Home |
Climate Change Project |
Table of Contents |
Courses | Search |
[1] | SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES |
[2] | No. 00-1406 |
[3] | 2002.SCT.0000109 <http://www.versuslaw.com> |
[4] | June 10, 2002 |
[5] | CHEVRON U. S. A. INC., PETITIONER v. MARIO ECHAZABAL |
[6] | SYLLABUS BY THE COURT |
[7] | OCTOBER TERM, 2001 |
[8] | Argued February 27, 2002 |
[9] | Decided June 10, 2002 |
[10] | Respondent Echazabal worked for independent contractors at one of petitioner
Chevron U. S A. Inc.'s oil refineries until Chevron refused to hire him
because of a liver condition -- which its doctors said would be exacerbated
by continued exposure to toxins at the refinery -- and the contractor
employing him laid him off in response to Chevron's request that it reassign
him to a job without exposure to toxins or remove him from the refinery.
Echazabal filed suit, claiming, among other things, that Chevron's actions
violated the Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990 (ADA). Chevron defended
under an Equal Employment Opportunity Commission (EEOC) regulation permitting
the defense that a worker's disability on the job would pose a direct
threat to his health. The District Court granted Chevron summary judgment,
but the Ninth Circuit reversed, finding that the regulation exceeded the
scope of permissible rulemaking under the ADA. |
[11] | Held: The ADA permits the EEOC's regulation. Pp. 3-13. |
[12] | (a) The ADA's discrimination definition covers a number of things an
employer might do to block a disabled person from advancing in the workplace,
such as "using qualification standards ... that screen out or tend to
screen out [such] an individual," 42 U. S. C. §12112(b)(6). And along
with §12113(a), the definition creates an affirmative defense for action
under a qualification standard "shown to be job-related ... and ... consistent
with business necessity," which "may include a requirement that an individual
shall not pose a direct threat to the health or safety of other individuals
in the workplace," §12113(b). The EEOC's regulation carries the defense
one step further, allowing an employer to screen out a potential worker
with a disability for risks on the job to his own health or safety. Pp.
3-5. |
[13] | (b) Echazabal relies on the canon expressio unius exclusio alterius
-- expressing one item of an associated group excludes another left unmentioned
-- for his argument that the ADA, by recognizing only threats to others,
precludes the regulation as a matter of law. The first strike against
the expression-exclusion rule here is in the statute, which includes the
threat-to-others provision as an example of legitimate qualifications
that are "job-related and consistent with business necessity." These spacious
defensive categories seem to give an agency a good deal of discretion
in setting the limits of permissible qualification standards. And the
expansive "may include" phrase points directly away from the sort of exclusive
specifications that Echazabal claims. Strike two is the failure to identify
any series of terms or things that should be understood to go hand in
hand, which are abridged in circumstances supporting a sensible inference
that the term left out must have been meant to be excluded. Echazabal
claims that Congress's adoption only of the threat-to-others exception
in the ADA was a deliberate omission of the threat-to-self exception included
in the EEOC's regulation implementing the precursor Rehabilitation Act
of 1973, which has language identical to that in the ADA. But this is
not an unequivocal implication of congressional intent. Because the EEOC
was not the only agency interpreting the Rehabilitation Act, its regulation
did not establish a clear, standard pairing of threats to self and others.
And, it is likely that Congress used such language in the ADA knowing
what the EEOC had made of that language under the earlier statute. The
third strike is simply that there is no apparent stopping point to the
argument that, by specifying a threat-to-others defense, Congress intended
a negative implication about those whose safety could be considered. For
example, Congress could not have meant that an employer could not defend
a refusal to hire when a worker's disability would threaten others outside
the workplace. Pp. 5-9. |
[14] | (c) Since Congress has not spoken exhaustively on threats to a worker's
own health, the regulation can claim adherence under the rule in Chevron
U. S. A. Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense Council, Inc., 467 U. S. 837,
843, so long as it makes sense of the statutory defense for qualification
standards that are "job-related and consistent with business necessity."
