[Editor's note: footnotes (if any) trail the opinion]
(Bench Opinion)
NOTE: Where it is feasible, a syllabus (headnote) will be released, as
is being done in connection with this case, at the time the opinion is
issued. The syllabus constitutes no part of the opinion of the Court but
has been prepared by the Reporter of Decisions for the convenience of
the reader. See United States v. Detroit Timber & Lumber Co., 200
U. S. 321, 337.
SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
Syllabus
VACCO, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF NEW YORK, et al.
v.
QUILL et al.
CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE SECOND CIRCUIT
No. 95-1858.
Argued January 8, 1997
Decided June 26, 1997
In New York, as in most States, it is a crime to aid another to commit
or attempt suicide, but patients may refuse even lifesaving medical treatment.
Respondent New York physicians assert that, although it would be consistent
with the standards of their medical practices to prescribe lethal medication
for mentally competent, terminally ill patients who are suffering great
pain and desire a doctor's help in taking their own lives, they are deterred
from doing so by New York's assisted-suicide ban. They, and three gravely
ill patients who have since died, sued the State's Attorney General, claiming
that the ban violates the Fourteenth Amendment's Equal Protection Clause.
The Federal District Court disagreed, but the Second Circuit reversed,
holding (1) that New York accords different treatment to those competent,
terminally ill persons who wish to hasten their deaths by selfadministering
prescribed drugs than it does to those who wish to do so by directing
the removal of life-support systems, and (2) that this supposed unequal
treatment is not rationally related to any legitimate state interests.
Held: New York's prohibition on assisting suicide does not violate the
Equal Protection Clause. Pp. 3-14.
(a) The Equal Protection Clause embodies a general rule that States must
treat like cases alike but may treat unlike cases accordingly. E.g., Plyler
v. Doe, 457 U. S. 202, 216. The New York statutes outlawing assisted suicide
neither infringe fundamental rights nor involve suspect classifications,
e.g., Washington v. Glucksberg, ante, at 14-24, and are therefore entitled
to a strong presumption of validity, Heller v. Doe, 509 U. S. 312, 319.
On their faces, neither the assisted-suicide ban nor the law permitting
patients to refuse medical treatment treats anyone differently from anyone
else or draws any distinctions between persons. Everyone, regardless of
physical condition, is entitled, if competent, to refuse unwanted lifesaving
medical treatment; no one is permitted to assist a suicide. Generally,
laws that apply evenhandedly to all unquestionably comply with equal protection.
E.g., New York City Transit Authority v. Beazer, 440 U. S. 568, 587. This
Court disagrees with the Second Circuit's submission that ending or refusing
lifesaving medical treatment "is nothing more nor less than assisted
suicide." The distinction between letting a patient die and making
that patient die is important, logical, rational, and well established:
It comports with fundamental legal principles of causation, see, e.g.,
People v. Kevorkian, 447 Mich. 436, 470-472, 527 N. W. 2d 714, 728, cert.
denied, 514 U. S. 1083, and intent, see, e.g., United States v. Bailey,
444 U. S. 394, 403-406; has been recognized, at least implicitly, by this
Court in Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dept. of Health, 497 U. S. 261, 278-280;
id., at 287-288 (O'Connor, J., concurring); and has been widely recognized
and endorsed in the medical profession, the state courts, and the overwhelming
majority of state legislatures, which, like New York's, have permitted
the former while prohibiting the latter. The Court therefore disagrees
with respondents' claim that the distinction is "arbitrary"
and "irrational." The line between the two acts may not always
be clear, but certainty is not required, even were it possible. Logic
and contemporary practice support New York's judgment that the two acts
are different, and New York may therefore, consistent with the Constitution,
treat them differently. Pp. 3-13.
(b) New York's reasons for recognizing and acting on the distinction
between refusing treatment and assisting a suicide-including prohibiting
intentional killing and preserving life; preventing suicide; maintaining
physicians' role as their patients' healers; protecting vulnerable people
from indifference, prejudice, and psychological and financial pressure
to end their lives; and avoiding a possible slide towards euthanasia-are
valid and important public interests that easily satisfy the constitutional
requirement that a legislative classification bear a rational relation
to some legitimate end. See Glucksberg, ante. Pp. 13-14. 80 F. 3d 716,
reversed.
Rehnquist, C. J., delivered the opinion of the Court, in which O'Connor,
Scalia, Kennedy, and Thomas, JJ., joined. O'Connor, J., filed a concurring
opinion, in which Ginsburg and Breyer, JJ., joined in part. Stevens, J.,
Souter, J., Ginsburg, J., and Breyer, J., filed opinions concurring in
the judgment.
NOTICE: This opinion is subject to formal revision before publication
in the preliminary print of the United States Reports. Readers are requested
to notify the Reporter of Decisions, Supreme Court of the United States,
Washington, D.C. 20543, of any typographical or other formal errors, in
order that corrections may be made before the preliminary print goes to
press.
[1] SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
[2] No. 95-1858
[3] DENNIS C. VACCO, ATTORNEY GENERAL OF NEW YORK, et al.,
[4] PETITIONERS
v.
[5] TIMOTHY E. QUILL et al.
[6] ON WRIT OF CERTIORARI TO THE UNITED STATES COURT OF APPEALS FOR THE
SECOND CIRCUIT
[7] June 26, 1997
[8] Chief Justice Rehnquist delivered the opinion of the Court.
[9] In New York, as in most States, it is a crime to aid another to commit
or attempt suicide, *fn1 but patients may refuse even lifesaving medical
treatment. *fn2 The question presented by this case is whether New York's
prohibition on assisting suicide therefore violates the Equal Protection
Clause of the Fourteenth Amendment. We hold that it does not.
[10] Petitioners are various New York public officials. Respondents Timothy
E. Quill, Samuel C. Klagsbrun, and Howard A. Grossman are physicians who
practice in New York. They assert that although it would be "consistent
with the standards of [their] medical practice[s]" to prescribe lethal
medication for "mentally competent, terminally ill patients"
who are suffering great pain and desire a doctor's help in taking their
own lives, they are deterred from doing so by New York's ban on assisting
suicide. App. 25-26. *fn3 Respondents, and three gravely ill patients
who have since died, *fn4 sued the State's Attorney General in the United
States District Court. They urged that because New York permits a competent
person to refuse life-sustaining medical treatment, and because the refusal
of such treatment is "essentially the same thing" as physician-assisted
suicide, New York's assisted-suicide ban violates the Equal Protection
Clause. Quill v. Koppell, 870 F. Supp. 78, 84-85 (SDNY 1994).
[11] The District Court disagreed: "[I]t is hardly unreasonable
or irrational for the State to recognize a difference between allowing
nature to take its course, even in the most severe situations, and intentionally
using an artificial death-producing device." Id., at 84. The court
noted New York's "obvious legitimate interests in preserving life,
and in protecting vulnerable persons," and concluded that "[u]nder
the United States Constitution and the federal system it establishes,
the resolution of this issue is left to the normal democratic processes
within the State." Id., at 84-85.
[12] The Court of Appeals for the Second Circuit reversed. 80 F. 3d 716
(1996). The court determined that, despite the assisted-suicide ban's
apparent general applicability, "New York law does not treat equally
all competent persons who are in the final stages of fatal illness and
wish to hasten their deaths," because "those in the final stages
of terminal illness who are on life-support systems are allowed to hasten
their deaths by directing the removal of such systems; but those who are
similarly situated, except for the previous attachment of life-sustaining
equipment, are not allowed to hasten death by self-administering prescribed
drugs." Id., at 727, 729. In the court's view, "[t]he ending
of life by [the withdrawal of life-support systems] is nothing more nor
less than assisted suicide." Id., at 729 (emphasis added) (citation
omitted). The Court of Appeals then examined whether this supposed unequal
treatment was rationally related to any legitimate state interests, *fn5
and concluded that "to the extent that [New York's statutes] prohibit
a physician from prescribing medications to be self-administered by a
mentally competent, terminally-ill person in the final stages of his terminal
illness, they are not rationally related to any legitimate state interest."
Id., at 731. We granted certiorari, 518 U. S. ___ (1996), and now reverse.
[13] The Equal Protection Clause commands that no State shall "deny
to any person within its jurisdiction the equal protection of the laws."
