morally evil act, and if
its provisions aim to make use of the irreversible consequences
of that act without in any way abiding the act itself, then, critics
contend, it is curious that the policy would insist on requiring
that eligible stem cell lines must have been obtained from embryos
originally intended for reproduction, with donor consent, and with
no financial inducements. If embryo destruction is in principle
a wrong, and if the policy's provisions keep the federal government
from complicity in that wrong, then why should it matter how precisely
the wrong was originally committed? The presence of these conditions,
it is argued, suggests that the policy is not in fact based in a
consistent and principled adherence to the proposition that human
embryos should be treated as inviolable.51
In response to this particular concern, some have argued that
the qualifying conditions reflect a secondary commitment to traditional
principles of human subject and embryo research, rather than a contradiction
of the fundamental commitment to avoiding the destruction of nascent
human life. To distinguish among evils, it is argued, is not to
deny that the distinct acts are all unacceptable.52
Another observer has suggested that the conditions-which reflect
the minimal standards for embryo donation for research before the
implementation of the policy-are an expression of the fact that
embryo destruction undertaken before the policy's implementation
was itself still subject to certain ethical rules, and that even
in rejecting the legitimacy of the act itself, it is still reasonable
to recognize the value of the rules. The policy, it is argued, itself
established a new standard, but still takes account of previous
standards.53
In response to the more general critique on grounds of inconsistency,
defenders of the policy, within and outside the Administration,
have voiced an understanding of the present policy as arising out
of a prudential effort to uphold a principle. The policy, as articulated
by these defenders, aims at least minimally to advance the ideal
that nascent human life ought not be violated, by assuring public
non-complicity in the destruction of human embryos, while seeking,
as much as reasonably possible within the bounds of the principle,
to benefit from the results of that embryo destruction that has
already occurred and can no longer be undone.54
As President Bush put it in his August 9, 2001, address announcing
the policy, "This allows us to explore the promise and potential
of stem cell research without crossing a fundamental moral line,
by providing taxpayer funding that would sanction or encourage further
destruction of human embryos that have at least the potential for
life."55
That "fundamental moral line" is an aspect of the more general
principle that human embryos should be treated as inviolable. The
policy, argue some of its advocates, therefore aims to put into
practice that moral principle, even if it does not do so on every
possible front, or to the greatest possible extent.
IV. The Moral Status of the Embryo
Many elements (though, as some commentators take care to note,
not all elements) of the ongoing debate about federal funding of
human embryonic stem cell research seem, as we have reviewed them,
to come down to a basic disagreement about the nature, character,
and moral status of the human embryo. The general view of the embryo
said to underlie the present policy, while it may be supported by
the president, and apparently by a majority of the Congress, is
by no means the consensus view of the country, or even clearly a
majority view.
Public debates over the moral status and appropriate treatment
of the human embryo have been quite contentious and divisive in
recent years. In part, this had to do with their almost inevitable
entanglement with the abortion debate in America, itself a deep
and thorny controversy. In part, too, this has had to do with the
fact that the question of the moral status of the human embryo touches
on a great many other fundamental moral and existential questions
involving human origins, human dignity, the moral significance of
our biology, and its relation to a great many traditional and widely
shared moral teachings. Differences of opinion on the moral status
of the embryo often suggest differences on these larger questions
of overall worldview.56
Nonetheless, the question of the human embryo has been taken by
nearly all commentators to be amenable to human reason and argument,
and a lively debate has raged despite (or perhaps precisely because
of) these widely diverging starting assumptions.
The question of the moral status of the human embryo has, in the
public arena, often been summed up in the question "when does life
begin?" This question suggests something of the quandary, though
the academic and intellectual debate generally takes a somewhat
more nuanced question as its starting point. That question takes
as its premise the fact that we seek to treat born human beings
(from newborns, through adults) as meriting protection and, in effect,
inviolable. It then asks what relation human embryos possess to
these live-born human individuals, and therefore whether they too
should be treated as inviolable, or not.58
The first and most common recourse in seeking an answer to such
questions has been human biology, and particularly embryology. In
a certain sense, this is peculiar, since we do not base our moral
judgments about how to treat adult human beings first and foremost
on their biological characteristics. Indeed, our society takes great
pride in its progress toward treating people equally despite biological
differences. And yet, the embryo is largely known to us through
the methods and tools of modern biology, and so it often proves
easiest for individuals on all sides of the issue to speak about
it in those terms. Nearly all participants in the dispute therefore
make some recourse to modern biology, whether to claim it illustrates
the embryo's essential continuity with and similarity to human beings
at other stages of life, or to argue that it shows profound and
meaningful discontinuities between embryos and live-born persons.
While we examine these differing contentions, it is crucial to
remember-as several commentators in recent years have noted-that
the biology itself is not necessarily decisive morally.58
A recognition of biological continuity would perhaps go some way
toward disqualifying the claims of certain biological markers or
states to demonstrate the permissibility of embryo-destruction,
but would not by itself imply that the moral situation is therefore
clear-cut in the direction of embryo inviolability.59
And recognizing the biological significance of some particular point,
marker, characteristic, or capacity would not, in itself, imply
some decisive moral significance. An understanding of the moral
nature or status of an early embryo is by no means necessarily dependent
upon, or derivable from, a description of early embryonic development.60
Any biological description requires some interpretation of its significance
before it can act as a guide to action.61
What follows is a brief review of developments in the debate over
the moral status of the human embryo in the past several years.
a) Continuity and Discontiunity
Many participants in the debate take the question of the biological
continuity or discontinuity of nascent and later human life to be
a crucially significant matter. They argue either that the fundamental
organismal continuity from the moment of fertilization until natural
death means that no lines can be drawn between embryos and adults;
or, on the other hand, that some particular point of discontinuity
(or the sum of several such points) marks a morally significant
distinction between stages, which should guide our treatment of
human embryos.