Chevron's reasons for claiming that the regulation is reasonable include,
inter alia, that it allows Chevron to avoid the risk of violating the
Occupational Safety and Health Act of 1970 (OSHA). Whether an employer
would be liable under OSHA for hiring an individual who consents to a
job's particular dangers is an open question, but the employer would be
courting trouble under OSHA. The EEOC's resolution exemplifies the substantive
choices that agencies are expected to make when Congress leaves the intersection
of competing objectives both imprecisely marked and subject to administrative
leeway. Nor can the EEOC's resolution be called unreasonable as allowing
the kind of workplace paternalism the ADA was meant to outlaw. The ADA
was trying to get at refusals to give an even break to classes of disabled
people, while claiming to act for their own good in reliance on untested
and pretextual stereotypes. This sort of sham protection is just what
the regulation disallows, by demanding a particularized enquiry into the
harms an employee would probably face. Finally, that the threat-to-self
defense reasonably falls within the general "job related" and "business
necessity" standard does not reduce the "direct threat" language to surplusage.
The provision made a conclusion clear that might otherwise have been fought
over in litigation or administrative rulemaking. Pp. 10-13. |
[15] | 226 F. 3d 1063, reversed and remanded. |
[16] | On Writ Of Certiorari To The United States Court Of Appeals For The
Ninth Circuit Court Below: 226 F. 3d 1063 |
[17] | The opinion of the court was delivered by: Justice Souter |
[18] | 536 U. S. ____ (2002) |
[19] | A regulation of the Equal Employment Opportunity Commission authorizes
refusal to hire an individual because his performance on the job would
endanger his own health, owing to a disability. The question in this case
is whether the Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990, 104 Stat. 328,
42 U. S. C. §12101 et seq. (1994 ed. and Supp. V), permits the regulation.*fn1 We hold that it does. |
[20] | I. |
[21] | Beginning in 1972, respondent Mario Echazabal worked for independent
contractors at an oil refinery owned by petitioner Chevron U. S. A. Inc.
Twice he applied for a job directly with Chevron, which offered to hire
him if he could pass the company's physical examination. See 42 U. S.
C. §12112(d)(3) (1994 ed.). Each time, the exam showed liver abnormality
or damage, the cause eventually being identified as Hepatitis C, which
Chevron's doctors said would be aggravated by continued exposure to toxins
at Chevron's refinery. In each instance, the company withdrew the offer,
and the second time it asked the contractor employing Echazabal either
to reassign him to a job without exposure to harmful chemicals or to remove
him from the refinery altogether. The contractor laid him off in early
1996. |
[22] | Echazabal filed suit, ultimately removed to federal court, claiming,
among other things, that Chevron violated the Americans With Disabilities
Act in refusing to hire him, or even to let him continue working in the
plant, because of a disability, his liver condition.*fn2 Chevron defended under a regulation of the Equal Employment
Opportunity Commission permitting the defense that a worker's disability
on the job would pose a "direct threat" to his health, see 29 CFR §1630.15(b)(2)
(2001). Although two medical witnesses disputed Chevron's judgment that
Echazabal's liver function was impaired and subject to further damage
under the job conditions in the refinery, the District Court granted summary
judgment for Chevron. It held that Echazabal raised no genuine issue of
material fact as to whether the company acted reasonably in relying on
its own doctors' medical advice, regardless of its accuracy. |
[23] | On appeal, the Ninth Circuit asked for briefs on a threshold question
not raised before, whether the EEOC's regulation recognizing a threat-to-self
defense, ibid., exceeded the scope of permissible rulemaking under the
ADA. 226 F. 3d 1063, 1066, n. 3 (2000). The Circuit held that it did and
reversed the summary judgment. The court rested its position on the text
of the ADA itself in explicitly recognizing an employer's right to adopt
an employment qualification barring anyone whose disability would place
others in the workplace at risk, while saying nothing about threats to
the disabled employee himself. The majority opinion reasoned that "by
specifying only threats to `other individuals in the workplace,' the statute
makes it clear that threats to other persons -- including the disabled
individual himself -- are not included within the scope of the [direct
threat] defense," id., at 1066-1067, and it indicated that any such regulation
would unreasonably conflict with congressional policy against paternalism
in the workplace, id., at 1067-1070. The court went on to reject Chevron's
further argument that Echazabal was not " `otherwise qualified' " to perform
the job, holding that the ability to perform a job without risk to one's
health or safety is not an " `essential function' " of the job. Id., at
1070. |
[24] | The decision conflicted with one from the Eleventh Circuit, Moses v.