This provision creates no substantive rights. San Antonio Independent
School Dist. v. Rodriguez, 411 U. S. 1, 33 (1973); id., at 59 (Stewart,
J., concurring). Instead, it embodies a general rule that States must
treat like cases alike but may treat unlike cases accordingly. Plyler
v. Doe, 457 U. S. 202, 216 (1982) (" `[T]he Constitution does not
require things which are different in fact or opinion to be treated in
law as though they were the same' ") (quoting Tigner v. Texas, 310
U. S. 141, 147 (1940)). If a legislative classification or distinction
"neither burdens a fundamental right nor targets a suspect class,
we will uphold [it] so long as it bears a rational relation to some legitimate
end." Romer v. Evans, 517 U. S. ___, ___ (slip op., at 10) (1996).
[14] New York's statutes outlawing assisting suicide affect and address
matters of profound significance to all New Yorkers alike. They neither
infringe fundamental rights nor involve suspect classifications. Washington
v. Glucksberg, ante, at 15-24; see 80 F. 3d, at 726; San Antonio School
Dist., 411 U. S., at 28 ("The system of alleged discrimination and
the class it defines have none of the traditional indicia of suspectness");
id., at 33-35 (courts must look to the Constitution, not the "importance"
of the asserted right, when deciding whether an asserted right is "fundamental").
These laws are therefore entitled to a "strong presumption of validity."
Heller v. Doe, 509 U. S. 312, 319 (1993).
[15] On their faces, neither New York's ban on assisting suicide nor
its statutes permitting patients to refuse medical treatment treat anyone
differently than anyone else or draw any distinctions between persons.
Everyone, regardless of physical condition, is entitled, if competent,
to refuse unwanted lifesaving medical treatment; no one is permitted to
assist a suicide. Generally speaking, laws that apply evenhandedly to
all "unquestionably comply" with the Equal Protection Clause.
New York City Transit Authority v. Beazer, 440 U. S. 568, 587 (1979);
see Personnel Administrator of Mass. v. Feeney, 442 U. S. 256, 271-273
(1979) ("[M]any [laws] affect certain groups unevenly, even though
the law itself treats them no differently from all other members of the
class described by the law").
[16] The Court of Appeals, however, concluded that some terminally ill
people-those who are on life-support systems-are treated differently than
those who are not, in that the former may "hasten death" by
ending treatment, but the latter may not "hasten death" through
physician-assisted suicide. 80 F. 3d, at 729. This conclusion depends
on the submission that ending or refusing lifesaving medical treatment
"is nothing more nor less than assisted suicide." Ibid. Unlike
the Court of Appeals, we think the distinction between assisting suicide
and withdrawing life-sustaining treatment, a distinction widely recognized
and endorsed in the medical profession *fn6 and in our legal traditions,
is both important and logical; it is certainly rational. See Feeney, supra,
at 272 ("When the basic classification is rationally based, uneven
effects upon particular groups within a class are ordinarily of no constitutional
concern").
[17] The distinction comports with fundamental legal principles of causation
and intent. First, when a patient refuses life-sustaining medical treatment,
he dies from an underlying fatal disease or pathology; but if a patient
ingests lethal medication prescribed by a physician, he is killed by that
medication. See, e.g., People v. Kevorkian, 447 Mich. 436, 470-472, 527
N. W. 2d 714, 728 (1994), cert. denied, 514 U. S. 1083 (1995); Matter
of Conroy, 98 N. J. 321, 355, 486 A. 2d 1209, 1226 (1985) (when feeding
tube is removed, death "result[s] . . . from [the patient's] underlying
medical condition"); In re Colyer, 99 Wash. 2d 114, 123, 660 P. 2d
738, 743 (1983) ("[D]eath which occurs after the removal of life
sustaining systems is from natural causes"); American Medical Association,
Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, Physician-Assisted Suicide, 10
Issues in Law & Medicine 91, 92 (1994) ("When a life-sustaining
treatment is declined, the patient dies primarily because of an underlying
disease").
[18] Furthermore, a physician who withdraws, or honors a patient's refusal
to begin, life-sustaining medical treatment purposefully intends, or may
so intend, only to respect his patient's wishes and "to cease doing
useless and futile or degrading things to the patient when [the patient]
no longer stands to benefit from them." Assisted Suicide in the United
States, Hearing before the Subcommittee on the Constitution of the House
Committee on the Judiciary, 104th Cong., 2d Sess., 368 (1996) (testimony
of Dr. Leon R. Kass). The same is true when a doctor provides aggressive
palliative care; in some cases, painkilling drugs may hasten a patient's
death, but the physician's purpose and intent is, or may be, only to ease
his patient's pain. A doctor who assists a suicide, however, "must,
necessarily and indubitably, intend primarily that the patient be made
dead." Id., at 367. Similarly, a patient who commits suicide with
a doctor's aid necessarily has the specific intent to end his or her own
life, while a patient who refuses or discontinues treatment might not.
See, e.g., Matter of Conroy, supra, at 351, 486 A. 2d, at 1224 (patients
who refuse life-sustaining treatment "may not harbor a specific intent
to die" and may instead "fervently wish to live, but to do so
free of unwanted medical technology, surgery, or drugs"); Superintendent
of Belchertown State School v. Saikewicz, 373 Mass. 728, 743, n. 11, 370
N. E. 2d 417, 426, n. 11 (1977) ("[I]n refusing treatment the patient
may not have the specific intent to die").
[19] The law has long used actors' intent or purpose to distinguish between
two acts that may have the same result. See, e.g., United States v. Bailey,
444 U. S. 394, 403-406 (1980) ("[T]he . . . common law of homicide
often distinguishes . . . between a person who knows that another person
will be killed as the result of his conduct and a person who acts with
the specific purpose of taking another's life"); Morissette v. United
States, 342 U. S. 246, 250 (1952) (distinctions based on intent are "universal
and persistent in mature systems of law"); M. Hale, 1 Pleas of the
Crown 412 (1847) ("If A., with an intent to prevent gangrene beginning
in his hand doth without any advice cut off his hand, by which he dies,
he is not thereby felo de se for tho it was a voluntary act, yet it was
not with an intent to kill himself"). Put differently, the law distinguishes
actions taken "because of" a given end from actions taken "in
spite of" their unintended but foreseen consequences. Feeney, 442
U. S., at 279; Compassion in Dying v. Washington, 79 F. 3d 790, 858 (CA9
1996) (Kleinfeld, J., dissenting) ("When General Eisenhower ordered
American soldiers onto the beaches of Normandy, he knew that he was sending
many American soldiers to certain death . . . . His purpose, though, was
to . . . liberate Europe from the Nazis").
[20] Given these general principles, it is not surprising that many courts,
including New York courts, have carefully distinguished refusing life-sustaining
treatment from suicide. See, e.g., Fosmire v. Nicoleau, 75 N. Y. 2d 218,
227, and n. 2, 551 N. E. 2d 77, 82, and n. 2 (1990) ("[M]erely declining
medical . . . care is not considered a suicidal act"). *fn7 In fact,
the first state-court decision explicitly to authorize withdrawing lifesaving
treatment noted the "real distinction between the self-infliction
of deadly harm and a self-determination against artificial life support."
In re Quinlan, 70 N. J. 10, 43, 52, and n. 9, 355 A. 2d 647, 665, 670,
and n. 9, cert. denied sub nom. Garger v. New Jersey, 429 U. S. 922 (1976).
And recently, the Michigan Supreme Court also rejected the argument that
the distinction "between acts that artificially sustain life and
acts that artificially curtail life" is merely a "distinction
without constitutional significance-a meaningless exercise in semantic
gymnastics," insisting that "the Cruzan majority disagreed and
so do we." Kevorkian, 447 Mich., at 471, 527 N. W. 2d, at 728. *fn8
[21] Similarly, the overwhelming majority of state legislatures have
drawn a clear line between assisting suicide and withdrawing or permitting
the refusal of unwanted lifesaving medical treatment by prohibiting the
former and permitting the latter. Glucksberg, ante, at 4-6, 11-15. And
"nearly all states expressly disapprove of suicide and assisted suicide
either in statutes dealing with durable powers of attorney in healthcare
situations, or in `living will' statutes." Kevorkian, 447 Mich.,
at 478-479, and nn. 53-54, 527 N. W. 2d, at 731-732, and nn. 53-54. *fn9
Thus, even as the States move to protect and promote patients' dignity
at the end of life, they remain opposed to physician-assisted suicide.