1. The case for continuity
Many of those who seek to defend the human embryo, and to have
it treated as inviolable, base their case on some form of the argument
for biological continuity. They argue that the human embryo is a
whole living member of the human species in the earliest stage of
natural development, and that given the appropriate environment,
it will, by self-directed integral organic functioning, develop
to the next more mature stage and become a human fetus, and then
a human child. The adult human beings around us, they argue, are
the same individuals who, at an earlier stage of life, were human
embryos. We all were then and are now distinct and complete human
organisms, not mere parts of other organisms.62
This view holds that only the very beginning of embryonic life
can serve as a reasonable boundary line in assessing the moral worth
of a human organism, because it is the moment marked out by nature
for the first visible appearance in the world of a new individual.
Before it, no new individual exists. After it, sperm and egg cells
are gone-subsumed and transformed into a new, third thing capable
of its own internally self-directed development. By itself, no sperm
or egg has the potential to become an adult, but zygotes routinely
do.63
Many authors therefore regard the completion of syngamy (the combining
of paternally- and maternally-contributed haploid pro-nuclei to
result in a unique diploid nucleus of a developing zygote) as a
meaningful marker of the beginning of a new protection-worthy human
life.64
After this point, there is a new genome, and there is a zygote (single
cell embryo) already beginning its first cleavage and thus its continuous
developmental path toward birth.
All further stages and events in embryological development, they
argue, are discrete labels applied to a system that is continuously
changing in its dimensions, scope, degree of differentiation, and
so on. Thus we can learn names for stages as if they were static,
but the living and developing embryo is continuously dynamic.65
More to the point, in the view of these commentators no such discrete
point in time or development would seem to give any justification
for assuming that the embryo in question was one thing at one point
and then suddenly became something different (for example, non-human
to human or non-person to person). None of the biological events
(or points in processes), they contend, is sufficient to tell us
what we are morally obligated to do, in the absence of one of the
additional premises indicating the moral standing (or lack thereof)
of the subject embryo, that the biological event is taken to represent.66
Some critics of this position argue that it makes too much of
mere genetic identity and (uncertain) potential, and does not make
enough of present condition, and of the significance of development
itself.67
There is more to being human, some observers argue, than a human
genome, and it matters that the early human embryo is a ball of
cells, without sentience or sensation, and without human form.68
In response, advocates of the argument from continuity suggest that
it is dangerous to begin to assign moral worth on the basis of particular
capacities and features, and that instead we must recognize each
member of our species from his or her earliest days as a human being
deserving of dignified treatment. There is, they argue, no clear
place to draw a line after the earliest formation of the organism,
and so there can be no stark division between nascent human life
and more mature individuals.69
2. Claims of meaningful discontinuity and developing
moral status
Many other observers, however, argue that some biologically or
morally significant discontinuities do in fact present themselves
in the course of early development. These arguments generally do
not simply hinge on biological descriptions-which are, in the absence
of analysis, largely devoid of obvious moral significance-and instead
begin from some implicit or explicit claim regarding the importance
of a particular feature, capacity, form, or function (or the progressive
accumulation of these) in defining a developing organism as meaningfully
a member of the human race. They are therefore not simply grounded
in biology, and appeal also to a moral or even metaphysical claim
about the meaning of humanity.70
They suggest that the developing human organism might become (at
once or progressively) deserving of protection as it becomes able
to feel pain, or to exhibit neural activity, or rudimentary self-awareness,
or some elements of the human form, or the capacity to function
independently, or as it progressively exhibits more and more of
these or other criteria. Until that time, many argue, the embryo
deserves some respect, but not protection on par (or nearly so)
with that otherwise afforded to human subjects.71
They suggest that genetic identity and organismic continuity are
not sufficient, and that what matters is present form and function,
more than mere potential.72
Several particular discontinuities (and combinations of them)
have been proposed as candidates for the division between early
stages when the human embryo may be disaggregated for research,
and later stages when it deserves some level of protection.
(a) Primitive streak
Among the most popular arguments for a meaningful point of discontinuity
are those that revolve around the appearance of the primitive
streak, which marks the point at which the vertebral column
will form. The primitive streak generally forms around the 14th
day after first cell division. It is taken to indicate the anterior-posterior
axis of an embryo (in vertebrates), although recent results suggest
that polarity is established much earlier, and in fact may be
indicated by the point of sperm entry.73
One principle reason for the importance placed on the primitive
streak has to do with the biology of twinning. Prior to the appearance
of the primitive streak, the embryo may relatively easily divide
completely to form identical twins. Some conclude that individuality
must not yet be established, since the embryo might yet become
two embryos.74
They argue that since individuality is essential to human personhood
and capacity for moral status, and since individuality presumes
a definitive single individual, and the singularity of the embryo
is not irrevocably settled prior to the appearance of the primitive
streak, the entity prior to the primitive streak stage does not
have definitive individuality and therefore cannot have moral
status.75
Critics of this line of reasoning note that twinning is a normal
(though not statistically very common) event, and that the division
of an embryo into two does not somehow demonstrate ex post
facto the lack of moral worth of the embryo before twinning.
Twinning, they suggest, affords no moral paradox and no proof
of the worthlessness of early embryos.76
Nonetheless, for this reason, and for others (discussed below)
having to do with the formation of the nervous system, primitive
streak has often been taken to be a highly significant marker
of embryological development, and many commentators suggest it
as a reasonable candidate for a meaningful point of discontinuity.