American Nonwovens, Inc., 97 F. 3d 446, 447 (1996), and raised tension
with the Seventh Circuit case of Koshinski v. Decatur Foundry, Inc., 177
F. 3d 599, 603 (1999). We granted certiorari, 534 U. S. 991 (2001), and
now reverse. |
[25] | II. |
[26] | Section 102 of the Americans with Disabilities Act of 1990, 104 Stat.
328, 42 U. S. C. §12101 et seq., prohibits "discriminat[ion] against a
qualified individual with a disability because of the disability ... in
regard to" a number of actions by an employer, including "hiring." 42
U. S. C. §12112(a). The statutory definition of "discriminat[ion]" covers
a number of things an employer might do to block a disabled person from
advancing in the workplace, such as "using qualification standards ...
that screen out or tend to screen out an individual with a disability."
§12112(b)(6). By that same definition, ibid., as well as by separate provision,
§12113(a), the Act creates an affirmative defense for action under a qualification
standard "shown to be job-related for the position in question and ...
consistent with business necessity." Such a standard may include "a requirement
that an individual shall not pose a direct threat to the health or safety
of other individuals in the workplace," §12113(b), if the individual cannot
perform the job safely with reasonable accommodation, §12113(a). By regulation,
the EEOC carries the defense one step further, in allowing an employer
to screen out a potential worker with a disability not only for risks
that he would pose to others in the workplace but for risks on the job
to his own health or safety as well: "The term `qualification standard'
may include a requirement that an individual shall not pose a direct threat
to the health or safety of the individual or others in the workplace."
29 CFR §1630.15(b)(2) (2001). |
[27] | Chevron relies on the regulation here, since it says a job in the refinery
would pose a "direct threat" to Echazabal's health. In seeking deference
to the agency, it argues that nothing in the statute unambiguously precludes
such a defense, while the regulation was adopted under authority explicitly
delegated by Congress, 42 U. S. C. §12116, and after notice-and-comment
rulemaking. See United States v. Mead Corp., 533 U. S. 218, 227 (2001);
Chevron U. S. A. Inc. v. Natural Resources Defense Council, Inc., 467
U. S. 837, 842-844 (1984). Echazabal, on the contrary, argues that as
a matter of law the statute precludes the regulation, which he claims
would be an unreasonable interpretation even if the agency had leeway
to go beyond the literal text. |
[28] | A. |
[29] | As for the textual bar to any agency action as a matter of law, Echazabal
says that Chevron loses on the threshold question whether the statute
leaves a gap for the EEOC to fill. See id., at 843-844. Echazabal recognizes
the generality of the language providing for a defense when a plaintiff
is screened out by "qualification standards" that are "job-related and
consistent with business necessity" (and reasonable accommodation would
not cure the difficulty posed by employment). 42 U. S. C. §12113(a). Without
more, those provisions would allow an employer to turn away someone whose
work would pose a serious risk to himself. That possibility is said to
be eliminated, however, by the further specification that " `qualification
standards' may include a requirement that an individual shall not pose
a direct threat to the health or safety of other individuals in the workplace."
§12113(b); see also §12111(3) (defining "direct threat" in terms of risk
to others). Echazabal contrasts this provision with an EEOC regulation
under the Rehabilitation Act of 1973, 87 Stat. 357, as amended, 29 U.