[22] New York is a case in point. The State enacted its current assisted-suicide
statutes in 1965. *fn10 Since then, New York has acted several times to
protect patients' common-law right to refuse treatment. Act of Aug. 7,
1987, ch. 818, Section(s) 1, 1987 N. Y. Laws 3140 ("Do Not Resuscitate
Orders") (codified as amended at N. Y. Pub. Health Law Section(s)
2960-2979 (McKinney 1994 and Supp. 1997)); Act of July 22, 1990, ch. 752,
Section(s) 2, 1990 N. Y. Laws 3547 ("Health Care Agents and Proxies")
(codified as amended at N. Y. Pub. Health Law Section(s) 2980-2994 (McKinney
1994 and Supp. 1997)). In so doing, however, the State has neither endorsed
a general right to "hasten death" nor approved physician-assisted
suicide. Quite the opposite: The State has reaffirmed the line between
"killing" and "letting die." See N. Y. Pub. Health
Law Section(s) 2989(3) (McKinney 1994) ("This article is not intended
to permit or promote suicide, assisted suicide, or euthanasia");
New York State Task Force on Life and the Law, Life-Sustaining Treatment:
Making Decisions and Appointing a Health Care Agent 36-42 (July 1987);
Do Not Resuscitate Orders: The Proposed Legislation and Report of the
New York State Task Force on Life and the Law 15 (Apr. 1986). More recently,
the New York State Task Force on Life and the Law studied assisted suicide
and euthanasia and, in 1994, unanimously recommended against legalization.
When Death is Sought: Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in the Medical Context
vii (1994). In the Task Force's view, "allowing decisions to forego
life-sustaining treatment and allowing assisted suicide or euthanasia
have radically different consequences and meanings for public policy."
Id., at 146.
[23] This Court has also recognized, at least implicitly, the distinction
between letting a patient die and making that patient die. In Cruzan v.
Director, Mo. Dept. of Health, 497 U. S. 261, 278 (1990), we concluded
that "[t]he principle that a competent person has a constitutionally
protected liberty interest in refusing unwanted medical treatment may
be inferred from our prior decisions," and we assumed the existence
of such a right for purposes of that case, id., at 279. But our assumption
of a right to refuse treatment was grounded not, as the Court of Appeals
supposed, on the proposition that patients have a general and abstract
"right to hasten death," 80 F. 3d, at 727-728, but on well established,
traditional rights to bodily integrity and freedom from unwanted touching,
Cruzan, 497 U. S., at 278-279; id., at 287-288 (O'Connor, J., concurring).
In fact, we observed that "the majority of States in this country
have laws imposing criminal penalties on one who assists another to commit
suicide." Id., at 280. Cruzan therefore provides no support for the
notion that refusing life-sustaining medical treatment is "nothing
more nor less than suicide." For all these reasons, we disagree with
respondents' claim that the distinction between refusing lifesaving medical
treatment and assisted suicide is "arbitrary" and "irrational."
Brief for Respondents 44. *fn11 Granted, in some cases, the line between
the two may not be clear, but certainty is not required, even were it
possible. *fn12 Logic and contemporary practice support New York's judgment
that the two acts are different, and New York may therefore, consistent
with the Constitution, treat them differently. By permitting everyone
to refuse unwanted medical treatment while prohibiting anyone from assisting
a suicide, New York law follows a longstanding and rational distinction.
[24] New York's reasons for recognizing and acting on this distinction-including
prohibiting intentional killing and preserving life; preventing suicide;
maintaining physicians' role as their patients' healers; protecting vulnerable
people from indifference, prejudice, and psychological and financial pressure
to end their lives; and avoiding a possible slide towards euthanasia-are
discussed in greater detail in our opinion in Glucksberg, ante. These
valid and important public interests easily satisfy the constitutional
requirement that a legislative classification bear a rational relation
to some legitimate end. *fn13
[25] The judgment of the Court of Appeals is reversed.
[26] It is so ordered.
[27] Justice O'Connor, concurring. *fn14
[28] Death will be different for each of us. For many, the last days
will be spent in physical pain and perhaps the despair that accompanies
physical deterioration and a loss of control of basic bodily and mental
functions. Some will seek medication to alleviate that pain and other
symptoms.
[29] The Court frames the issue in this case as whether the Due Process
Clause of the Constitution protects a "right to commit suicide which
itself includes a right to assistance in doing so," ante, at 18,
and concludes that our Nation's history, legal traditions, and practices
do not support the existence of such a right. I join the Court's opinions
because I agree that there is no generalized right to "commit suicide."
But respondents urge us to address the narrower question whether a mentally
competent person who is experiencing great suffering has a constitutionally
cognizable interest in controlling the circumstances of his or her imminent
death. I see no need to reach that question in the context of the facial
challenges to the New York and Washington laws at issue here. See ante,
at 18 ("The Washington statute at issue in this case prohibits `aid[ing]
another person to attempt suicide,'. . . and, thus, the question before
us is whether the `liberty' specially protected by the Due Process Clause
includes a right to commit suicide which itself includes a right to assistance
in doing so"). The parties and amici agree that in these States a
patient who is suffering from a terminal illness and who is experiencing
great pain has no legal barriers to obtaining medication, from qualified
physicians, to alleviate that suffering, even to the point of causing
unconsciousness and hastening death. See Wash. Rev. Code Section(s) 70.122.010
(1994); Brief for Petitioners in No. 95-1858, p. 15, n. 9; Brief for Respondents
in No. 95-1858, p. 15. In this light, even assuming that we would recognize
such an interest, I agree that the State's interests in protecting those
who are not truly competent or facing imminent death, or those whose decisions
to hasten death would not truly be voluntary, are sufficiently weighty
to justify a prohibition against physician-assisted suicide. Ante, at
27-30; post, at 11 (Stevens, J., concurring in judgments); post, at 33-39
(Souter, J., concurring in judgment).
[30] Every one of us at some point may be affected by our own or a family
member's terminal illness. There is no reason to think the democratic
process will not strike the proper balance between the interests of terminally
ill, mentally competent individuals who would seek to end their suffering
and the State's interests in protecting those who might seek to end life
mistakenly or under pressure. As the Court recognizes, States are presently
undertaking extensive and serious evaluation of physician-assisted suicide
and other related issues. Ante, at 11, 12-13; see post, at 36-39 (Souter,
J., concurring in judgment). In such circumstances, "the . . . challenging
task of crafting appropriate procedures for safeguarding . . . liberty
interests is entrusted to the `laboratory' of the States . . . in the
first instance." Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dept. of Health, 497 U.
S. 261, 292 (1990) (O'Connor, J., concurring) (citing New State Ice Co.
v. Liebmann, 285 U. S. 262, 311 (1932)).
[31] In sum, there is no need to address the question whether suffering
patients have a constitutionally cognizable interest in obtaining relief
from the suffering that they may experience in the last days of their
lives. There is no dispute that dying patients in Washington and New York
can obtain palliative care, even when doing so would hasten their deaths.
The difficulty in defining terminal illness and the risk that a dying
patient's request for assistance in ending his or her life might not be
truly voluntary justifies the prohibitions on assisted suicide we uphold
here.
[32] Justice Stevens, concurring in the judgments.
[33] The Court ends its opinion with the important observation that our
holding today is fully consistent with a continuation of the vigorous
debate about the "morality, legality, and practicality of physician-assisted
suicide" in a democratic society. Ante, at 32. I write separately
to make it clear that there is also room for further debate about the
limits that the Constitution places on the power of the States to punish
the practice.
I.
[34] The morality, legality, and practicality of capital punishment have
been the subject of debate for many years. In 1976, this Court upheld
the constitutionality of the practice in cases coming to us from Georgia,
*fn15 Florida *fn16, and Texas. *fn17 In those cases we concluded that
a State does have the power to place a lesser value on some lives than
on others; there is no absolute requirement that a State treat all human
life as having an equal right to preservation. Because the state legislatures
had sufficiently narrowed the category of lives that the State could terminate,
and had enacted special procedures to ensure that the defendant belonged
in that limited category, we concluded that the statutes were not unconstitutional
on their face. In later cases coming to us from each of those States,
however, we found that some applications of the statutes were unconstitutional.