Supporters of embryo research regularly propose the 14th
day of development as a logical stopping point for permissible
embryo research.1
(b) Nervous system
A second argument for discontinuity, related to the primitive
streak case, focuses on the developing nervous system. Many observers
regard the nervous system as an especially important marker of
humanity, both because the human brain is critical in making human
beings human, and because the nervous system is the seat of sensation,
and in this case especially the sensation of pain. Proponents
of this view hold that before an embryo has developed the capacity
for feeling pain (or, in some forms of the argument, before sentience),
we cross no crucial moral boundary in subjecting it to destructive
research.78
For some, this is taken to mean that the primitive streak, as
the first marker of a future nervous system, is a crucial feature
of developing life. For others, further points of neural development
are held to be decisive.79
(c) Human Form
Some observers also argue that some rudimentary features of
the human form must be apparent before we can consider the human
embryo deserving of protection. In this view, the human form truly
signals the presence of a human life in the making, and calls
upon our moral sentiments to treat the being in question as one
of us.80
Different versions of this argument appeal to different particular
elements (or combinations of elements) of the human form as decisive,
but all suggest that a ball of cells is not recognizably human,
and therefore ought not to be treated as simply one of
us.81
These various particular cases for discontinuity (and these are
not the only ones propounded through the years) are not mutually
exclusive, and indeed many of them point to more than one particular
point or element of early human development as finally decisive
of moral status, but rather to a developing moral status accruing
to the developing human organism.82
Their claim, in the broadest terms, is that in its earliest stages
the human embryo is not yet simply a human person, and need not
be treated as though it was. Human development, they contend, is
not an unimportant element of human life, and a being at the earliest
stages of that process is not to be treated the same as a being
much farther along.83
There are differences, and these differences matter, in ways that
can be determined by human choice and understanding, as well as
by an understanding of biological facts.84
b) Special Cases and Exceptions Some arguments in favor
of permitting or funding embryo research do not explicitly (or exclusively)
rely upon a case for discontinuity or for a developing moral status
founded in the embryo's biology. Instead, or in addition, they rely
upon questions of embryo-viability, potential, and unique circumstances
to address questions of the moral status of certain particular
human embryos.
(a.) IVF Spares
The most commonly cited case is that of cryogenically frozen
IVF embryos, left over from assisted reproduction procedures and
stored, perhaps indefinitely, in the freezers of an IVF clinic.
One recent study suggests there are hundreds of thousands of such
embryos in the United States alone.85
Most of these frozen embryos may never be claimed by the original
egg and sperm donors for use in assisted reproduction procedures.
They are destined to remain frozen and, eventually, to die without
developing further. Though there have been some efforts to build
interest in the adoption of such embryos, and their use in assisted
reproduction by other couples, such adoption, some commentators
suggest, is very unlikely to become a large-scale phenomenon,
or to affect the fate of most of these embryos.86
Under the present funding policy, if these frozen embryos were
used in research, and embryonic stem cells were derived from them,
research on the resulting cells would not be eligible for federal
funding. Many observers argue that it should be, and that these
particular embryos, whatever one's position on the embryo question
in general, are essentially destined to die without ever developing,
and that it would therefore be appropriate to at least redeem
some possible good from their existence.87
Indeed, since so many cryopreserved embryos are already in existence,
and since the vast majority seem very unlikely to be adopted even
if we were to pursue and encourage embryo adoption, and since
many may not be viable even if they were to be transferred, some
observers have argued that practically speaking they are virtually
all already lost.88
Not that they are already dead, but they are in a so-called "terminal
situation" from which no rescue is practically possible. In view
of this situation, one commentator proposes extending the principle
of permitting the killing of innocents to these embryos. That
is, killing may be morally permissible in cases where the innocent
will soon die for other unavoidable reasons, and where there is
another innocent who can somehow be rescued through or as a result
of that normally impermissible act of killing (thus nothing more
is lost). He points out that the case of cryopreserved embryos
stretches the application of the "nothing is lost" principle further
than previous uses, because the embryos in question are alive
and likely if not certain to die only because of human choices
and designs specifically directed toward them. The principle is
also stretched because the lives that might be saved through embryo
deaths are quite distant. The potential lives saved are those
of unspecified persons with some of a range of disease that might
be treated by therapies that as yet do not exist and are not in
any particular case known to be likely, let alone certain, to
help. And again, all this is the case only if the research depending
on the embryo deaths does indeed prove fruitful as hoped. However,
against all these formidable and indefinitely extended ifs,
there is the present fact that the cryopreserved embryos are already
here, already have little or no prospect of rescue-are, in one
observer's description, already lost.89
Presumably if embryo destruction for human embryonic stem cell
research were generally agreed to be permissible through this
principle, it could be federally funded, subject to such secondary
considerations as the just allocation of resources and the need
for free and informed consent by donors.
One concern with this approach to embryos left over from IVF
procedures involves what critics have called the circular reasoning
of the argument: the embryos are in a "terminal situation" because
of human choice and design, so to then decide that since they
are going to die anyway they may as well be put to good use, is
to ignore the moral implications of the original decision to create
and freeze them.90
Some proponents of using IVF spares, however, argue that the present
situation is properly understood as a forced choice between two
mutually exclusive alternatives, both in some sense tragic, for
the final deposition of stored embryos (whether donated or abandoned).