S. C. §701 et seq., antedating the ADA, which recognized an employer's
right to consider threats both to other workers and to the threatening
employee himself. Because the ADA defense provision recognizes threats
only if they extend to another, Echazabal reads the statute to imply as
a matter of law that threats to the worker himself cannot count. |
[30] | The argument follows the reliance of the Ninth Circuit majority on the
interpretive canon, expressio unius exclusio alterius, "expressing one
item of [an] associated group or series excludes another left unmentioned."
United States v. Vonn, 535 U. S. ___ , ___ , (2002) (slip op., at 8).
The rule is fine when it applies, but this case joins some others in showing
when it does not. See, e.g., id., at ___ (slip op., at 9); United Dominion
Industries, Inc. v. United States, 532 U. S. 822, 836 (2001); Pauley v.
BethEnergy Mines, Inc., 501 U. S. 680, 703 (1991). |
[31] | The first strike against the expression-exclusion rule here is right
in the text that Echazabal quotes. Congress included the harm-to-others
provision as an example of legitimate qualifications that are "job-related
and consistent with business necessity." These are spacious defensive
categories, which seem to give an agency (or in the absence of agency
action, a court) a good deal of discretion in setting the limits of permissible
qualification standards. That discretion is confirmed, if not magnified,
by the provision that "qualification standards" falling within the limits
of job relation and business necessity "may include" a veto on those who
would directly threaten others in the workplace. Far from supporting Echazabal's
position, the expansive phrasing of "may include" points directly away
from the sort of exclusive specification he claims. United States v. New
York Telephone Co., 434 U. S. 159, 169 (1977); Federal Land Bank of St.
Paul v. Bismarck Lumber Co., 314 U. S. 95, 100 (1941).*fn3 |
[32] | Just as statutory language suggesting exclusiveness is missing, so is
that essential extra-statutory ingredient of an expression-exclusion demonstration,
the series of terms from which an omission bespeaks a negative implication.
The canon depends on identifying a series of two or more terms or things
that should be understood to go hand in hand, which are abridged in circumstances
supporting a sensible inference that the term left out must have been
meant to be excluded. E. Crawford, Construction of Statutes 337 (1940)
(expressio unius " `properly applies only when in the natural association
of ideas in the mind of the reader that which is expressed is so set over
by way of strong contrast to that which is omitted that the contrast enforces
the affirmative inference' " (quoting State ex rel. Curtis v. De Corps,
134 Ohio St. 295, 299, 16 N. E. 2d 459, 462 (1938)); United States v.
Vonn, supra. |
[33] | Strike two in this case is the failure to identify any such established
series, including both threats to others and threats to self, from which
Congress appears to have made a deliberate choice to omit the latter item
as a signal of the affirmative defense's scope. The closest Echazabal
comes is the EEOC's rule interpreting the Rehabilitation Act of 1973,
87 Stat. 357, as amended, 29 U. S. C. §701 et seq., a precursor of the
ADA. That statute excepts from the definition of a protected "qualified
individual with a handicap" anyone who would pose a "direct threat to
the health or safety of other individuals," but, like the later ADA, the
Rehabilitation Act says nothing about threats to self that particular
employment might pose. 42 U. S. C. §12113(b). The EEOC nonetheless extended
the exception to cover threat-to-self employment, 29 CFR §1613.702(f)
(1990), and Echazabal argues that Congress's adoption only of the threat-to-others
exception in the ADA must have been a deliberate omission of the Rehabilitation
Act regulation's tandem term of threat-to-self, with intent to exclude
it. |
[34] | But two reasons stand in the way of treating the omission as an unequivocal
implication of congressional intent. The first is that the EEOC was not
the only agency interpreting the Rehabilitation Act, with the consequence
that its regulation did not establish a clear, standard pairing of threats
to self and others. While the EEOC did amplify upon the text of the Rehabilitation
Act exclusion by recognizing threats to self along with threats to others,
three other agencies adopting regulations under the Rehabilitation Act
did not. See 28 CFR §42.540(l)(1) (1990) (Department of Justice), 29 CFR
§32.3 (1990) (Department of Labor), and 45 CFR §84.3(k)(1) (1990) (Department
of Health and Human Services).*fn4 It would be a stretch, then, to say that there was a
standard usage, with its source in agency practice or elsewhere, that
connected threats to others so closely to threats to self that leaving
out one was like ignoring a twin. |
[35] | Even if we put aside this variety of administrative experience, however,
and look no further than the EEOC's Rehabilitation Act regulation pairing
self and others, the congressional choice to speak only of threats to
others would still be equivocal. Consider what the ADA reference to threats
to others might have meant on somewhat different facts. If the Rehabilitation
Act had spoken only of "threats to health" and the EEOC regulation had
read that to mean threats to self or others, a congressional choice to
be more specific in the ADA by listing threats to others but not threats
to self would have carried a message. The most probable reading would
have been that Congress understood what a failure to specify could lead
to and had made a choice to limit the possibilities. The statutory basis
for any agency rulemaking under the ADA would have been different from
its basis under the Rehabilitation Act and would have indicated a difference
in the agency's rulemaking discretion. But these are not the circumstances
here. Instead of making the ADA different from the Rehabilitation Act
on the point at issue, Congress used identical language, knowing full
well what the EEOC had made of that language under the earlier statute.