*fn18
[35] Today, the Court decides that Washington's statute prohibiting assisted
suicide is not invalid "on its face," that is to say, in all
or most cases in which it might be applied. *fn19 That holding, however,
does not foreclose the possibility that some applications of the statute
might well be invalid.
[36] As originally filed, this case presented a challenge to the Washington
statute on its face and as it applied to three terminally ill, mentally
competent patients and to four physicians who treat terminally ill patients.
After the District Court issued its opinion holding that the statute placed
an undue burden on the right to commit physician-assisted suicide, see
Compassion in Dying v. Washington, 850 F. Supp. 1454, 1462, 1465 (WD Wash.
1994), the three patients died. Although the Court of Appeals considered
the constitutionality of the statute "as applied to the prescription
of life-ending medication for use by terminally ill, competent adult patients
who wish to hasten their deaths," Compassion in Dying v. Washington,
79 F. 3d 790, 798 (CA9 1996), the court did not have before it any individual
plaintiff seeking to hasten her death or any doctor who was threatened
with prosecution for assisting in the suicide of a particular patient;
its analysis and eventual holding that the statute was unconstitutional
was not limited to a particular set of plaintiffs before it.
[37] The appropriate standard to be applied in cases making facial challenges
to state statutes has been the subject of debate within this Court. See
Janklow v. Planned Parenthood, Sioux Falls Clinic, 517 U. S. ___ (1996).
Upholding the validity of the federal Bail Reform Act of 1984, the Court
stated in United States v. Salerno, 481 U. S. 739 (1987), that a "facial
challenge to a legislative Act is, of course, the most difficult challenge
to mount successfully, since the challenger must establish that no set
of circumstances exists under which the Act would be valid." Id.,
at 745. *fn20 I do not believe the Court has ever actually applied such
a strict standard, *fn21 even in Salerno itself, and the Court does not
appear to apply Salerno here. Nevertheless, the Court does conceive of
respondents' claim as a facial challenge-addressing not the application
of the statute to a particular set of plaintiffs before it, but the constitutionality
of the statute's categorical prohibition against "aid[ing] another
person to attempt suicide." Ante, at 18 (internal quotation marks
omitted) (citing Wash. Rev. Code Section(s) 9A.36.060(1) (1994)). Accordingly,
the Court requires the plaintiffs to show that the interest in liberty
protected by the Fourteenth Amendment "includes a right to commit
suicide which itself includes a right to assistance in doing so."
Ante, at 18.
[38] History and tradition provide ample support for refusing to recognize
an open-ended constitutional right to commit suicide. Much more than the
State's paternalistic interest in protecting the individual from the irrevocable
consequences of an ill-advised decision motivated by temporary concerns
is at stake. There is truth in John Donne's observation that "No
man is an island." *fn22 The State has an interest in preserving
and fostering the benefits that every human being may provide to the community-a
community that thrives on the exchange of ideas, expressions of affection,
shared memories and humorous incidents as well as on the material contributions
that its members create and support. The value to others of a person's
life is far too precious to allow the individual to claim a constitutional
entitlement to complete autonomy in making a decision to end that life.
Thus, I fully agree with the Court that the "liberty" protected
by the Due Process Clause does not include a categorical "right to
commit suicide which itself includes a right to assistance in doing so."
Ante, at 18.
[39] But just as our conclusion that capital punishment is not always
unconstitutional did not preclude later decisions holding that it is sometimes
impermissibly cruel, so is it equally clear that a decision upholding
a general statutory prohibition of assisted suicide does not mean that
every possible application of the statute would be valid. A State, like
Washington, that has authorized the death penalty and thereby has concluded
that the sanctity of human life does not require that it always be preserved,
must acknowledge that there are situations in which an interest in hastening
death is legitimate. Indeed, not only is that interest sometimes legitimate,
I am also convinced that there are times when it is entitled to constitutional
protection.
II.
[40] In Cruzan v. Director, Mo. Dept. of Health, 497 U. S. 261 (1990),
the Court assumed that the interest in liberty protected by the Fourteenth
Amendment encompassed the right of a terminally ill patient to direct
the withdrawal of life-sustaining treatment. As the Court correctly observes
today, that assumption "was not simply deduced from abstract concepts
of personal autonomy." Ante, at 21. Instead, it was supported by
the common-law tradition protecting the individual's general right to
refuse unwanted medical treatment. Ibid. We have recognized, however,
that this common-law right to refuse treatment is neither absolute nor
always sufficiently weighty to overcome valid countervailing state interests.
As Justice Brennan pointed out in his Cruzan dissent, we have upheld legislation
imposing punishment on persons refusing to be vaccinated, 497 U. S., at
312, n. 12, citing Jacobson v. Massachusetts, 197 U. S. 11, 26-27 (1905),
and as Justice Scalia pointed out in his concurrence, the State ordinarily
has the right to interfere with an attempt to commit suicide by, for example,
forcibly placing a bandage on a self-inflicted wound to stop the flow
of blood. 497 U. S., at 298. In most cases, the individual's constitutionally
protected interest in his or her own physical autonomy, including the
right to refuse unwanted medical treatment, will give way to the State's
interest in preserving human life.
[41] Cruzan, however, was not the normal case. Given the irreversible
nature of her illness and the progressive character of her suffering,
*fn23 Nancy Cruzan's interest in refusing medical care was incidental
to her more basic interest in controlling the manner and timing of her
death. In finding that her best interests would be served by cutting off
the nourishment that kept her alive, the trial court did more than simply
vindicate Cruzan's interest in refusing medical treatment; the court,
in essence, authorized affirmative conduct that would hasten her death.
When this Court reviewed the case and upheld Missouri's requirement that
there be clear and convincing evidence establishing Nancy Cruzan's intent
to have life-sustaining nourishment withdrawn, it made two important assumptions:
(1) that there was a "liberty interest" in refusing unwanted
treatment protected by the Due Process Clause; and (2) that this liberty
interest did not "end the inquiry" because it might be outweighed
by relevant state interests. Id., at 279. I agree with both of those assumptions,
but I insist that the source of Nancy Cruzan's right to refuse treatment
was not just a common-law rule. Rather, this right is an aspect of a far
broader and more basic concept of freedom that is even older than the
common law. *fn24 This freedom embraces, not merely a person's right to
refuse a particular kind of unwanted treatment, but also her interest
in dignity, and in determining the character of the memories that will
survive long after her death. *fn25 In recognizing that the State's interests
did not outweigh Nancy Cruzan's liberty interest in refusing medical treatment,
Cruzan rested not simply on the common-law right to refuse medical treatment,
but-at least implicitly-on the even more fundamental right to make this
"deeply personal decision," 497 U. S., at 289 (O'Connor, J.,
concurring).
[42] Thus, the common-law right to protection from battery, which included
the right to refuse medical treatment in most circumstances, did not mark
"the outer limits of the substantive sphere of liberty" that
supported the Cruzan family's decision to hasten Nancy's death. Planned
Parenthood of Southeastern Pa. v. Casey, 505 U. S. 833, 848 (1992). Those
limits have never been precisely defined. They are generally identified
by the importance and character of the decision confronted by the individual,
Whalen v. Roe, 429 U. S. 589, 599-600, n. 26 (1977). Whatever the outer
limits of the concept may be, it definitely includes protection for matters
"central to personal dignity and autonomy." Casey, 505 U. S.,
at 851. It includes,
[43] "the individual's right to make certain unusually important
decisions that will affect his own, or his family's, destiny. The Court
has referred to such decisions as implicating `basic values,' as being
`fundamental,' and as being dignified by history and tradition. The character
of the Court's language in these cases brings to mind the origins of the
American heritage of freedom-the abiding interest in individual liberty
that makes certain state intrusions on the citizen's right to decide how
he will live his own life intolerable." Fitzgerald v. Porter Memorial
Hospital, 523 F. 2d 716, 719-720 (CA7 1975) (footnotes omitted), cert.
denied, 425 U. S. 916 (1976).
[44] The Cruzan case demonstrated that some state intrusions on the right
to decide how death will be encountered are also intolerable. The now-deceased
plaintiffs in this action may in fact have had a liberty interest even
stronger than Nancy Cruzan's because, not only were they terminally ill,
they were suffering constant and severe pain. Avoiding intolerable pain
and the indignity of living one's final days incapacitated and in agony
is certainly "[a]t the heart of [the] liberty . . . to define one's
own concept of existence, of meaning, of the universe, and of the mystery
of human life." Casey, 505 U. S., at 851.