One choice may then be justified as the lesser evil. Even if the
original decisions leading to the creation and storage of these
embryos were misguided, the embryos exist, and the decisions cannot
be undone.91
A further concern involves the question of whether in accepting
the application of the "nothing is lost" principle for
already existing embryos, it would be possible to condone future
use of excess embryos, or whether the principle requires the prevention
of the creation or storage of "excess" embryos in the future.92
Further, this application of the principle applies to embryos
created for the purpose of reproduction and inadvertently not
transferred. Should research use be accepted, however, it is not
clear that it would be possible to differentiate embryos created
solely for reproduction, and embryos created with an eye to research
uses. It might therefore be difficult to avoid condoning the creation
of extra embryos with research in mind.93
Other observers, however, take the presence of cryogenically
preserved embryos further, and conclude that there is good reason
for using some embryos for research not only because a tragic
situation already exists, but because the donation of embryos
is an act of positive good, and that using donated embryos is
a social obligation conferred by their presence as donated entities.94
This approach would have us start by recognizing that in the current
situation there is a set of embryos (in IVF clinics) such that
none of the members will ever enter a uterus, uterine tube, or
even a (still hypothetical) artificial uterus.95
These, in one commentator's term, are "unenabled," and have no
potential for full development. Since there is no possible way
for such embryos to develop, there is no "possible person" to
whom any "unenabled" embryo corresponds, and therefore using them
in research involves no loss of possible life.96
Critics of this approach argue that in effect it allows the
moral status of a given embryo to be simply decided by those responsible
for it. That is, whether a given embryo has moral status depends
on whether it has a practical prospect of developing, as evidenced
by whether it enters a uterus. Whether it enters a uterus, in
turn, depends on human choices, so the moral status of a given
embryo depends on human choices. If we choose to remove opportunity
by removing enabling conditions such as a uterus in which to implant,
then the embryo lacks just that, the opportunity to develop in
conditions permitting development, but its intrinsic potential
to develop (given needed conditions) has not changed.97
Nonetheless, in the view of a number of commentators, the fact
of the existence of these frozen embryos changes the balance of
duties and respect. In these and similar ways, many observers
have argued that the presence of hundreds of thousands of frozen
embryos with little to no chance of ever developing to birth creates
special circumstances in which the use of embryos in research
(whether destroying them for research or allowing them to die
and subsequently using them)98
does not depend upon a final judgment regarding the moral status
or worth of the human embryo as such.99
(b) Natural Embryo Loss
Some authors point to the high rate of embryo loss under natural
and unassisted conditions, and argue that directed embryo destruction
for the purpose of research would not result in greater loss than
this natural process, and would result in far greater benefits
for humanity.100
The rate of natural embryo loss after conception in unassisted
human reproduction is high, some suggest as high as 80 percent,101
and the fact of natural loss is fairly well known, so that persons
who engage in or permit the pursuit of conception through unassisted
reproduction are knowingly bringing about the conception of many
embryos that will die. We generally do not regard this embryo
loss as unacceptably tragic or engage in great efforts to avert
it, or to find ways to diminish it. These commentators argue,
therefore, that making use of artificially created embryos for
research would not result in the destruction of a greater portion
of those embryos than might have died in natural unassisted reproduction.102
Moreover, they suggest, the high rate of natural embryo loss
should bring into question the views of those who believe that
early-stage human embryos merit equal treatment with human children
and adults. If so many die in the natural course of things, how
do we not treat natural procreation as a great fountain of tragedy
and carnage? They argue that the natural rate of embryo loss,
and our response to it, should teach us something about the limited
significance of human embryos in the earliest stages. One observer
adds that the same logic should diminish our concerns about creating
human embryos for research, as long as sufficient embryos are
created for implantation to keep the chances of survival for any
given embryo as good as the chances in natural reproduction.103
Another further argues that human embryonic stem cell research
actually raises the probability of longer survival for all humans
including embryonic ones, and is therefore a case of permissible
taking of life, even on the assumption that the embryos are persons.104
Opponents of this view, however, have argued that natural death
of embryos and deaths caused by intentional efforts to destroy
embryos for research are not morally equivalent, and that the
character of our reaction to the former does not permit us simply
to engage in the latter. They propose that moral status is not
ascribed to a being by the reaction of others to its death or
in any other sense by their view of its value.105
(c) Prediction of Non-Viability of Embryos
A further approach to the subject seeks to identify a subset
of cryopreserved embryos that might reasonably be regarded as
non-viable in advance. That is, although the embryos are not
dead, and could presumably be thawed and would still exhibit some
cellular function, they would be unlikely to survive even if transfer
were available. Since IVF procedures often result in more embryos
being conceived than can be transferred at one time, goes the
argument, the clinicians must make judgments about which of the
available embryos seem most likely to survive and develop. So
by applying similar judgment to frozen embryos, we might identify
those that would be least likely to survive even under the most
favorable circumstances. These embryos might then reasonably
be regarded as non-viable, and perhaps available for research
use since their use will not disrupt a potential life. 106
There has not been much direct reaction to this view in the
ongoing ethical debates, though some observers have noted, in
other contexts, that the techniques used to identify embryos more
or less likely to develop successfully in IVF procedures-techniques
most often based on visual assessment of the embryos-have never
been proven effective, or even tested to ascertain their validity.107
(d) Creation of Non-Viable Embryo-like Artifacts
A related proposal suggests that we avoid the risk of error
in identifying or defining some class of embryos as non-viable
and instead seek to create embryo-like entities that would be
guaranteed non-viable. This proposal is motivated in part by an
understanding of development as not just a set of events but a
directed sequence (or network of sequences) that point toward
the adult, reproducing, stage of the organism in question. By
implication then, an embryo is not merely a very young organism,
nor merely a group of adherent cells, but an organism that is
in the process of developing along that directed path. So development
is not just what embryos do, but developing is what embryos
essentially are. Conversely, goes the argument, an entity
that is not capable of developing is not an embryo, although it
may have many embryo-like properties. This leads to the proposal
that researchers might create "artifacts" that would be embryo-like
in many respects, and could even yield embryonic stem cells, but
would fundamentally not be embryos, in that they would be designed
not to have full developmental capacity.108
This might be done by manipulating the genome of the embryo in
question by knocking out genes necessary for extra-embryonic membranes
or for another process such as angiogenesis.109
This proposal has been critiqued by some on two general grounds.
First, they suggest, it would require significant research to
assure both that the knock-out procedure did reliably result in
a non-viable entity, and that the resulting entity still produced
stem cells that were normal (or else they would be of little interest).