Did Congress mean to imply that the agency had been wrong in reading the
earlier language to allow it to recognize threats to self, or did Congress
just assume that the agency was free to do under the ADA what it had already
done under the earlier Act's identical language? There is no way to tell.
Omitting the EEOC's reference to self-harm while using the very language
that the EEOC had read as consistent with recognizing self-harm is equivocal
at best. No negative inference is possible. |
[36] | There is even a third strike against applying the expression-exclusion
rule here. It is simply that there is no apparent stopping point to the
argument that by specifying a threat-to-others defense Congress intended
a negative implication about those whose safety could be considered. When
Congress specified threats to others in the workplace, for example, could
it possibly have meant that an employer could not defend a refusal to
hire when a worker's disability would threaten others outside the workplace?
If Typhoid Mary had come under the ADA, would a meat packer have been
defenseless if Mary had sued after being turned away? See 42 U. S. C.
§12113(d). Expressio unius just fails to work here. |
[37] | B. |
[38] | Since Congress has not spoken exhaustively on threats to a worker's
own health, the agency regulation can claim adherence under the rule in
Chevron, 467 U. S., at 843, so long as it makes sense of the statutory
defense for qualification standards that are "job-related and consistent
with business necessity." 42 U. S. C. §12113(a). Chevron's reasons for
calling the regulation reasonable are unsurprising: moral concerns aside,
it wishes to avoid time lost to sickness, excessive turnover from medical
retirement or death, litigation under state tort law, and the risk of
violating the national Occupational Safety and Health Act of 1970, 84
Stat. 1590, as amended, 29 U. S. C. §651 et seq. Although Echazabal claims
that none of these reasons is legitimate, focusing on the concern with
OSHA will be enough to show that the regulation is entitled to survive. |
[39] | Echazabal points out that there is no known instance of OSHA enforcement,
or even threatened enforcement, against an employer who relied on the
ADA to hire a worker willing to accept a risk to himself from his disability
on the job. In Echazabal's mind, this shows that invoking OSHA policy
and possible OSHA liability is just a red herring to excuse covert discrimination.