[45] While I agree with the Court that Cruzan does not decide the issue
presented by these cases, Cruzan did give recognition, not just to vague,
unbridled notions of autonomy, but to the more specific interest in making
decisions about how to confront an imminent death. Although there is no
absolute right to physician-assisted suicide, Cruzan makes it clear that
some individuals who no longer have the option of deciding whether to
live or to die because they are already on the threshold of death have
a constitutionally protected interest that may outweigh the State's interest
in preserving life at all costs. The liberty interest at stake in a case
like this differs from, and is stronger than, both the common-law right
to refuse medical treatment and the unbridled interest in deciding whether
to live or die. It is an interest in deciding how, rather than whether,
a critical threshold shall be crossed.
III.
[46] The state interests supporting a general rule banning the practice
of physician-assisted suicide do not have the same force in all cases.
First and foremost of these interests is the " `unqualified interest
in the preservation of human life,' " ante, at 24, (quoting Cruzan,
497 U. S., at 282,) which is equated with " `the sanctity of life,'
" ante, at 25, (quoting the American Law Institute, Model Penal Code
Section(s) 210.5, Comment 5, p. 100 (Official Draft and Revised Comments
1980)). That interest not only justifies-it commands-maximum protection
of every individual's interest in remaining alive, which in turn commands
the same protection for decisions about whether to commence or to terminate
life-support systems or to administer pain medication that may hasten
death. Properly viewed, however, this interest is not a collective interest
that should always outweigh the interests of a person who because of pain,
incapacity, or sedation finds her life intolerable, but rather, an aspect
of individual freedom.
[47] Many terminally ill people find their lives meaningful even if filled
with pain or dependence on others. Some find value in living through suffering;
some have an abiding desire to witness particular events in their families'
lives; many believe it a sin to hasten death. Individuals of different
religious faiths make different judgments and choices about whether to
live on under such circumstances. There are those who will want to continue
aggressive treatment; those who would prefer terminal sedation; and those
who will seek withdrawal from life-support systems and death by gradual
starvation and dehydration. Although as a general matter the State's interest
in the contributions each person may make to society outweighs the person's
interest in ending her life, this interest does not have the same force
for a terminally ill patient faced not with the choice of whether to live,
only of how to die. Allowing the individual, rather than the State, to
make judgments " `about the "quality" of life that a particular
individual may enjoy.' " ante, at 25 (quoting Cruzan, 497 U. S.,
at 282), does not mean that the lives of terminally-ill, disabled people
have less value than the lives of those who are healthy, see ante, at
28. Rather, it gives proper recognition to the individual's interest in
choosing a final chapter that accords with her life story, rather than
one that demeans her values and poisons memories of her. See Brief for
Bioethicists as Amici Curiae 11; see also R. Dworkin, Life's Dominion
213 (1993) ("Whether it is in someone's best interests that his life
end in one way rather than another depends on so much else that is special
about him-about the shape and character of his life and his own sense
of his integrity and critical interests-that no uniform collective decision
can possibly hope to serve everyone even decently").
[48] Similarly, the State's legitimate interests in preventing suicide,
protecting the vulnerable from coercion and abuse, and preventing euthanasia
are less significant in this context. I agree that the State has a compelling
interest in preventing persons from committing suicide because of depression,
or coercion by third parties. But the State's legitimate interest in preventing
abuse does not apply to an individual who is not victimized by abuse,
who is not suffering from depression, and who makes a rational and voluntary
decision to seek assistance in dying. Although, as the New York Task Force
report discusses, diagnosing depression and other mental illness is not
always easy, mental health workers and other professionals expert in working
with dying patients can help patients cope with depression and pain, and
help patients assess their options. See Brief for Washington State Psychological
Association et al. as Amici Curiae 8-10.
[49] Relatedly, the State and amici express the concern that patients
whose physical pain is inadequately treated will be more likely to request
assisted suicide. Encouraging the development and ensuring the availability
of adequate pain treatment is of utmost importance; palliative care, however,
cannot alleviate all pain and suffering. See Orentlicher, Legalization
of Physician Assisted Suicide: A Very Modest Revolution, 38 Boston College
L. Rev. (Galley, p. 8) (1997) ("Greater use of palliative care would
reduce the demand for assisted suicide, but it will not eliminate [it]");
see also Brief for Coalition of Hospice Professionals as Amici Curiae
8 (citing studies showing that "[a]s death becomes more imminent,
pain and suffering become progressively more difficult to treat").
An individual adequately informed of the care alternatives thus might
make a rational choice for assisted suicide. For such an individual, the
State's interest in preventing potential abuse and mistake is only minimally
implicated.
[50] The final major interest asserted by the State is its interest in
preserving the traditional integrity of the medical profession. The fear
is that a rule permitting physicians to assist in suicide is inconsistent
with the perception that they serve their patients solely as healers.
But for some patients, it would be a physician's refusal to dispense medication
to ease their suffering and make their death tolerable and dignified that
would be inconsistent with the healing role See Block & Billings,
Patient Request to Hasten Death, 154 Archives Internal Med. 2039, 2045
(1994) (A doctor's refusal to hasten death "may be experienced by
the [dying] patient as an abandonment, a rejection, or an expression of
inappropriate paternalistic authority"). For doctors who have long-standing
relationships with their patients, who have given their patients advice
on alternative treatments, who are attentive to their patient's individualized
needs, and who are knowledgeable about pain symptom management and palliative
care options, see Quill, Death and Dignity, A Case of Individualized Decision
Making, 324 New England J. of Med. 691-694 (1991), heeding a patient's
desire to assist in her suicide would not serve to harm the physician-patient
relationship. Furthermore, because physicians are already involved in
making decisions that hasten the death of terminally ill patients-through
termination of life support, withholding of medical treatment, and terminal
sedation-there is in fact significant tension between the traditional
view of the physician's role and the actual practice in a growing number
of cases. *fn26
[51] As the New York State Task Force on Life and the Law recognized,
a State's prohibition of assisted suicide is justified by the fact that
the " `ideal' " case in which "patients would be screened
for depression and offered treatment, effective pain medication would
be available, and all patients would have a supportive committed family
and doctor" is not the usual case. New York State Task Force on Life
and the Law, When Death Is Sought: Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in
the Medical Context 120 (May 1994). Although, as the Court concludes today,
these potential harms are sufficient to support the State's general public
policy against assisted suicide, they will not always outweigh the individual
liberty interest of a particular patient. Unlike the Court of Appeals,
I would not say as a categorical matter that these state interests are
invalid as to the entire class of terminally ill, mentally competent patients.
I do not, however, foreclose the possibility that an individual plaintiff
seeking to hasten her death, or a doctor whose assistance was sought,
could prevail in a more particularized challenge. Future cases will determine
whether such a challenge may succeed.
IV.
[52] In New York, a doctor must respect a competent person's decision
to refuse or to discontinue medical treatment even though death will thereby
ensue, but the same doctor would be guilty of a felony if she provided
her patient assistance in committing suicide. *fn27 Today we hold that
the Equal Protection Clause is not violated by the resulting disparate
treatment of two classes of terminally ill people who may have the same
interest in hastening death. I agree that the distinction between permitting
death to ensue from an underlying fatal disease and causing it to occur
by the administration of medication or other means provides a constitutionally
sufficient basis for the State's classification. *fn28 Unlike the Court,
however, see Vacco, ante, at 6-7, I am not persuaded that in all cases
there will in fact be a significant difference between the intent of the
physicians, the patients or the families in the two situations.
[53] There may be little distinction between the intent of a terminally-ill
patient who decides to remove her life-support and one who seeks the assistance
of a doctor in ending her life; in both situations, the patient is seeking
to hasten a certain, impending death. The doctor's intent might also be
the same in prescribing lethal medication as it is in terminating life
support. A doctor who fails to administer medical treatment to one who
is dying from a disease could be doing so with an intent to harm or kill
that patient. Conversely, a doctor who prescribes lethal medication does
not necessarily intend the patient's death-rather that doctor may seek
simply to ease the patient's suffering and to comply with her wishes.