This research might itself be morally problematic. And second,
some have wondered whether the knock-out procedure might not be
morally constitutive of embryo destruction, and whether designing
and creating a developing organism with some human features but
with no hope of long-term development may not itself be morally
troublesome.110
For the moment, this approach is purely speculative, and so
would have no bearing on the present embryonic stem cell research
funding policy, or the considerations surrounding it, though it
has begun to play a part in the debates over the moral status
of the embryo, and the permissibility of embryo research more
generally.
V. Other Related Concerns A number
of commentators have also raised some issues and concerns which,
while they do not fall neatly into the above categories, strike
us as highly relevant to the human embryonic stem cell research
debate.
Some, for instance, have argued that any federal policy must take
note not only of the state and potential promise of embryonic stem
cell science, but also that of some potential alternatives to such
research, which might be less morally troubling to some Americans.
Many opponents of public funding for human embryonic stem cell research,
for instance, have argued that more attention should be paid, and
more resources devoted, to human adult stem cell research, which
does not raise many of the moral difficulties present in the embryonic
stem cell debates111
(though, for some, it still does raise a number of ethical difficulties).112
Such research, they contend, could make embryonic stem cell research
(or at the very least publicly funded embryonic stem cell research)113
unnecessary. In response, however, others have argued that embryonic
stem cells may possess unique advantages over adult stem cells,
just as the opposite may be the case, and that therefore both avenues,
and also research using stem cells derived from fetal tissue, should
be pursued simultaneously.114
In a related staff paper, we examine some of the scientific facts
regarding adult and embryonic stem cells, but in the context of
the ethical and political debates, the distinctions between them
have been quite important and prominent.
Other observers have raised concerns related to the debate itself,
rather than to the specifics of one technique or another, or of
one funding policy or another. Some, for instance, have argued that
what is needed in the human embryonic stem cell research debate
is not only an exchange of views about the substantive issues (though
that is surely crucial) but also some sense of the appropriate democratic
process for deliberation on such a profoundly contentious issue,
and for establishing appropriate public policy. The embryonic stem
cell debate, it is argued, offers a valuable opportunity to think
through the ways in which the American polity debates the most contentious
moral issues.115
Others have also argued that the debate, as it has taken shape
over the past several years, has focused almost exclusively on questions
of the status of the embryo, when other issues-including commodification,
human nature, embodiment, and the purposes of science and medicine-also
bear heavily on the subject, and may illuminate it in ways at least
as significant.116
Others have also noted that many participants on all sides of
the embryonic stem cell research debate have tended almost carelessly
to accept the assumption-which at this point has not yet found grounding
in the experimental or clinical findings of the research-that embryonic
stem cell research will someday soon bring cures to many who are
ailing. Such talk, some observers have argued, tends to raise false
hopes, and thus does a genuine disservice to the sick and disabled.117
"It is misleading to suggest that stem cells will bring cures,"
one such writer observers, "particularly cures for patients now
coping with the serious diseases the research targets."118
A related concern, raised by some of the same commentators, involves
what has been termed "the disproportionate emphasis on stem cell
research in contemporary health politics."119
The prominence of this debate in American politics, they argue,
may tend to distract us from the fact that many Americans, and even
more people elsewhere, lack very basic healthcare, and do not have
access to those medical tools and techniques that already exist,
and that do not raise profound controversy.120
In these ways, the controversial possibility of scientific alternatives,
as well as concerns about the health of American democracy, the
honesty of a political debate that touches on the hopes and fears
of many who are suffering, and the bigger picture of health politics
all impinge upon the question of federal funding of human embryonic
stem cell research.
Conclusion Participants in the public
debate surrounding human embryonic stem cell research and the Administration's
funding policy have addressed themselves to the character of the
question at issue; the nature, object, assumptions, and premises
of the policy itself; the vexing question of the human embryo; and
a number of other related concerns. As we have seen, strong and
powerfully argued views have been presented on various sides of
each of these questions. It may be that developments and discoveries
in biology will never finally be enough to settle the question,
and that the decisive issues are principally ones of competing moral
views of human life, human dignity, and scientific progress. This
is likely not a subject that will ever be settled by slogans or
syllogisms, and perhaps it will not be settled at all any time soon.
But the rich and growing ethical debates do suggest the possibility
of progress toward greater understanding, and more informed public
decision-making.
_______________ ENDNOTES
-
"Press Conference by President Bush and Italian Prime Minister
Berlusconi," as made available by the White House Press Office,
July 23, 2001.
-
See, for instance, Weissman, I., "Stem Cells-Scientific, Medical
and Political Issues," New England Journal of Medicine, 346:20,
May 16, 2002, 1578.
-
See, for instance, Green, R. "Determining Moral Status," American
Journal of Bioethics, 2:1, 28-9.
-
See, for instance, Orr, R. "The Moral Status of the Embryonal
Stem Cell: Inherent or Imputed?" American Journal of Bioethics,
2:1, 57-8
-
See, for instance, Doerflinger, R. "Ditching Religion and Reality,"
American Journal of Bioethics, 2:1, 31.
-
See, for instance, Latham, S. "Ethics and Politics," American
Journal of Bioethics, 2:1, 46.
-
See, for instance, Marquis, D. "Stem Cell Research: The Failure
of Bioethics," Free Inquiry, Winter 2002.
-
See, for instance, the testimony of Richard Doerflinger before
the Council on June 12, 2003. A transcript of that testimony
is available on the Council website at http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/jun03/session4.html
-
See, for instance, FitzGerald, K. "Questions Concerning the
Current Stem Cell Debate," American Journal of Bioethics,
2:1, 50-1.
-
See, for instance, Haseltine, W. "Regenerative Medicine: A Future
Healing Art," Brookings Review, Winter 2003.
-
See, for instance, Stolberg, S. "Scientists Urge Bigger Supply
of Stem Cells," The New York Times, September 11, 2001,
p. A1.