But there is another side to this. The text of OSHA itself says its point
is "to assure so far as possible every working man and woman in the Nation
safe and healthful working conditions," §651(b), and Congress specifically
obligated an employer to "furnish to each of his employees employment
and a place of employment which are free from recognized hazards that
are causing or are likely to cause death or serious physical harm to his
employees," §654(a)(1). Although there may be an open question whether
an employer would actually be liable under OSHA for hiring an individual
who knowingly consented to the particular dangers the job would pose to
him, see Brief for United States et al. as Amici Curiae 19, n. 7, there
is no denying that the employer would be asking for trouble: his decision
to hire would put Congress's policy in the ADA, a disabled individual's
right to operate on equal terms within the workplace, at loggerheads with
the competing policy of OSHA, to ensure the safety of "each" and "every"
worker. Courts would, of course, resolve the tension if there were no
agency action, but the EEOC's resolution exemplifies the substantive choices
that agencies are expected to make when Congress leaves the intersection
of competing objectives both imprecisely marked but subject to the administrative
leeway found in 42 U. S. C. §12113(a). |
[40] | Nor can the EEOC's resolution be fairly called unreasonable as allowing
the kind of workplace paternalism the ADA was meant to outlaw. It is true
that Congress had paternalism in its sights when it passed the ADA, see
§12101(a)(5) (recognizing "overprotective rules and policies" as a form
of discrimination). But the EEOC has taken this to mean that Congress
was not aiming at an employer's refusal to place disabled workers at a
specifically demonstrated risk, but was trying to get at refusals to give
an even break to classes of disabled people, while claiming to act for
their own good in reliance on untested and pretextual stereotypes.*fn5 Its regulation disallows just this sort of sham protection,
through demands for a particularized enquiry into the harms the employee
would probably face. The direct threat defense must be "based on a reasonable
medical judgment that relies on the most current medical knowledge and/or
the best available objective evidence," and upon an expressly "individualized
assessment of the individual's present ability to safely perform the essential
functions of the job," reached after considering, among other things,
the imminence of the risk and the severity of the harm portended. 29 CFR
§1630.2(r) (2001). The EEOC was certainly acting within the reasonable
zone when it saw a difference between rejecting workplace paternalism
and ignoring specific and documented risks to the employee himself, even
if the employee would take his chances for the sake of getting a job.*fn6 |
[41] | Finally, our conclusions that some regulation is permissible and this
one is reasonable are not open to Echazabal's objection that they reduce
the direct threat provision to "surplusage," see Babbitt v. Sweet Home
Chapter, Communities for Great Ore., 515 U. S. 687, 698 (1995). The mere
fact that a threat-to-self defense reasonably falls within the general
"job related" and "business necessity" standard does not mean that Congress
accomplished nothing with its explicit provision for a defense based on
threats to others. The provision made a conclusion clear that might otherwise
have been fought over in litigation or administrative rulemaking. It did
not lack a job to do merely because the EEOC might have adopted the same
rule later in applying the general defense provisions, nor was its job
any less responsible simply because the agency was left with the option
to go a step further. A provision can be useful even without congressional
attention being indispensable. |
[42] | Accordingly, we reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals and remand
the case for proceedings consistent with this opinion. |
[43] | It is so ordered. |
|
|
Opinion Footnotes | |
|
|
[44] | *fn1 We do not consider the further issue passed upon by
the Ninth Circuit, which held that the respondent is a " `qualified individual'
" who "can perform the essential functions of the employment position,"
42 U. S. C. §12111(8) (1994 ed.). 226 F. 3d 1063, 1072 (2000). That issue
will only resurface if the Circuit concludes that the decision of respondent's
employer to exclude him was not based on the sort of individualized medical
enquiry required by the regulation, an issue on which the District Court
granted summary judgment for petitioner and which we leave to the Ninth
Circuit for initial appellate consideration if warranted. |
[45] | *fn2 Chevron did not dispute for purposes of its summary-judgment
motion that Echazabal is "disabled" under the ADA, and Echazabal did not
argue that Chevron could have made a " `reasonable accommodation.' " App.