The illusory character of any differences in intent or causation is confirmed
by the fact that the American Medical Association unequivocally endorses
the practice of terminal sedation-the administration of sufficient dosages
of pain-killing medication to terminally ill patients to protect them
from excruciating pain even when it is clear that the time of death will
be advanced. The purpose of terminal sedation is to ease the suffering
of the patient and comply with her wishes, and the actual cause of death
is the administration of heavy doses of lethal sedatives. This same intent
and causation may exist when a doctor complies with a patient's request
for lethal medication to hasten her death. *fn29
[54] Thus, although the differences the majority notes in causation and
intent between terminating life-support and assisting in suicide support
the Court's rejection of the respondents' facial challenge, these distinctions
may be inapplicable to particular terminally ill patients
and their doctors. Our holding today in Vacco
v. Quill that
the Equal Protection Clause is not violated by New York's classification,
just like our holding in Washington v. Glucksberg that the Washington
statute is not invalid on its face, does not foreclose the possibility
that some applications of the New York statute may impose an intolerable
intrusion on the patient's freedom.
[55] There remains room for vigorous debate about the outcome of particular
cases that are not necessarily resolved by the opinions announced today.
How such cases may be decided will depend on their specific facts. In
my judgment, however, it is clear that the so-called "unqualified
interest in the preservation of human life," Cruzan, 497 U. S., at
282, Glucksberg, ante, at 24, is not itself sufficient to outweigh the
interest in liberty that may justify the only possible means of preserving
a dying patient's dignity and alleviating her intolerable suffering.
[56] Justice Souter, concurring in the judgment.
[57] Even though I do not conclude that assisted suicide is a fundamental
right entitled to recognition at this time, I accord the claims raised
by the patients and physicians in this case and Washington v. Glucksberg
a high degree of importance, requiring a commensurate justification. See
Washington v. Glucksberg, ante, at 24-41 (Souter, J., concurring in judgment).
The reasons that lead me to conclude in Glucksberg that the prohibition
on assisted suicide is not arbitrary under the due process standard also
support the distinction between assistance to suicide, which is banned,
and practices such as termination of artificial life support and death-hastening
pain medication, which are permitted. I accordingly concur in the judgment
of the Court.
[58] Justice Ginsburg, concurring in the judgments.
[59] I concur in the Court's judgments in these cases substantially for
the reasons stated by Justice O'Connor in her concurring opinion.
***** BEGIN FOOTNOTE(S) HERE *****
[60] *fn1 N. Y. Penal Law Section(s) 125.15 (McKinney 1987) ("Manslaughter
in the second degree") provides: "A person is guilty of manslaughter
in the second degree when . . . (3) He intentionally causes or aids another
person to commit suicide. Manslaughter in the second degree is a class
C felony." Section 120.30 ("Promoting a suicide attempt")
states: "A person is guilty of promoting a suicide attempt when he
intentionally causes or aids another person to attempt suicide. Promoting
a suicide attempt is a class E felony." See generally, Washington
v. Glucksberg, ___ U. S. ___ (1997), ante, at 4-15.
[61] *fn2 "It is established under New York law that a competent
person may refuse medical treatment, even if the withdrawal of such treatment
will result in death." Quill v. Koppell, 870 F. Supp. 78, 84 (SDNY
1994); see N. Y. Pub. Health Law, Art. 29-B, Section(s) 2960-2979 (McKinney
1993 & Supp. 1997) ("Orders Not to Resuscitate") (regulating
right of "adult with capacity" to direct issuance of orders
not to resuscitate); id., Section(s) 2980-2994 ("Health Care Agents
and Proxies") (allowing appointment of agents "to make . . .
health care decisions on the principal's behalf," including decisions
to refuse lifesaving treatment).
[62] *fn3 Declaration of Timothy E. Quill, M. D., App. 42-49; Declaration
of Samuel C. Klagsbrun, M. D., id., at 68-74; Declaration of Howard A.
Grossman, M. D., id., at 84-89; 80 F. 3d 716, 719 (CA2 1996).
[63] *fn4 These three patients stated that they had no chance of recovery,
faced the "prospect of progressive loss of bodily function and integrity
and increasing pain and suffering," and desired medical assistance
in ending their lives. App. 25-26; Declaration of William A. Barth, id.,
at 96-98; Declaration of George A. Kingsley, id., at 99-102; Declaration
of Jane Doe, id., at 105-109.
[64] *fn5 The court acknowledged that because New York's assisted-suicide
statutes "do not impinge on any fundamental rights [or] involve suspect
classifications," they were subject only to rational-basis judicial
scrutiny. 80 F. 3d, at 726-727.
[65] *fn6 The American Medical Association emphasizes the "fundamental
difference between refusing life-sustaining treatment and demanding a
life-ending treatment." American Medical Association, Council on
Ethical and Judicial Affairs, Physician-Assisted Suicide, 10 Issues in
Law & Medicine 91, 93 (1994); see also American Medical Association,
Council on Ethical and Judicial Affairs, Decisions Near the End of Life,
267 JAMA 2229, 2230-2231, 2233 (1992) ("The withdrawing or withholding
of life-sustaining treatment is not inherently contrary to the principles
of beneficence and nonmaleficence," but assisted suicide "is
contrary to the prohibition against using the tools of medicine to cause
a patient's death"); New York State Task Force on Life and the Law,
When Death is Sought: Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in the Medical Context
108 (1994) ("[Professional organizations] consistently distinguish
assisted suicide and euthanasia from the withdrawing or withholding of
treatment, and from the provision of palliative treatments or other medical
care that risk fatal side effects"); Brief for the American Medical
Association et al. as Amici Curiae 18-25. Of course, as respondents' lawsuit
demonstrates, there are differences of opinion within the medical profession
on this question. See New York Task Force, When Death is Sought, supra,
at 104-109.
[66] *fn7 Thus, the Second Circuit erred in reading New York law as creating
a "right to hasten death"; instead, the authorities cited by
the court recognize a right to refuse treatment, and nowhere equate the
exercise of this right with suicide. Schloendorff v. Society of New York
Hospital, 211 N. Y. 125, 129-130, 105 N. E. 92, 93 (1914), which contains
Justice Cardozo's famous statement that "[e]very human being of adult
years and sound mind has a right to determine what shall be done with
his own body," was simply an informed-consent case. See also Rivers
v. Katz, 67 N. Y. 2d 485, 495, 495 N. E. 2d 337, 343 (1986) (right to
refuse antipsychotic medication is not absolute, and may be limited when
"the patient presents a danger to himself"); Matter of Storar,
52 N. Y. 2d 363, 377, n. 6, 420 N. E. 2d 64, 71, n. 6, cert. denied, 454
U. S. 858 (1981).
[67] *fn8 Many courts have recognized this distinction. See, e.g., Kevorkian
v. Thompson, 947 F. Supp. 1152, 1178, and nn. 20-21 (ED Mich. 1997); In
re Fiori, 543 Pa. 592, 602, 673 A. 2d 905, 910 (1996); Singletary v. Costello,
665 So. 2d 1099, 1106 (Fla. App. 1996); Laurie v. Senecal, 666 A. 2d 806,
808-809 (R. I. 1995); State ex rel. Schuetzle v. Vogel, 537 N. W. 2d 358,
360 (N. D. 1995); Thor v. Superior Court, 5 Cal. 4th 725, 741-742, 855
P. 2d 375, 385-386 (1993); DeGrella v. Elston, 858 S. W. 2d 698, 707 (Ky.
1993); People v. Adams, 216 Cal. App. 3d 1431, 1440, 265 Cal. Rptr. 568,
573-574 (1990); Guardianship of Jane Doe, 411 Mass. 512, 522-523, 583
N. E. 2d 1263, 1270, cert. denied sub nom. Doe v. Gross, 503 U. S. 950
(1992); In re L. W., 167 Wis. 2d 53, 83, 482 N. W. 2d 60, 71 (1992); In
re Rosebush, 195 Mich. App. 675, 681, n. 2, 491 N. W. 2d 633, 636, n.
2 (1992); Donaldson v. Van de Kamp, 2 Cal. App. 4th 1614, 1619-1625, 4
Cal. Rptr. 2d 59, 61-64 (1992); In re Lawrance, 579 N. E. 2d 32, 40, n.