-
See, for instance, Perry, D. "Patients' Voices: The Powerful
Sound in the Stem Cell Debate," Science, 287:5457, 1423;
and the testimony of Irving Weissman before the Council on February
13, 2002, available on the Council website at http://bioethics.gov/transcripts/feb02/feb13session2.html
-
This point was taken up by the Council in its report Human
Cloning and Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry (July 2002),
chapter 6, p. 168.
-
One useful description of this approach to the issue is Zoloth,
L., "Jordan's Banks, A View from the First Years of Human Embryonic
Stem Cell Research," American Journal of Bioethics, 2:1,
7.
-
Callahan, D. What Price Better Health: The Hazards of the
Research Imperative. Los Angeles: University of California
Press, 2003; also see Daniel Callahan's testimony before the
Council on July 24, 2003, available on the Council's website
at http://bioethics.gov/transcripts/july03/session1.html
-
FitzGerald, K., op. cit., 50-1.
-
For examples, see Weiss, R. "Legal Barriers to Human Cloning
May Not Hold Up," The Washington Post, May 23, 2001.
-
See, for instance, Elias, P. "States, Feds May Clash over Cloning
Rules," Genomics and Genetics Weekly, April 12, 2002,
p. 24
-
This, for instance, was the line of reasoning of the American
Bar Association when, in August of 2002, it issued a resolution
supporting limited therapeutic research using cloned human embryos.
The report of the ABA's Section of Individual Rights and Responsibilities
(available from the ABA) lays out the case.
-
See, for instance, Russo, E. "Policy Questions and Some Answers,"
The Scientist, April 15, 2003.
-
R. Alta Charo, of the University of Wisconsin Law School, quoted
in Coyle, M. "The Clone Zone," The National Law Journal,
May 15, 2002.
-
Alan Meisel of the University of Pittsburgh School of Law, quoted
in Coyle, M. "The Clone Zone," The National Law Journal,
May 15, 2002.
-
See: Maher v. Roe 432 U.S.464 (1977); Harris v. McRae
448 U.S. 297 (1980); Rust v. Sullivan 500 U.S. 173 (1991).
-
Berkowitz, P. "The Meaning of Federal Funding," a paper commissioned
by the President's Council on Bioethics, available on the Council
website at http://www.bioethics.gov/background/berkowitz.html.
See also Khushf, G., and Best, R. "Stem Cells and the Man on
the Moon: Should We Go There from Here?" American Journal
of Bioethics, 2:1, 38.
-
FitzGerald, K., op. cit., 50-1.
-
Doerflinger, R., op. cit., 31.
-
See, for instance, Lauritzen, P. "Report on the Ethics of Stem
Cell Research," a commissioned paper prepared at the request
of the Council; and Dresser, R. "Embryonic Stem Cells: Expanding
the Analysis," American Journal of Bioethics, 2:1, 40-1.
-
Childress, J. "Federal Policy Toward Embryonic Stem Cell Research,"
American Journal of Bioethics, 2:1, 34.
-
Kahn, J. "missing the mark on stem cells," Bioethics Examiner,
5:3, Fall 2001, p.1.
-
Murray, T. "Hard Cell," The American Prospect September
24, 2001.
-
See, for instance, the testimony of Richard Doerflinger before
the Council on June 12, 2003. A transcript of that testimony
is available on the Council website at http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/jun03/session4.html
-
Bush, G.W. "Stem Cell Science and the Preservation of Life,"
The New York Times, August 12, 2001, p. D13.
-
"How many lines," Washington Post, August 31, 2001, p.A22.
-
Daley, G. "Cloning and Stem Cells-Handicapping the Political
and Scientific Debates," New England Journal of Medicine,
349:3, P. 211.
-
Kennedy, D. "Stem Cells: Still Here, Still Waiting," Science,
300, May 9, 2003, p. 865.
-
See, for instance, Brickley, P. "Scientists Seek Passports to
Freer Environments," The Scientist, 15:36, August 20,
2001.
-
See, for instance, Weissman, I. "Stem Cells-Scientific, Medical
and Political Issues", New England Journal of Medicine,
346:20, May 16, 2002, 1578.
-
See, for instance, Weise, E. "USA's Stem Cell Scientists Fear
a Research Brain-Drain," USA Today, May 12, 2003, p.
6D.
-
Clark, J. "Squandering Our Technological Future," The New
York Times, August 30, 2001, p. A19. See also the testimony
of Thomas Okarma, President and CEO of Geron Corporation, before
the Council on September 4, 2003. The full transcript of Okarma's
testimony may be found on the Council's website at http://bioethics.gov/transcripts/sep03/session4.html
-
Robertson, J. "Crossing the Ethical Chasm: Embryo Status and
Moral Complicity," American Journal of Bioethics, 2:1,
33.
-
See, for instance, Pizzo, P. "Remove Obstacles to Stem Cell
Research," San Jose Mercury-News, June 19, 2003; and
Holden, C. and Vogel, G. "'Show Us the Cells' U.S. Researchers
Say," Science, 297, August 9, 2002, p. 923.
-
See, for instance, Capron, A. "Stem Cell Politics: The New Shape
to the Road Ahead," American Journal of Bioethics, 2:1,
35-6.
-
Robertson, J., op. cit., 33-4.
-
This comment was made by Council member Gilbert Meilaender in
Council discussion on September 4, 2003. A transcript of that
discussion is available on the Council website at http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/sep03/session2.html
-
See, for insance, FitzGerald, K., op. cit., 50-1.
-
Khushf, G., and Best, R., op. cit., 38.
-
See, for instance, Stolberg, S., op. cit.
-
See, for instance, Robertson, J. "Ethics and Policy in Embryonic
Stem Cell Research," Kennedy Institute of Ethics Journal,
9:2, 109-136; Spike, J. "Bush and Stem Cell Research: An Ethically
Confused Policy," American Journal of Bioethics, 2:1,
46; and Capron, A., op. cit., 36.