184, n. 6. |
[46] | *fn3 In saying that the expansive textual phrases point in
the direction of agency leeway we do not mean that the defense provisions
place no limit on agency rulemaking. Without deciding whether all safety-related
qualification standards must satisfy the ADA's direct-threat standard,
see Albertson's, Inc. v. Kirkingburg, 527 U. S. 555, 569-570, n. 15 (1999),
we assume that some such regulations are implicitly precluded by the Act's
specification of a direct-threat defense, such as those allowing "indirect"
threats of "insignificant" harm. This is so because the definitional and
defense provisions describing the defense in terms of "direct" threats
of "significant" harm, 42 U. S. C. §§12113(b), 12111(3), are obviously
intended to forbid qualifications that screen out by reference to general
categories pretextually applied. See infra, at 11-12, and n. 5. Recognizing
the "indirect" and "insignificant" would simply reopen the door to pretext
by way of defense. |
[47] | *fn4 In fact, we have said that the regulations issued by
the Department of Health and Human Services, which had previously been
the regulations of the Department of Health, Education, and Welfare, are
of "particular significance" in interpreting the Rehabilitation Act because
"HEW was the agency responsible for coordinating the implementation and
enforcement of §504 of the Rehabilitation Act, 29 U. S. C. §794," prohibiting
discrimination against individuals with disabilities by recipients of
federal funds. Toyota Motor Mfg., Ky., Inc. v. Williams, 534 U. S. 184,
195 (2002). Unfortunately for Echazabal's argument, the congruence of
the ADA with the HEW regulations does not produce an unequivocal statement
of congressional intent. |
[48] | *fn5 Echazabal's contention that the Act's legislative history
is to the contrary is unpersuasive. Although some of the comments within
the legislative history decry paternalism in general terms, see, e.g.,
H. R. Rep. No. 101-485, pt. 2, p. 72 (1990) ("It is critical that paternalistic
concerns for the disabled person's own safety not be used to disqualify
an otherwise qualified applicant"); ADA Conf. Rep., 136 Cong. Rec. 17377
(1990) (statement of Sen. Kennedy) ("[A]n employer could not use as an
excuse for not hiring a person with HIV disease the claim that the employer
was simply `protecting the individual' from opportunistic diseases to
which the individual might be exposed"), those comments that elaborate
actually express the more pointed concern that such justifications are
usually pretextual, rooted in generalities and misperceptions about disabilities.
See, e.g., H. R. Rep. No. 101-485, at 74 ("Generalized fear about risks
from the employment environment, such as exacerbation of the disability
caused by stress, cannot be used by an employer to disqualify a person
with a disability"); S. Rep. No. 101-116, p. 28 (1989) ("It would also
be a violation to deny employment to an applicant based on generalized
fears about the safety of the applicant ... . By definition, such fears
are based on averages and group-based predictions. This legislation requires
individualized assessments"). Similarly, Echazabal points to several of
our decisions expressing concern under Title VII, which like the ADA allows
employers to defend otherwise discriminatory practices that are "consistent
with business necessity," 42 U. S. C. §2000e-2(k), with employers adopting
rules that exclude women from jobs that are seen as too risky. See, e.g.,
Dothard v. Rawlinson, 433 U. S. 321, 335 (1977); Automobile Workers v.
Johnson Controls, Inc., 499 U. S. 187, 202 (1991). Those cases, however,
are beside the point, as they, like Title VII generally, were concerned
with paternalistic judgments based on the broad category of gender, while
the EEOC has required that judgments based on the direct threat provision
be made on the basis of individualized risk assessments. |
[49] | *fn6 Respect for this distinction does not entail the requirement,
as Echazabal claims, that qualification standards be "neutral," stating
what the job requires, as distinct from a worker's disqualifying characteristics.
Brief for Respondent 26. It is just as much business necessity for skyscraper
contractors to have steelworkers without vertigo as to have well-balanced
ones. See 226 F. 3d, at 1074 (Trott, J., dissenting). Reasonableness does
not turn on formalism. We have no occasion, however, to try to describe
how acutely an employee must exhibit a disqualifying condition before
an employer may exclude him from the class of the generally qualified.
See Brief for Respondent 31. This is a job for the trial courts in the
first instance. |
The Climate Change and Public Health Law Site
The Best on the WWW Since 1995!
Copyright as to non-public domain materials
See DR-KATE.COM for home hurricane and disaster preparation
See WWW.EPR-ART.COM for photography of southern Louisiana and Hurricane Katrina
Professor Edward P. Richards, III, JD, MPH - Webmaster
Provide Website Feedback - https://www.lsu.edu/feedback
Privacy Statement - https://www.lsu.edu/privacy
Accessibility Statement - https://www.lsu.edu/accessibility