4 (Ind. 1991); McKay v. Bergstedt, 106 Nev. 808, 822-823, 801 P. 2d 617,
626-627 (1990); In re Browning, 568 So. 2d 4, 14 (Fla. 1990); McConnell
v. Beverly Enterprises-Connecticut, Inc., 209 Conn. 692, 710, 553 A. 2d
596, 605 (1989); State v. McAfee, 259 Ga. 579, 581, 385 S. E. 2d 651,
652 (1989); In re Grant, 109 Wash. 2d 545, 563, 747 P. 2d 445, 454-455
(1987); In re Gardner, 534 A. 2d 947, 955-956 (Me. 1987); Matter of Farrell,
108 N. J. 335, 349-350, 529 A. 2d 404, 411 (1987); Rasmussen v. Fleming,
154 Ariz. 207, 218, 741 P. 2d 674, 685 (1987); Bouvia v. Superior Court,
179 Cal. App. 3d 1127, 1144-1145, 225 Cal. Rptr. 297, 306 (1986); Von
Holden v. Chapman, 87 App. Div. 2d 66, 70, 450 N. Y. S. 2d 623, 627 (1982);
Bartling v. Superior Court, 163 Cal. App. 3d 186, 196-197, 209 Cal. Rptr.
220, 225-226 (1984); Foody v. Manchester Memorial Hospital, 40 Conn. Sup.
127, 137, 482 A. 2d 713, 720 (1984); In re P. V. W., 424 So. 2d 1015,
1022 (La. 1982); Leach v. Akron General Medical Center, 68 Ohio Misc.
1, 10, 426 N. E. 2d 809, 815 (Ohio Comm. Pleas 1980); In re Severns, 425
A. 2d 156, 161 (Del. Ch. 1980); Satz v. Perlmutter, 362 So. 2d 160, 162-163
(Fla. App. 1978); Application of the President and Directors of Georgetown
College, 331 F. 2d 1000, 1009 (CADC), cert. denied, 377 U. S. 978 (1964);
Brophy v. New England Sinai Hospital, 398 Mass. 417, 439, 497 N. E. 2d
626, 638 (1986). The British House of Lords has also recognized the distinction.
Airedale N. H. S. Trust v. Bland, 2 W. L. R. 316, 368 (1993).
[68] *fn9 See Ala. Code Section(s) 22-8A-10 (1990); Alaska Stat. Ann.
Section(s) 18.12.080(a), (f) (1996); Ariz. Rev. Stat. Ann. Section(s)
36-3210 (Supp. 1996); Ark. Code Ann. Section(s) 20-13-905(a), (f), 20-17-210(a),(g)
(1991 and Supp. 1995); Cal. Health & Safety Code Ann. Section(s) 7191.5(a),
(g) (West Supp. 1997); Cal. Prob. Code Ann. Section(s) 4723 (West. Supp.
1997); Colo. Rev. Stat. Section(s) 15-14-504(4), 15-18-112(1), 15-18.5-101(3),
15-18.6-108 (1987 and Supp. 1996); Conn. Gen. Stat. Section(s) 19a-575
(Supp. 1996); Del. Code Ann., Tit. 16, Section(s) 2512 (Supp. 1996); D.
C. Code Ann. Section(s) 6-2430, 21-2212 (1995 and Supp. 1996); Fla. Stat.
Section(s) 765.309(1), (2) (Supp. 1997); Ga. Code Ann. Section(s) 31-32-11(b),
31-36-2(b) (1996); Haw. Rev. Stat. Section(s) 327D-13 (1996); Idaho Code
Section(s) 39-152 (Supp. 1996); Ill. Comp. Stat., ch. 755, Section(s)
35/9(f), 40/5, 40/50, 45/2-1 (1992); Ind. Code Section(s) 16-36-1-13,
16-36-4-19, 30-5-5-17 (1994 and Supp. 1996); Iowa Code Section(s) 144A.11.1-144A.11.6,
144B.12.2 (1989 and West Supp. 1997); Kan. Stat. Ann. Section(s) 65-28,109
(1985); Ky. Rev. Stat. Ann. Section(s) 311.638 (Baldwin Supp. 1992); La.
Rev. Stat. Ann. 40: Section(s) 1299.58.10(A), (B) (West 1992); Me. Rev.
Stat. Ann., Tit. 18-A, Section(s) 5-813(b), (c) (West Supp. 1996); Mass.
Gen. Laws 201D, Section(s) 12 (Supp. 1997); Md. Health Code Ann. Section(s)
5-611(c) (1994); Mich. Comp. Laws Ann. Section(s) 700.496(20) (West 1995);
Minn. Stat. Section(s) 145B.14, 145C.14 (Supp. 1997); Miss. Code Ann.
Section(s) 41-41-117(2),41-41-119(1) (Supp. 1992); Mo. Rev. Stat. Section(s)
459.015.3, 459.055(5) (1992); Mont. Code Ann. Section(s) 50-9-205(1),
(7), 50-10-104(1), (6) (1995); Neb. Rev. Stat. Section(s) 20-412(1), (7),
30-3401(3) (1995); N. H. Rev. Stat. Ann. Section(s) 137-H:10, 137-H:13,
137-J:1 (1996); N. J. Stat. Ann. Section(s) 26:2H-54(d), (e), 26:2H-77
(West 1996); N. M. Stat. Ann. Section(s) 24-7A-13(B)(1), (C) (Supp. 1995);
N. Y. Pub. Health Law Section(s) 2989(3) (1993); Nev. Rev. Stat. Section(s)
449.670(2) (1996); N. C. Gen. Stat. Section(s) 90-320(b), 90-321(f) (1993);
N. D. Cent. Code Section(s) 23-06.4-01, 23-06.5-01 (1991); Ohio Rev. Code
Ann. Section(s) 2133.12(A), (D) (Supp. 1996); Okla. Stat. Ann., Tit. 63,
Section(s) 3101.2(C),3101.12(A),(G) (1996); 20 Pa. Cons. Stat. Section(s)
5402(b) (Supp. 1996); R. I. Gen. Laws Section(s) 23-4.10-9(a), (f), 23-4.11-10(a),
(f) (1996); S. C. Code Ann. Section(s) 44-77-130, 44-78-50(A), (C), 62-5-504(O)
(Supp. 1996); S. D. Codified Laws Section(s) 34-12D-14, 34-12D-20 (1994);
Tenn. Code Ann. Section(s) 32-11-110(a), 39-13-216 (Supp. 1996); Tex.
Health & Safety Code Ann. Section(s) 672.017, 672.020, 672.021 (1992);
Utah Code Ann. Section(s) 75-2-1116,75-2-1118 (1993); Va. Code Ann. Section(s)
54.1-2990 (1994); Vt. Stat. Ann., Tit. 18, Section(s) 5260 (1987); V.
I. Code Ann., Tit. 19, Section(s) 198(a), (g) (1995); Wash. Rev. Code
Section(s) 70.122.070(1), 70.122.100 (Supp. 1997); W. Va. Code Section(s)
16-30-10, 16-30A-16(a), 16-30B-2(b), 16-30B-13, 16-30C-14 (1995); Wis.
Stat. Section(s) 154.11(1), (6), 154.25(7), 155.70(7) (Supp. 1996); Wyo.
Stat. Section(s) 3-5-211, 35-22-109, 35-22-208 (1994 & Supp. 1996).
See also, 42 U. S. C. Section(s) 14402(b)(1), (2), (4) ("Assisted
Suicide Funding Restriction Act of 1997").
[69] *fn10 It has always been a crime, either by statute or under the
common law, to assist a suicide in New York. See Marzen, O'Dowd, Crone,
& Balch, Suicide: A Constitutional Right?, 24 Duquesne L. Rev. 1,
205-210 (1985) (Appendix).
[70] *fn11 Respondents also argue that the State irrationally distinguishes
between physician-assisted suicide and "terminal sedation,"
a process respondents characterize as "induc[ing] barbiturate coma
and then starv[ing] the person to death." Brief for Respondents 48-50;
see 80 F. 3d, at 729. Petitioners insist, however, that " `[a]lthough
proponents of physician-assisted suicide and euthanasia contend that terminal
sedation is covert physician-assisted suicide or euthanasia, the concept
of sedating pharmacotherapy is based on informed consent and the principle
of double effect.' " Reply Brief for Petitioners 12 (quoting P. Rousseau,
Terminal Sedation in the Care of Dying Patients, 156 Archives Internal
Med. 1785, 1785-1786 (1996)). Just as a State may prohibit assisting suicide
while permitting patients to refuse unwanted lifesaving treatment, it
may permit palliative care related to that refusal, which may have the
foreseen but unintended "double effect" of hastening the patient's
death. See New York Task Force, When Death is Sought, supra, n. 6, at
163 ("It is widely recognized that the provision of pain medication
is ethically and professionally acceptable even when the treatment may
hasten the patient's death, if the medication is intended to alleviate
pain and severe discomfort, not to cause death").