-
The statement was made by bioethicist Glen McGee, in reference
to the Clinton-era proposed NIH rules on funding, quoted in
Spanogle, J. "Transforming Life," The Baylor Line (Winter
2000), p. 30.
-
The remark was made by Bishop Joseph A. Fiorenza, President
of the U.S. Conference of Catholic Bishops, in a news release
("Catholic Bishops Criticize Bush Policy on Embryo Research,"
made available by the United States Conference of Catholic Bishops,
August 9, 2001).
-
This argument arose in the course of Council discussion on September
4, 2003 (see particularly the comments of Council member Michael
Sandel in that discussion.) A transcript of that session is
available on the Council website at http://www.bioethics.gov/transcripts/sep03/session2.html
-
Ibid., see particularly the comments of Council member Mary
Ann Glendon in that discussion.
-
Ibid., see particularly the comments of Council member William
Hurlbut in that discussion.
-
Some reasons to regard public funding of activities in a different
light from mere permission are proposed in Khushf, G., and Best,
R., op. cit., 38.
-
"Remarks by the President on Stem Cell Research," as made available
by the White House Press Office, August 9, 2001.
-
See, for instance, London, A. "Embryos, Stem Cells, and the
'Strategic' Element of Public Moral Reasoning," American
Journal of Bioethics, 2:1, 56.
-
For examples of this way of proceeding-both in arguments supporting
embryo research, and arguments opposing it-see, among numerous
other sources, the Council's July 2002 report, Human Cloning
and Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry, chapter 6.
-
See, for instance, McCartney, J. "Embryonic Stem Cell Research
and Respect for Human Life: Philosophical and Legal Reflections,"
Albany Law Review 65:3, 597-624.
-
See, for instance, Orr, R., op. cit., 57-8.
-
See, for instance, Steinberg, D. "Can Moral Worthiness Be Seen
Using a Microscope?" American Journal of Bioethics, 2:1,
49.
-
See, for instance, Green, R., op. cit., 20.
-
See, for instance, Doerflinger, R., op. cit., 31-3; Orr, R.,
op. cit., 57-8; and the personal statements of Council members
William Hurlbut and Robert George and Alfonso Gomez-Lobo, in
the Council's July 2002 report Human Cloning and Human Dignity:
An Ethical Inquiry, among others.
-
See, for instance, Orr, R., op. cit., 57-8.
-
See, for instance, Sullivan, D. "The Conception View of Personhood:
A Review," Ethics and Medicine, 19:1 (Spring 2003), p.
11-33.
-
A form of this argument was presented by some members of the
Council in the Council's July, 2001 report Human Cloning
and Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry, chapter 6, and in
several of the personal statements appended to that report.
-
See, for instance, Steinberg, D., op. cit., 49.
-
See, for instance, Green , R., op. cit., 20-30.
-
See, for instance, Lanza, R., et al. "The Ethical Validity
of Using Nuclear Transfer in Human Transplantation," Journal
of the American Medical Association, 284:24, 3175-9.
-
See, for instance, Orr, R., op. cit., 57-9; Callahan, S. "Zygotes
and Blastocysts : Human enough to protect," Commonweal,
June 14, 2002; the position articulated by several members of
this Council in our July 2002 report Human Cloning and Human
Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry, chapter 6; and the personal
statements of Council members Robert George and Alfonso Gomez-Lobo,
and William Hurlbut in that same report.
-
See, for instance, Steinberg, D., op. cit., 49-50; and Green,
R., op. cit., 20.
-
See, for instance, Myer, M., and Lawrence, J. "Respecting What
We Destroy: Reflections on Human Embryo Research," Hastings
Center Report, 31:1, 16-23.
-
See, for instance, Strong, C. "The Moral Status of Preembryos,
Embryos, Fetuses, and Infants," The Journal of Medicine and
Philosophy 22:5, 457-78.
-
Pearson, H. "Developmental Biology: Your Destiny, from Day One,"
Nature, 418:6893, p. 14-15.
-
See, for instance, McCartney, J., op. cit., 601-602; Brogaard,
B. "The moral status of the human embryo: the twinning
argument," Free Inquiry, Winter 2002; Myer, M.,
and Lawrence, J., op. cit., 18. The question of twinning-pro
and con-was also taken up by the Council in its July 2002 report,
Human Cloning and Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry,
chapter 6.
-
See, for instance, Green , R., op. cit., 21-2; Lanza, R., op.
cit., 3177.
-
See, for instance, Ashley, B., and Moraczewski, A. "Cloning,
Aquinas, and the Embryonic Person," National Catholic Bioethics
Quartely 1:2, 189-201; Orr, R., op. cit., 58; Marquis, D. op.
cit.; and Lori Andrews quoted in , Green, R., op. cit., 22.
The question of twinning-pro and con-was also taken up by the
Council in its July 2002 report, Human Cloning and Human
Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry, chapter 6.
-
See, for instance, National Institutes of Health, Report
of the Human Embryo Research Panel (Bethesda, MD: NIH),
1994; National Bioethics Advisory Commission, Ethical Issues
in Human Stem Cell Research (Washington, DC: Government
Printing Office), 1999, p. 7; and the position articulated by
several members of this Council in our July 2002 report Human
Cloning and Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry, chapter 6,
among many others.
-
See, for instance, Lanza, R., op. cit., 3177.
-
See, for instance, Strong, C., op. cit., 467.
-
See, for instance, Wilson, J. "On Abortion" Commentary,
January 1994; and the position articulated by several members
of this Council in our July 2002 report Human Cloning and
Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry, chapter 6.
-
See, for instance, Green, R., op. cit., 20-30; and the position
articulated by several members of this Council in our July 2002
report Human Cloning and Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry,
chapter 6.
-
See, for instance, National Institutes of Health, Report
of the Human Embryo Research Panel (Bethesda, MD: NIH),
1994; and the position articulated by several members of this
Council in our July 2002 report Human Cloning and Human Dignity:
An Ethical Inquiry, chapter 6.
-
See, for instance, McGee, D. "The Idolatry of Absolutizing in
the Stem Cell Debate," American Journal of Bioethics,
2:1, 53-4.
-
See, for instance, Green, R., op. cit., 20.
-
Hoffman, D.I., et al., "Cryopreserved Embryos in the United
States and Their Availability for Research," Fertility and
Sterility, 79: 1063-1069.
-
See, for instance, Spike, J., op. cit., 45.
-
See, for instance, the testimony of Michael West before the
Labor, HHS, and Education Subcommittee of the Senate Appropriations
Committee, December 4, 2001, among others.
-
Outka, G. "The Ethics of Stem Cell Research," a paper presented
to the Council for its April 2002 meeting, and available on
the Council website at http://bioethics.gov/background/outkapaper.html.
A slightly revised version appeared in the Kennedy Institute
of Ethics Journal, 12:2, p. 175-213.
-
-
See, for instance, "The Stem Cell Sell," Commonweal,
August 17, 2001; Meilaender, G. "Spare Embryos," The Weekly
Standard, August 26, 2002; and Council discussion of Gene
Outka's paper, in its April 2002 meeting, a transcript of which
is available on the Council website at http://bioethics.gov/transcripts/apr02/apr25full.html#3
-
See, for instance, McCartney, J, op. cit., 615.
-
This concern is raised in Outka, G. "The Ethics of Stem Cell
Research," a paper presented to the Council for its April 2002
meeting, and available on the Council website at http://bioethics.gov/background/outkapaper.html.
Also see the Council discussion of that paper, available on
the Council website at http://bioethics.gov/transcripts/apr02/apr25full.html#3;
and see Meilaender, G., op. cit.
-
See, for instance, the transcript of Council discussion on April
25, 2002, available on the Council's website at http://bioethics.gov/transcripts/apr02/apr25session3.html
-
Guinin, L. "Morals and Primordials," Science, 292:1659-60.
-
-
-
See, for instance, Orr, R., op. cit., 58.
-
Mahowald, M. and Mahwoald P. "Embryonic Stem Cell Retrieval
and a Possible Ethical Bypass," American Journal of Bioethics,
2:1, 42-3.
-
See, for instance, Zoloth, L., op. cit., 4-5.
-
See, for instance, Harris, J. "The ethical use of human embryonic
stem cells in research and therapy," in Burley, J. and Harris,
J., eds. A Companion to Genetics: Philosophy and the Genetic
Revolution, Oxford: Basil Blackwell, 2001; and Savulescu,
J. "The Embryonic Stem Cell Lottery and the Cannibalization
of Human Beings," Bioethics, 16:6, 508-529.
-
This subject was discussed in a Council session on January 16,
2003. When asked, in the course of testimony before the Council,
about the rate of natural embryo loss, Dr. John Opitz (Professor
of Pediatrics, Human Genetics, and Obstetrics/Gynecology, School
of Medicine, University of Utah) responded: "Estimates range
all the way from 60 percent to 80 percent of the very earliest
stages, cleavage stages, for example, that are lost." The transcript
of this session is available on the Council website at http://bioethics.gov/transcripts/jan03/session1.html
-
-
Harris, J. "Stem Cells, Sex & Procreation," a paper presented
to the American Philosophical Society, March 29, 2003.
-
Savulescu, J., op. cit., 508-529.
-
See, for instance, Orr, R., op. cit., 57-9.
-
See, for instance, Zoloth, L., op. cit., 4-5.
-
See, for instance, Mandavilli, A. "Fertility's New Frontier
Takes Shape in the Test Tube," Nature Medicine, 9:8,
1095.
-
See, for instance, Weiss, R. "Can Scientists Bypass Stem Cells'
Moral Minefield?" The Washington Post, December 14, 1998,
p. A3.
-
See, for instance, the personal statement of Council Member
William Hurlbut, appended to the Council's July 2002 report
Human Cloning and Human Dignity: An Ethical Inquiry.
-
See, for instance, several observers quoted in Weiss, R. "Can
Scientists Bypass Stem Cells' Moral Minefield?" The Washington
Post, December 14, 1998, p. A3.
-
See, for instance, Orr, R., op. cit., 57-8; "A review of the
National Institute of Health's Guidelines for Research Using
Human Pluripotent Stem Cells," Issues in Law and Medicine,
3:17, p. 293; and the testimony of Rep. Dave Weldon before the
Technology and Space Subcommittee of the Senate Commerce, Science
and Transportation Committee, January 29, 2003.
-
Lauritzen, P. "Report on the Ethics of Stem Cell Research,"
a commissioned paper prepared at the request of the Council.
-
See, for instance, Oldham, R. "Stem Cells: Private Sector Can
Do It Better," The Wall Street Journal, August 28, 2001,
p. A14.
-
See, for example, the discussion and testimony at the Council's
April 2002 meeting, available on the Council's website at http://bioethics.gov/transcripts/apr02/apr25full.html.
-
Strong, C. "Those Divisive Stem Cells: Dealing with Our Most
Contentious Issues," American Journal of Bioethics, 2:1,
39-40.
-
Lauritzen, P. "Report on the Ethics of Stem Cell Research,"
a commissioned paper prepared at the request of the Council.
-
See, for instance, Dresser, R., op. cit., 40-1; and FitzGerald,
K., op. cit., 50-1
-
Dresser, R., op. cit., 41.
-
-
See also: FitzGerald, K., op. cit., 50-1.
______________
Footnotes
i.
Lori Andrews detailed both these ongoing efforts and existing legislation
in the states in testimony before the Council’s July 2003
meeting, and in the accompanying paper.
|