[71] *fn12 We do not insist, as Justice Stevens suggests, ante, at 14-15
(concurring opinion), that "in all cases there will in fact be a
significant difference between the intent of the physicians, the patients
or the families [in withdrawal-of-treatment and physician-assisted-suicide
cases]." See 6-7, supra ("[A] physician who withdraws, or honors
a patient's refusal to begin, life-sustaining medical treatment purposefully
intends, or may so intend, only to respect his patient's wishes . . .
. The same is true when a doctor provides aggressive palliative care;
. . . the physician's purpose and intent is, or may be, only to ease his
patient's pain") (emphasis added). In the absence of omniscience,
however, the State is entitled to act on the reasonableness of the distinction.
[72] *fn13 Justice Stevens observes that our holding today "does
not foreclose the possibility that some applications of the New York statute
may impose an intolerable intrusion on the patient's freedom." Ante,
at 16 (concurring opinion). This is true, but, as we observe in Glucksberg,
ante, at 31-32, n. 24, a particular plaintiff hoping to show that New
York's assisted-suicide ban was unconstitutional in his particular case
would need to present different and considerably stronger arguments than
those advanced by respondents here.
[73] *fn14 Justice Ginsburg concurs in the Court's judgments substantially
for the reasons stated in this opinion. Justice Breyer joins this opinion
except insofar as it joins the opinions of the Court.
[74] *fn15 Gregg v. Georgia, 428 U. S. 153 (1976)
[75] *fn16 Proffitt v. Florida, 428 U. S. 242 (1976).
[76] *fn17 Jurek v. Texas, 428 U. S. 262 (1976).
[77] *fn18 See, e.g., Godfrey v. Georgia, 446 U. S. 420 (1980); Enmund
v. Florida, 458 U. S. 782 (1982); Penry v. Lynaugh, 492 U. S. 302 (1989).
[78] *fn19 See ante, at 3, n. 5.
[79] *fn20 If the Court had actually applied the Salerno standard in
this action, it would have taken only a few paragraphs to identify situations
in which the Washington statute could be validly enforced. In Salerno
itself, the Court would have needed only to look at whether the statute
could be constitutionally applied to the arrestees before it; any further
analysis would have been superfluous. See Dorf, Facial Challenges to State
and Federal Statutes, 46 Stan. L. Rev. 235, 239-240 (1994) (arguing that
if the Salerno standard were taken literally, a litigant could not succeed
in her facial challenge unless she also succeeded in her as applied challenge).
[80] *fn21 In other cases and in other contexts, we have imposed a significantly
lesser burden on the challenger. The most lenient standard that we have
applied requires the challenger to establish that the invalid applications
of a statute "must not only be real, but substantial as well, judged
in relation to the statute's plainly legitimate sweep." Broadrick
v. Oklahoma, 413 U. S. 601, 615 (1973). As the Court's opinion demonstrates,
Washington's statute prohibiting assisted suicide has a "plainly
legitimate sweep." While that demonstration provides a sufficient
justification for rejecting respondents' facial challenge, it does not
mean that every application of the statute should or will be upheld.
[81] *fn22 "Who casts not up his eye to the sun when it rises? but
who takes off his eye from a comet when that breaks out? Who bends not
his ear to any bell which upon any occasion rings? but who can remove
it from that bell which is passing a piece of himself out of this world?
No man is an island, entire of itself; every man is a piece of the continent,
a part of the main. If a clod be washed away by the sea, Europe is the
less, as well as if a promontory were, as well as if a manor of thy friend's
or of thine own were; any man's death diminishes me, because I am involved
in mankind; and therefore never send to know for whom the bell tolls;
it tolls for thee." J. Donne, Meditation No. 17, Devotions Upon Emergent
Occasions 86, 87 (A. Raspa ed. 1987).
[82] *fn23 See 497 U. S., at 332, n. 2.
[83] *fn24 "[N]either the Bill of Rights nor the laws of sovereign
States create the liberty which the Due Process Clause protects. The relevant
constitutional provisions are limitations on the power of the sovereign
to infringe on the liberty of the citizen. The relevant state laws either
create property rights, or they curtail the freedom of the citizen who
must live in an ordered society. Of course, law is essential to the exercise
and enjoyment of individual liberty in a complex society. But it is not
the source of liberty, and surely not the exclusive source.
[84] "I had thought it self-evident that all men were endowed by
their Creator with liberty as one of the cardinal unalienable rights.
It is that basic freedom which the Due Process Clause protects, rather
than the particular rights or privileges conferred by specific laws or
regulations." Meachum v. Fano, 427 U. S. 215, 230 (1976) (Stevens,
J., dissenting).
[85] *fn25 "Nancy Cruzan's interest in life, no less than that of
any other person, includes an interest in how she will be thought of after
her death by those whose opinions mattered to her. There can be no doubt
that her life made her dear to her family and to others. How she dies
will affect how that life is remembered." Cruzan v. Director, Mo.
Dept. of Health, 497 U. S. 261, 344 (1990) (Stevens, J., dissenting).
[86] "Each of us has an interest in the kind of memories that will
survive after death. To that end, individual decisions are often motivated
by their impact on others. A member of the kind of family identified in
the trial court's findings in this case would likely have not only a normal
interest in minimizing the burden that her own illness imposes on others,
but also an interest in having their memories of her filled predominantly
with thoughts about her past vitality rather than her current condition."
Id., at 356.
[87] *fn26 I note that there is evidence that a significant number of
physicians support the practice of hastening death in particular situations.
A survey published in the New England Journal of Medicine, found that
56% of responding doctors in Michigan preferred legalizing assisted suicide
to an explicit ban. Bachman et al., Attitudes of Michigan Physicians and
the Public Toward Legalizing Physician-Assisted Suicide and Voluntary
Euthanasia, 334 New England J. Med. 303-309 (1996). In a survey of Oregon
doctors, 60% of the responding doctors supported legalizing assisted suicide
for terminally ill patients. See Lee et al., Legalizing Assisted Suicide-Views
of Physicians in Oregon, 335 New England J. Med. 310-315 (1996). Another
study showed that 12% of physicians polled in Washington State reported
that they had been asked by their terminally ill patients for prescriptions
to hasten death, and that, in the year prior to the study, 24% of those
physicians had complied with such requests. See Back, Wallace, Starks,
& Perlman, Physician-Assisted Suicide and Euthanasia in Washington
State, 275 JAMA 919-925 (1996); see also Doukas, Waterhouse, Gorenflo,
& Seld, Attitudes and Behaviors on Physician-Assisted Death: A Study
of Michigan Oncologists, 13 J. Clinical Oncology 1055 (1995) (reporting
that 18% of responding Michigan oncologists reported active participation
in assisted suicide); Slome, Moulton, Huffine, Gorter, & Abrams, Physicians'
Attitudes Toward Assisted Suicide in AIDS, 5 J. Acquired Immune Deficiency
Syndromes 712 (1992) (reporting that 24% of responding physicians who
treat AIDS patients would likely grant a patient's request for assistance
in hastening death).
[88] *fn27 See Vacco v.
Quill, ante, at 1, nn. 1 and 2.
[89] *fn28 The American Medical Association recognized this distinction
when it supported Nancy Cruzan and continues to recognize this distinction
in its support of the States in these cases.
[90] *fn29 If a doctor prescribes lethal drugs to be self-administered
by the patient, it not at all clear that the physician's intent is that
the patient "be made dead," ante, at 7 (internal quotation marks
omitted). Many patients prescribed lethal medications never actually take
them; they merely acquire some sense of control in the process of dying
that the availability of those medications provides. See Back, supra n.
12, at 922; see also Quill, 324 New England J. Med., at 693 (describing
how some patients fear death less when they feel they have the option
of physician-assisted suicide).
***** END FOOTNOTE(S) HERE *****
[Editor's note: Illustrations from the original opinion, if any, are
available in the print version]
Copyright 1998 VersusLaw, Inc., (206) 250-0142 http://www.versuslaw.com
19970626
1997.SCT.84
|